summaryrefslogtreecommitdiff
path: root/doc/faq/FAQ.tex
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
Diffstat (limited to 'doc/faq/FAQ.tex')
-rw-r--r--doc/faq/FAQ.tex2481
1 files changed, 2481 insertions, 0 deletions
diff --git a/doc/faq/FAQ.tex b/doc/faq/FAQ.tex
new file mode 100644
index 00000000..2b5d898f
--- /dev/null
+++ b/doc/faq/FAQ.tex
@@ -0,0 +1,2481 @@
+\RequirePackage{ifpdf}
+\ifpdf % si on est en pdflatex
+\documentclass[a4paper,pdftex]{article}
+\else
+\documentclass[a4paper]{article}
+\fi
+\pagestyle{plain}
+
+% yay les symboles
+\usepackage{stmaryrd}
+\usepackage{amssymb}
+\usepackage{url}
+%\usepackage{multicol}
+\usepackage{hevea}
+\usepackage{fullpage}
+\usepackage[latin1]{inputenc}
+\usepackage[english]{babel}
+
+\ifpdf % si on est en pdflatex
+ \usepackage[pdftex]{graphicx}
+\else
+ \usepackage[dvips]{graphicx}
+\fi
+
+%\input{../macros.tex}
+
+% Making hevea happy
+%HEVEA \renewcommand{\textbar}{|}
+%HEVEA \renewcommand{\textunderscore}{\_}
+
+\def\Question#1{\stepcounter{question}\subsubsection{#1}}
+
+% version et date
+\def\faqversion{0.1}
+
+% les macros d'amour
+\def\Coq{\textsc{Coq}}
+\def\Why{\textsc{Why}}
+\def\Caduceus{\textsc{Caduceus}}
+\def\Krakatoa{\textsc{Krakatoa}}
+\def\Ltac{\textsc{Ltac}}
+\def\CoqIde{\textsc{CoqIde}}
+
+\newcommand{\coqtt}[1]{{\tt #1}}
+\newcommand{\coqimp}{{\mbox{\tt ->}}}
+\newcommand{\coqequiv}{{\mbox{\tt <->}}}
+
+
+% macro pour les tactics
+\def\split{{\tt split}}
+\def\assumption{{\tt assumption}}
+\def\auto{{\tt auto}}
+\def\trivial{{\tt trivial}}
+\def\tauto{{\tt tauto}}
+\def\left{{\tt left}}
+\def\right{{\tt right}}
+\def\decompose{{\tt decompose}}
+\def\intro{{\tt intro}}
+\def\intros{{\tt intros}}
+\def\field{{\tt field}}
+\def\ring{{\tt ring}}
+\def\apply{{\tt apply}}
+\def\exact{{\tt exact}}
+\def\cut{{\tt cut}}
+\def\assert{{\tt assert}}
+\def\solve{{\tt solve}}
+\def\idtac{{\tt idtac}}
+\def\fail{{\tt fail}}
+\def\existstac{{\tt exists}}
+\def\firstorder{{\tt firstorder}}
+\def\congruence{{\tt congruence}}
+\def\gb{{\tt gb}}
+\def\generalize{{\tt generalize}}
+\def\abstracttac{{\tt abstract}}
+\def\eapply{{\tt eapply}}
+\def\unfold{{\tt unfold}}
+\def\rewrite{{\tt rewrite}}
+\def\replace{{\tt replace}}
+\def\simpl{{\tt simpl}}
+\def\elim{{\tt elim}}
+\def\set{{\tt set}}
+\def\pose{{\tt pose}}
+\def\case{{\tt case}}
+\def\destruct{{\tt destruct}}
+\def\reflexivity{{\tt reflexivity}}
+\def\transitivity{{\tt transitivity}}
+\def\symmetry{{\tt symmetry}}
+\def\Focus{{\tt Focus}}
+\def\discriminate{{\tt discriminate}}
+\def\contradiction{{\tt contradiction}}
+\def\intuition{{\tt intuition}}
+\def\try{{\tt try}}
+\def\repeat{{\tt repeat}}
+\def\eauto{{\tt eauto}}
+\def\subst{{\tt subst}}
+\def\symmetryin{{\tt symmetryin}}
+\def\instantiate{{\tt instantiate}}
+\def\inversion{{\tt inversion}}
+\def\Defined{{\tt Defined}}
+\def\Qed{{\tt Qed}}
+\def\pattern{{\tt pattern}}
+\def\Type{{\tt Type}}
+\def\Prop{{\tt Prop}}
+\def\Set{{\tt Set}}
+
+
+\newcommand\vfile[2]{\ahref{#1}{\tt {#2}.v}}
+\urldef{\InitWf}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Init.Wf.html}
+\urldef{\LogicBerardi}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Berardi.html}
+\urldef{\LogicClassical}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Classical.html}
+\urldef{\LogicClassicalFacts}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.ClassicalFacts.html}
+\urldef{\LogicClassicalDescription}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.ClassicalDescription.html}
+\urldef{\LogicProofIrrelevance}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.ProofIrrelevance.html}
+\urldef{\LogicEqdep}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Eqdep.html}
+\urldef{\LogicEqdepDec}{\url}
+ {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Eqdep_dec.html}
+
+
+
+
+\begin{document}
+\bibliographystyle{plain}
+\newcounter{question}
+\renewcommand{\thesubsubsection}{\arabic{question}}
+
+%%%%%%% Coq pour les nuls %%%%%%%
+
+\title{Coq Version 8.0 for the Clueless\\
+ \large(\protect\ref{lastquestion}
+ \ Hints)
+}
+\author{Pierre Castéran \and Hugo Herbelin \and Florent Kirchner \and Benjamin Monate \and Julien Narboux}
+\maketitle
+
+%%%%%%%
+
+\begin{abstract}
+This note intends to provide an easy way to get acquainted with the
+{\Coq} theorem prover. It tries to formulate appropriate answers
+to some of the questions any newcomers will face, and to give
+pointers to other references when possible.
+\end{abstract}
+
+%%%%%%%
+
+%\begin{multicols}{2}
+\tableofcontents
+%\end{multicols}
+
+%%%%%%%
+
+\newpage
+
+\section{Introduction}
+This FAQ is the sum of the questions that came to mind as we developed
+proofs in \Coq. Since we are singularly short-minded, we wrote the
+answers we found on bits of papers to have them at hand whenever the
+situation occurs again. This is pretty much the result of that: a
+collection of tips one can refer to when proofs become intricate. Yes,
+this means we won't take the blame for the shortcomings of this
+FAQ. But if you want to contribute and send in your own question and
+answers, feel free to write to us\ldots
+
+%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
+
+\section{Presentation}
+
+\Question{What is {\Coq}?}\label{whatiscoq}
+The {\Coq} tool is a formal proof management system: a proof done with {\Coq} is mechanically checked by the machine.
+In particular, {\Coq} allows:
+\begin{itemize}
+ \item the definition of mathematical objects and programming objects,
+ \item to state mathematical theorems and software specifications,
+ \item to interactively develop formal proofs of these theorems,
+ \item to check these proofs by a small certification ``kernel''.
+\end{itemize}
+{\Coq} is based on a logical framework called ``Calculus of Inductive
+Constructions'' extended by a modular development system for theories.
+
+\Question{Did you really need to name it like that?}
+Some French computer scientists have a tradition of naming their
+software as animal species: Caml, Elan, Foc or Phox are examples
+of this tacit convention. In French, ``coq'' means rooster, and it
+sounds like the initials of the Calculus of Constructions CoC on which
+it is based.
+
+\Question{Is {\Coq} a theorem prover?}
+
+{\Coq} comes with decision and semi-decision procedures (
+propositional calculus, Presburger's arithmetic, ring and field
+simplification, resolution, ...) but the main style for proving
+theorems is interactively by using LCF-style tactics.
+
+
+\Question{What are the other theorem provers?}
+Many other theorem provers are available for use nowadays.
+Isabelle, HOL, HOL Light, Lego, Nuprl, PVS are examples of provers that are fairly similar
+to {\Coq} by the way they interact with the user. Other relatives of
+{\Coq} are ACL2, Agda/Alfa, Twelf, Kiv, Mizar, NqThm,
+\begin{htmlonly}%
+Omega\ldots
+\end{htmlonly}
+\begin{latexonly}%
+{$\Omega$}mega\ldots
+\end{latexonly}
+
+\Question{What do I have to trust when I see a proof checked by Coq?}
+
+You have to trust:
+
+\begin{description}
+\item[The theory behind Coq] The theory of {\Coq} version 8.0 is
+generally admitted to be consistent wrt Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory +
+inaccessible cardinals. Proofs of consistency of subsystems of the
+theory of Coq can be found in the literature.
+\item[The Coq kernel implementation] You have to trust that the
+implementation of the {\Coq} kernel mirrors the theory behind {\Coq}. The
+kernel is intentionally small to limit the risk of conceptual or
+accidental implementation bugs.
+\item[The Objective Caml compiler] The {\Coq} kernel is written using the
+Objective Caml language but it uses only the most standard features
+(no object, no label ...), so that it is highly unprobable that an
+Objective Caml bug breaks the consistency of {\Coq} without breaking all
+other kinds of features of {\Coq} or of other software compiled with
+Objective Caml.
+\item[Your hardware] In theory, if your hardware does not work
+properly, it can accidentally be the case that False becomes
+provable. But it is more likely the case that the whole {\Coq} system
+will be unusable. You can check your proof using different computers
+if you feel the need to.
+\item[Your axioms] Your axioms must be consistent with the theory
+behind {\Coq}.
+\end{description}
+
+
+\Question{Where can I find information about the theory behind {\Coq}?}
+\begin{description}
+\item[The Calculus of Inductive Constructions] The
+\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/Reference-Manual006.html}{corresponding}
+chapter and the chapter on
+\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/Reference-Manual007.html}{modules} in
+the {\Coq} Reference Manual.
+\item[Type theory] A book~\cite{ProofsTypes} or some lecture
+notes~\cite{Types:Dowek}.
+\item[Inductive types]
+Christine Paulin-Mohring's habilitation thesis~\cite{Pau96b}.
+\item[Co-Inductive types]
+Eduardo Giménez' thesis~\cite{EGThese}.
+\item[Miscellaneous] A
+\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/biblio.html}{bibliography} about Coq
+\end{description}
+
+
+\Question{How can I use {\Coq} to prove programs?}
+
+You can either extract a program from a proof by using the extraction
+mechanism or use dedicated tools, such as
+\ahref{http://why.lri.fr}{\Why},
+\ahref{http://krakatoa.lri.fr}{\Krakatoa},
+\ahref{http://why.lri.fr/caduceus/index.en.html}{\Caduceus}, to prove
+annotated programs written in other languages.
+
+%\Question{How many {\Coq} users are there?}
+%
+%An estimation is about 100 regular users.
+
+\Question{How old is {\Coq}?}
+
+The first implementation is from 1985 (it was named {\sf CoC} which is
+the acronym of the name of the logic it implemented: the Calculus of
+Constructions). The first official release of {\Coq} (version 4.10)
+was distributed in 1989.
+
+\Question{What are the \Coq-related tools?}
+
+There are graphical user interfaces:
+\begin{description}
+\item[Coqide] A GTK based GUI for \Coq.
+\item[Pcoq] A GUI for {\Coq} with proof by pointing and pretty printing.
+\item[coqwc] A tool similar to {\tt wc} to count lines in {\Coq} files.
+\item[Proof General] A emacs mode for {\Coq} and many other proof assistants.
+\end{description}
+
+There are documentation and browsing tools:
+
+\begin{description}
+\item[Helm/Mowgli] A rendering, searching and publishing tool.
+\item[coq-tex] A tool to insert {\Coq} examples within .tex files.
+\item[coqdoc] A documentation tool for \Coq.
+\end{description}
+
+There are front-ends for specific languages:
+
+\begin{description}
+\item[Why] A back-end generator of verification conditions.
+\item[Krakatoa] A Java code certification tool that uses both {\Coq} and {\Why} to verify the soundness of implementations with regards to the specifications.
+\item[Caduceus] A C code certification tool that uses both {\Coq} and \Why.
+\item[Zenon] A first-order theorem prover.
+\item[Focal] The \ahref{http://focal.inria.fr}{Focal} project aims at building an environment to develop certified computer algebra libraries.
+\end{description}
+
+\Question{What are the high-level tactics of \Coq}
+
+\begin{itemize}
+\item Decision of quantifier-free Presburger's Arithmetic
+\item Simplification of expressions on rings and fields
+\item Decision of closed systems of equations
+\item Semi-decision of first-order logic
+\item Prolog-style proof search, possibly involving equalities
+\end{itemize}
+
+\Question{What are the main libraries available for \Coq}
+
+\begin{itemize}
+\item Basic Peano's arithmetic, binary integer numbers, rational numbers,
+\item Real analysis,
+\item Libraries for lists, boolean, maps, floating-point numbers,
+\item Libraries for relations, sets and constructive algebra,
+\item Geometry
+\end{itemize}
+
+
+\Question{What are the mathematical applications for {\Coq}?}
+
+{\Coq} is used for formalizing mathematical theories, for teaching,
+and for proving properties of algorithms or programs libraries.
+
+The largest mathematical formalization has been done at the University
+of Nijmegen (see the
+\ahref{http://vacuumcleaner.cs.kun.nl/c-corn}{Constructive Coq
+Repository at Nijmegen}).
+
+A symbolic step has also been obtained by formalizing in full a proof
+of the Four Color Theorem.
+
+\Question{What are the industrial applications for {\Coq}?}
+
+{\Coq} is used e.g. to prove properties of the JavaCard system
+(especially by Schlumberger and Trusted Logic). It has
+also been used to formalize the semantics of the Lucid-Synchrone
+data-flow synchronous calculus used by Esterel-Technologies.
+
+\iffalse
+todo christine compilo lustre?
+\fi
+
+%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
+
+\section{Documentation}
+
+\Question{Where can I find documentation about {\Coq}?}
+All the documentation about \Coq, from the reference manual~\cite{Coq:manual} to
+friendly tutorials~\cite{Coq:Tutorial} and documentation of the standard library, is available
+\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc-eng.html}{online}.
+All these documents are viewable either in browsable HTML, or as
+downloadable postscripts.
+
+\Question{Where can I find this FAQ on the web?}
+
+This FAQ is available online at \ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/faq.html}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/faq.html}}.
+
+\Question{How can I submit suggestions / improvements / additions for this FAQ?}
+
+This FAQ is unfinished (in the sense that there are some obvious
+sections that are missing). Please send contributions to \texttt{Florent.Kirchner at lix.polytechnique.fr} and \texttt{Julien.Narboux at inria.fr}.
+
+\Question{Is there any mailing list about {\Coq}?}
+The main {\Coq} mailing list is \url{coq-club@pauillac.inria.fr}, which
+broadcasts questions and suggestions about the implementation, the
+logical formalism or proof developments. See
+\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/mailman/listinfo/coq-club}{\url{http://pauillac.inria.fr/mailman/listinfo/coq-club}} for
+subscription. For bugs reports see question \ref{coqbug}.
+
+\Question{Where can I find an archive of the list?}
+The archives of the {\Coq} mailing list are available at
+\ahref{http://pauillac.inria.fr/pipermail/coq-club}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr/pipermail/coq-club}}.
+
+
+\Question{How can I be kept informed of new releases of {\Coq}?}
+
+New versions of {\Coq} are announced on the coq-club mailing list. If you only want to receive information about new releases, you can subscribe to {\Coq} on \ahref{http://freshmeat.net/projects/coq/}{\url{http://freshmeat.net/projects/coq/}}.
+
+
+\Question{Is there any book about {\Coq}?}
+
+The first book on \Coq, Yves Bertot and Pierre Castéran's Coq'Art has been published by Springer-Verlag in 2004:
+\begin{quote}
+``This book provides a pragmatic introduction to the development of
+proofs and certified programs using \Coq. With its large collection of
+examples and exercises it is an invaluable tool for researchers,
+students, and engineers interested in formal methods and the
+development of zero-default software.''
+\end{quote}
+
+\Question{Where can I find some {\Coq} examples?}
+
+There are examples in the manual~\cite{Coq:manual} and in the
+Coq'Art~\cite{Coq:coqart} exercises \ahref{\url{http://www.labri.fr/Perso/~casteran/CoqArt/index.html}}{\url{http://www.labri.fr/Perso/~casteran/CoqArt/index.html}}.
+You can also find large developments using
+{\Coq} in the {\Coq} user contributions:
+\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/contrib-eng.html}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr/contrib-eng.html}}.
+
+\Question{How can I report a bug?}\label{coqbug}
+
+You can use the web interface accessible at \ahref{http://coq.inria.fr}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr}}, link ``contacts''.
+
+
+%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
+
+\section{Installation}
+
+\Question{What is the license of {\Coq}?}
+{\Coq} is distributed under the GNU Lesser General License
+(LGPL).
+
+\Question{Where can I find the sources of {\Coq}?}
+The sources of {\Coq} can be found online in the tar.gz'ed packages
+(\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr}}, link
+``download''). Development sources can be accessed at
+\ahref{http://coq.gforge.inria.fr/}{\url{http://coq.gforge.inria.fr/}}
+
+\Question{On which platform is {\Coq} available?}
+Compiled binaries are available for Linux, MacOS X, and Windows. The
+sources can be easily compiled on all platforms supporting Objective
+Caml.
+
+%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
+
+\section{The logic of {\Coq}}
+
+\subsection{General}
+
+\Question{What is the logic of \Coq?}
+
+{\Coq} is based on an axiom-free type theory called
+the Calculus of Inductive Constructions (see Coquand \cite{CoHu86},
+Luo~\cite{Luo90}
+and Coquand--Paulin-Mohring \cite{CoPa89}). It includes higher-order
+functions and predicates, inductive and co-inductive datatypes and
+predicates, and a stratified hierarchy of sets.
+
+\Question{Is \Coq's logic intuitionistic or classical?}
+
+{\Coq}'s logic is modular. The core logic is intuitionistic
+(i.e. excluded-middle $A\vee\neg A$ is not granted by default). It can
+be extended to classical logic on demand by requiring an
+optional module stating $A\vee\neg A$.
+
+\Question{Can I define non-terminating programs in \Coq?}
+
+All programs in {\Coq} are terminating. Especially, loops
+must come with an evidence of their termination.
+
+Non-terminating programs can be simulated by passing around a
+bound on how long the program is allowed to run before dying.
+
+\Question{How is equational reasoning working in {\Coq}?}
+
+ {\Coq} comes with an internal notion of computation called
+{\em conversion} (e.g. $(x+1)+y$ is internally equivalent to
+$(x+y)+1$; similarly applying argument $a$ to a function mapping $x$
+to some expression $t$ converts to the expression $t$ where $x$ is
+replaced by $a$). This notion of conversion (which is decidable
+because {\Coq} programs are terminating) covers a certain part of
+equational reasoning but is limited to sequential evaluation of
+expressions of (not necessarily closed) programs. Besides conversion,
+equations have to be treated by hand or using specialised tactics.
+
+\subsection{Axioms}
+
+\Question{What axioms can be safely added to {\Coq}?}
+
+There are a few typical useful axioms that are independent from the
+Calculus of Inductive Constructions and that can be safely added to
+{\Coq}. These axioms are stated in the directory {\tt Logic} of the
+standard library of {\Coq}. The most interesting ones are
+
+\begin{itemize}
+\item Excluded-middle: $\forall A:Prop, A \vee \neg A$
+\item Proof-irrelevance: $\forall A:Prop \forall p_1 p_2:A, p_1=p_2$
+\item Unicity of equality proofs (or equivalently Streicher's axiom $K$):
+$\forall A \forall x y:A \forall p_1 p_2:x=y, p_1=p_2$
+\item The axiom of unique choice: $\forall x \exists! y R(x,y) \rightarrow \exists f \forall x R(x,f(x))$
+\item The functional axiom of choice: $\forall x \exists y R(x,y) \rightarrow \exists f \forall x R(x,f(x))$
+\item Extensionality of predicates: $\forall P Q:A\rightarrow Prop, (\forall x, P(x) \leftrightarrow Q(x)) \rightarrow P=Q$
+\item Extensionality of functions: $\forall f g:A\rightarrow B, (\forall x, f(x)=g(x)) \rightarrow f=g$
+\end{itemize}
+
+Here is a summary of the relative strength of these axioms, most
+proofs can be found in directory {\tt Logic} of the standard library.
+The justification of their validity relies on the interpretability in
+set theory.
+
+%HEVEA\imgsrc{axioms.png}
+%BEGIN LATEX
+\ifpdf % si on est en pdflatex
+\includegraphics[width=1.0\textwidth]{axioms.png}
+\else
+\includegraphics[width=1.0\textwidth]{axioms.eps}
+\fi
+%END LATEX
+
+\Question{What standard axioms are inconsistent with {\Coq}?}
+
+The axiom of unique choice together with classical logic
+(e.g. excluded-middle) are inconsistent in the variant of the Calculus
+of Inductive Constructions where {\Set} is impredicative.
+
+As a consequence, the functional form of the axiom of choice and
+excluded-middle, or any form of the axiom of choice together with
+predicate extensionality are inconsistent in the {\Set}-impredicative
+version of the Calculus of Inductive Constructions.
+
+The main purpose of the \Set-predicative restriction of the Calculus
+of Inductive Constructions is precisely to accommodate these axioms
+which are quite standard in mathematical usage.
+
+The $\Set$-predicative system is commonly considered consistent by
+interpreting it in a standard set-theoretic boolean model, even with
+classical logic, axiom of choice and predicate extensionality added.
+
+\Question{What is Streicher's axiom $K$}
+\label{Streicher}
+
+Streicher's axiom $K$~\cite{HofStr98} is an axiom that asserts
+dependent elimination of reflexive equality proofs.
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Axiom Streicher_K :
+ forall (A:Type) (x:A) (P: x=x -> Prop),
+ P (refl_equal x) -> forall p: x=x, P p.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+In the general case, axiom $K$ is an independent statement of the
+Calculus of Inductive Constructions. However, it is true on decidable
+domains (see file \vfile{\LogicEqdepDec}{Eqdep\_dec}). It is also
+trivially a consequence of proof-irrelevance (see
+\ref{proof-irrelevance}) hence of classical logic.
+
+Axiom $K$ is equivalent to {\em Uniqueness of Identity Proofs} \cite{HofStr98}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Axiom UIP : forall (A:Set) (x y:A) (p1 p2: x=y), p1 = p2.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+Axiom $K$ is also equivalent to {\em Uniqueness of Reflexive Identity Proofs} \cite{HofStr98}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Axiom UIP_refl : forall (A:Set) (x:A) (p: x=x), p = refl_equal x.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+Axiom $K$ is also equivalent to
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Axiom
+ eq_rec_eq :
+ forall (A:Set) (x:A) (P: A->Set) (p:P x) (h: x=x),
+ p = eq_rect x P p x h.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+It is also equivalent to the injectivity of dependent equality (dependent equality is itself equivalent to equality of dependent pairs).
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Inductive eq_dep (U:Set) (P:U -> Set) (p:U) (x:P p) :
+forall q:U, P q -> Prop :=
+ eq_dep_intro : eq_dep U P p x p x.
+Axiom
+ eq_dep_eq :
+ forall (U:Set) (u:U) (P:U -> Set) (p1 p2:P u),
+ eq_dep U P u p1 u p2 -> p1 = p2.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\Question{What is proof-irrelevance}
+\label{proof-irrelevance}
+
+A specificity of the Calculus of Inductive Constructions is to permit
+statements about proofs. This leads to the question of comparing two
+proofs of the same proposition. Identifying all proofs of the same
+proposition is called {\em proof-irrelevance}:
+$$
+\forall A:\Prop, \forall p q:A, p=q
+$$
+
+Proof-irrelevance (in {\Prop}) can be assumed without contradiction in
+{\Coq}. It expresses that only provability matters, whatever the exact
+form of the proof is. This is in harmony with the common purely
+logical interpretation of {\Prop}. Contrastingly, proof-irrelevance is
+inconsistent in {\Set} since there are types in {\Set}, such as the
+type of booleans, that are provably more than 2 elements.
+
+Proof-irrelevance (in {\Prop}) is a consequence of classical logic
+(see proofs in file \vfile{\LogicClassical}{Classical} and
+\vfile{\LogicBerardi}{Berardi}). Proof-irrelevance is also a
+consequence of propositional extensionality (i.e. \coqtt{(A {\coqequiv} B)
+{\coqimp} A=B}, see the proof in file
+\vfile{\LogicClassicalFacts}{ClassicalFacts}).
+
+Proof-irrelevance directly implies Streicher's axiom $K$.
+
+\Question{What about functional extensionality?}
+
+Extensionality of functions is admittedly consistent with the
+Set-predicative Calculus of Inductive Constructions.
+
+%\begin{coq_example*}
+% Axiom extensionality : (A,B:Set)(f,g:(A->B))(x:A)(f x)=(g x)->f=g.
+%\end{coq_example*}
+
+Let {\tt A}, {\tt B} be types. To deal with extensionality on
+\verb=A->B= without relying on a general extensionality axiom,
+a possible approach is to define one's own extensional equality on
+\verb=A->B=.
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Variables A B : Set.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Definition ext_eq (f g: A->B) := forall x:A, f x = g x.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+and to reason on \verb=A->B= as a setoid (see the Chapter on
+Setoids in the Reference Manual).
+
+\Question{Is {\Prop} impredicative?}
+
+Yes, the sort {\Prop} of propositions is {\em
+impredicative}. Otherwise said, a statement of the form $\forall
+A:Prop, P(A)$ can be instantiated by itself: if $\forall A:\Prop, P(A)$
+is provable, then $P(\forall A:\Prop, P(A))$ is.
+
+\Question{Is {\Set} impredicative?}
+
+No, the sort {\Set} lying at the bottom of the hierarchy of
+computational types is {\em predicative} in the basic {\Coq} system.
+This means that a family of types in {\Set}, e.g. $\forall A:\Set, A
+\rightarrow A$, is not a type in {\Set} and it cannot be applied on
+itself.
+
+However, the sort {\Set} was impredicative in the original versions of
+{\Coq}. For backward compatibility, or for experiments by
+knowledgeable users, the logic of {\Coq} can be set impredicative for
+{\Set} by calling {\Coq} with the option {\tt -impredicative-set}.
+
+{\Set} has been made predicative from version 8.0 of {\Coq}. The main
+reason is to interact smoothly with a classical mathematical world
+where both excluded-middle and the axiom of description are valid (see
+file \vfile{\LogicClassicalDescription}{ClassicalDescription} for a
+proof that excluded-middle and description implies the double negation
+of excluded-middle in {\Set} and file {\tt Hurkens\_Set.v} from the
+user contribution {\tt Rocq/PARADOXES} for a proof that
+impredicativity of {\Set} implies the simple negation of
+excluded-middle in {\Set}).
+
+\Question{Is {\Type} impredicative?}
+
+No, {\Type} is stratified. This is hidden for the
+user, but {\Coq} internally maintains a set of constraints ensuring
+stratification.
+
+If {\Type} were impredicative then it would be possible to encode
+Girard's systems $U-$ and $U$ in {\Coq} and it is known from Girard,
+Coquand, Hurkens and Miquel that systems $U-$ and $U$ are inconsistent
+[Girard 1972, Coquand 1991, Hurkens 1993, Miquel 2001]. This encoding
+can be found in file {\tt Logic/Hurkens.v} of {\Coq} standard library.
+
+For instance, when the user see {\tt $\forall$ X:Type, X->X : Type}, each
+occurrence of {\Type} is implicitly bound to a different level, say
+$\alpha$ and $\beta$ and the actual statement is {\tt
+forall X:Type($\alpha$), X->X : Type($\beta$)} with the constraint
+$\alpha<\beta$.
+
+When a statement violates a constraint, the message {\tt Universe
+inconsistency} appears. Example: {\tt fun (x:Type) (y:$\forall$ X:Type, X
+{\coqimp} X) => y x x}.
+
+\Question{I have two proofs of the same proposition. Can I prove they are equal?}
+
+In the base {\Coq} system, the answer is generally no. However, if
+classical logic is set, the answer is yes for propositions in {\Prop}.
+The answer is also yes if proof irrelevance holds (see question
+\ref{proof-irrelevance}).
+
+There are also ``simple enough'' propositions for which you can prove
+the equality without requiring any extra axioms. This is typically
+the case for propositions defined deterministically as a first-order
+inductive predicate on decidable sets. See for instance in question
+\ref{le-uniqueness} an axiom-free proof of the unicity of the proofs of
+the proposition {\tt le m n} (less or equal on {\tt nat}).
+
+% It is an ongoing work of research to natively include proof
+% irrelevance in {\Coq}.
+
+\Question{I have two proofs of an equality statement. Can I prove they are
+equal?}
+
+ Yes, if equality is decidable on the domain considered (which
+is the case for {\tt nat}, {\tt bool}, etc): see {\Coq} file
+\verb=Eqdep_dec.v=). No otherwise, unless
+assuming Streicher's axiom $K$ (see \cite{HofStr98}) or a more general
+assumption such as proof-irrelevance (see \ref{proof-irrelevance}) or
+classical logic.
+
+All of these statements can be found in file \vfile{\LogicEqdep}{Eqdep}.
+
+\Question{Can I prove that the second components of equal dependent
+pairs are equal?}
+
+ The answer is the same as for proofs of equality
+statements. It is provable if equality on the domain of the first
+component is decidable (look at \verb=inj_right_pair= from file
+\vfile{\LogicEqdepDec}{Eqdep\_dec}), but not provable in the general
+case. However, it is consistent (with the Calculus of Constructions)
+to assume it is true. The file \vfile{\LogicEqdep}{Eqdep} actually
+provides an axiom (equivalent to Streicher's axiom $K$) which entails
+the result (look at \verb=inj_pair2= in \vfile{\LogicEqdep}{Eqdep}).
+
+\subsection{Impredicativity}
+
+\Question{Why {\tt injection} does not work on impredicative {\tt Set}?}
+
+ E.g. in this case (this occurs only in the {\tt Set}-impredicative
+ variant of \Coq):
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Reset Initial.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Inductive I : Type :=
+ intro : forall k:Set, k -> I.
+Lemma eq_jdef :
+ forall x y:nat, intro _ x = intro _ y -> x = y.
+Proof.
+ intros x y H; injection H.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+ Injectivity of constructors is restricted to predicative types. If
+injectivity on large inductive types were not restricted, we would be
+allowed to derive an inconsistency (e.g. following the lines of
+Burali-Forti paradox). The question remains open whether injectivity
+is consistent on some large inductive types not expressive enough to
+encode known paradoxes (such as type I above).
+
+
+\Question{What is a ``large inductive definition''?}
+
+An inductive definition in {\Prop} or {\Set} is called large
+if its constructors embed sets or propositions. As an example, here is
+a large inductive type:
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Inductive sigST (P:Set -> Set) : Type :=
+ existST : forall X:Set, P X -> sigST P.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+In the {\tt Set} impredicative variant of {\Coq}, large inductive
+definitions in {\tt Set} have restricted elimination schemes to
+prevent inconsistencies. Especially, projecting the set or the
+proposition content of a large inductive definition is forbidden. If
+it were allowed, it would be possible to encode e.g. Burali-Forti
+paradox \cite{Gir70,Coq85}.
+
+
+%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
+\section{Talkin' with the Rooster}
+
+
+%%%%%%%
+\subsection{My goal is ..., how can I prove it?}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is a conjunction, how can I prove it?}
+
+Use some theorem or assumption or use the {\split} tactic.
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B:Prop, A->B-> A/\B.
+intros.
+split.
+assumption.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{My goal contains a conjunction as an hypothesis, how can I use it?}
+
+If you want to decompose your hypothesis into other hypothesis you can use the {\decompose} tactic:
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B:Prop, A/\B-> B.
+intros.
+decompose [and] H.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is a disjunction, how can I prove it?}
+
+You can prove the left part or the right part of the disjunction using
+{\left} or {\right} tactics. If you want to do a classical
+reasoning step, use the {\tt classic} axiom to prove the right part with the assumption
+that the left part of the disjunction is false.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B:Prop, A-> A\/B.
+intros.
+left.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+An example using classical reasoning:
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Require Import Classical.
+
+Ltac classical_right :=
+match goal with
+| _:_ |-?X1 \/ _ => (elim (classic X1);intro;[left;trivial|right])
+end.
+
+Ltac classical_left :=
+match goal with
+| _:_ |- _ \/?X1 => (elim (classic X1);intro;[right;trivial|left])
+end.
+
+
+Goal forall A B:Prop, (~A -> B) -> A\/B.
+intros.
+classical_right.
+auto.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{My goal is an universally quantified statement, how can I prove it?}
+
+Use some theorem or assumption or introduce the quantified variable in
+the context using the {\intro} tactic. If there are several
+variables you can use the {\intros} tactic. A good habit is to
+provide names for these variables: {\Coq} will do it anyway, but such
+automatic naming decreases legibility and robustness.
+
+
+\Question{My goal is an existential, how can I prove it?}
+
+Use some theorem or assumption or exhibit the witness using the {\existstac} tactic.
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal exists x:nat, forall y, x+y=y.
+exists 0.
+intros.
+auto.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is solvable by some lemma, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\apply} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Reset Initial.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Lemma mylemma : forall x, x+0 = x.
+auto.
+Qed.
+
+Goal 3+0 = 3.
+apply mylemma.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+
+\Question{My goal contains False as an hypothesis, how can I prove it?}
+
+You can use the {\contradiction} or {\intuition} tactics.
+
+
+\Question{My goal is an equality of two convertible terms, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\reflexivity} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall x, 0+x = x.
+intros.
+reflexivity.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{My goal is a {\tt let x := a in ...}, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\intro} tactic.
+
+
+\Question{My goal is a {\tt let (a, ..., b) := c in}, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\destruct} c as (a,...,b) tactic.
+
+
+\Question{My goal contains some existential hypotheses, how can I use it?}
+
+You can use the tactic {\elim} with you hypotheses as an argument.
+
+\Question{My goal contains some existential hypotheses, how can I use it and decompose my knowledge about this new thing into different hypotheses?}
+
+\begin{verbatim}
+Ltac DecompEx H P := elim H;intro P;intro TO;decompose [and] TO;clear TO;clear H.
+\end{verbatim}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is an equality, how can I swap the left and right hand terms?}
+
+Just use the {\symmetry} tactic.
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall x y : nat, x=y -> y=x.
+intros.
+symmetry.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{My hypothesis is an equality, how can I swap the left and right hand terms?}
+
+Just use the {\symmetryin} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall x y : nat, x=y -> y=x.
+intros.
+symmetry in H.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is an equality, how can I prove it by transitivity?}
+
+Just use the {\transitivity} tactic.
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall x y z : nat, x=y -> y=z -> x=z.
+intros.
+transitivity y.
+assumption.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal would be solvable using {\tt apply;assumption} if it would not create meta-variables, how can I prove it?}
+
+You can use {\tt eapply yourtheorem;eauto} but it won't work in all cases ! (for example if more than one hypothesis match one of the subgoals generated by \eapply) so you should rather use {\tt try solve [eapply yourtheorem;eauto]}, otherwise some metavariables may be incorrectly instantiated.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Lemma trans : forall x y z : nat, x=y -> y=z -> x=z.
+intros.
+transitivity y;assumption.
+Qed.
+
+Goal forall x y z : nat, x=y -> y=z -> x=z.
+intros.
+eapply trans;eauto.
+Qed.
+
+Goal forall x y z t : nat, x=y -> x=t -> y=z -> x=z.
+intros.
+eapply trans;eauto.
+Undo.
+eapply trans.
+apply H.
+auto.
+Qed.
+
+Goal forall x y z t : nat, x=y -> x=t -> y=z -> x=z.
+intros.
+eapply trans;eauto.
+Undo.
+try solve [eapply trans;eauto].
+eapply trans.
+apply H.
+auto.
+Qed.
+
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{My goal is solvable by some lemma within a set of lemmas and I don't want to remember which one, how can I prove it?}
+
+You can use a what is called a hints' base.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Require Import ZArith.
+Require Ring.
+Open Local Scope Z_scope.
+Lemma toto1 : 1+1 = 2.
+ring.
+Qed.
+Lemma toto2 : 2+2 = 4.
+ring.
+Qed.
+Lemma toto3 : 2+1 = 3.
+ring.
+Qed.
+
+Hint Resolve toto1 toto2 toto3 : mybase.
+
+Goal 2+(1+1)=4.
+auto with mybase.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is one of the hypotheses, how can I prove it?}
+
+Use the {\assumption} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal 1=1 -> 1=1.
+intro.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal appears twice in the hypotheses and I want to choose which one is used, how can I do it?}
+
+Use the {\exact} tactic.
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal 1=1 -> 1=1 -> 1=1.
+intros.
+exact H0.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{What can be the difference between applying one hypothesis or another in the context of the last question?}
+
+From a proof point of view it is equivalent but if you want to extract
+a program from your proof, the two hypotheses can lead to different
+programs.
+
+
+\Question{My goal is a propositional tautology, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\tauto} tactic.
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B:Prop, A-> (A\/B) /\ A.
+intros.
+tauto.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{My goal is a first order formula, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the semi-decision tactic: \firstorder.
+
+\iffalse
+todo: demander un exemple à Pierre
+\fi
+
+\Question{My goal is solvable by a sequence of rewrites, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\congruence} tactic.
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall a b c d e, a=d -> b=e -> c+b=d -> c+e=a.
+intros.
+congruence.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is a disequality solvable by a sequence of rewrites, how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\congruence} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall a b c d, a<>d -> b=a -> d=c+b -> b<>c+b.
+intros.
+congruence.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is an equality on some ring (e.g. natural numbers), how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\ring} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Require Import ZArith.
+Require Ring.
+Open Local Scope Z_scope.
+Goal forall a b : Z, (a+b)*(a+b) = a*a + 2*a*b + b*b.
+intros.
+ring.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{My goal is an equality on some field (e.g. real numbers), how can I prove it?}
+
+Just use the {\field} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Require Import Reals.
+Require Ring.
+Open Local Scope R_scope.
+Goal forall a b : R, b*a<>0 -> (a/b) * (b/a) = 1.
+intros.
+field.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is an inequality on integers in Presburger's arithmetic (an expression build from +,-,constants and variables), how can I prove it?}
+
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Require Import ZArith.
+Require Omega.
+Open Local Scope Z_scope.
+Goal forall a : Z, a>0 -> a+a > a.
+intros.
+omega.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\Question{My goal is an equation solvable using equational hypothesis on some ring (e.g. natural numbers), how can I prove it?}
+
+You need the {\gb} tactic (see Loïc Pottier's homepage).
+
+\subsection{Tactics usage}
+
+\Question{I want to state a fact that I will use later as an hypothesis, how can I do it?}
+
+If you want to use forward reasoning (first proving the fact and then
+using it) you just need to use the {\assert} tactic. If you want to use
+backward reasoning (proving your goal using an assumption and then
+proving the assumption) use the {\cut} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B C D : Prop, (A -> B) -> (B->C) -> A -> C.
+intros.
+assert (A->C).
+intro;apply H0;apply H;assumption.
+apply H2.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+
+Goal forall A B C D : Prop, (A -> B) -> (B->C) -> A -> C.
+intros.
+cut (A->C).
+intro.
+apply H2;assumption.
+intro;apply H0;apply H;assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+
+
+\Question{I want to state a fact that I will use later as an hypothesis and prove it later, how can I do it?}
+
+You can use {\cut} followed by {\intro} or you can use the following {\Ltac} command:
+\begin{verbatim}
+Ltac assert_later t := cut t;[intro|idtac].
+\end{verbatim}
+
+\Question{What is the difference between {\Qed} and {\Defined}?}
+
+These two commands perform type checking, but when {\Defined} is used the new definition is set as transparent, otherwise it is defined as opaque (see \ref{opaque}).
+
+
+\Question{How can I know what a tactic does?}
+
+You can use the {\tt info} command.
+
+
+
+\Question{Why {\auto} does not work? How can I fix it?}
+
+You can increase the depth of the proof search or add some lemmas in the base of hints.
+Perhaps you may need to use \eauto.
+
+\Question{What is {\eauto}?}
+
+This is the same tactic as \auto, but it relies on {\eapply} instead of \apply.
+
+\iffalse
+todo les espaces
+\fi
+
+\Question{How can I speed up {\auto}?}
+
+You can use \texttt{info }\auto to replace {\auto} by the tactics it generates.
+You can split your hint bases into smaller ones.
+
+
+\Question{What is the equivalent of {\tauto} for classical logic?}
+
+Currently there are no equivalent tactic for classical logic. You can use Gödel's ``not not'' translation.
+
+
+\Question{I want to replace some term with another in the goal, how can I do it?}
+
+If one of your hypothesis (say {\tt H}) states that the terms are equal you can use the {\rewrite} tactic. Otherwise you can use the {\replace} {\tt with} tactic.
+
+\Question{I want to replace some term with another in an hypothesis, how can I do it?}
+
+You can use the {\rewrite} {\tt in} tactic.
+
+\Question{I want to replace some symbol with its definition, how can I do it?}
+
+You can use the {\unfold} tactic.
+
+\Question{How can I reduce some term?}
+
+You can use the {\simpl} tactic.
+
+\Question{How can I declare a shortcut for some term?}
+
+You can use the {\set} or {\pose} tactics.
+
+\Question{How can I perform case analysis?}
+
+You can use the {\case} or {\destruct} tactics.
+
+
+\Question{Why should I name my intros?}
+
+When you use the {\intro} tactic you don't have to give a name to your
+hypothesis. If you do so the name will be generated by {\Coq} but your
+scripts may be less robust. If you add some hypothesis to your theorem
+(or change their order), you will have to change your proof to adapt
+to the new names.
+
+\Question{How can I automatize the naming?}
+
+You can use the {\tt Show Intro.} or {\tt Show Intros.} commands to generate the names and use your editor to generate a fully named {\intro} tactic.
+This can be automatized within {\tt xemacs}.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B C : Prop, A -> B -> C -> A/\B/\C.
+Show Intros.
+(*
+A B C H H0
+H1
+*)
+intros A B C H H0 H1.
+repeat split;assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{I want to automatize the use of some tactic, how can I do it?}
+
+You need to use the {\tt proof with T} command and add {\ldots} at the
+end of your sentences.
+
+For instance:
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B C : Prop, A -> B/\C -> A/\B/\C.
+Proof with assumption.
+intros.
+split...
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{I want to execute the {\texttt proof with} tactic only if it solves the goal, how can I do it?}
+
+You need to use the {\try} and {\solve} tactics. For instance:
+\begin{coq_example}
+Require Import ZArith.
+Require Ring.
+Open Local Scope Z_scope.
+Goal forall a b c : Z, a+b=b+a.
+Proof with try solve [ring].
+intros...
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{How can I do the opposite of the {\intro} tactic?}
+
+You can use the {\generalize} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Goal forall A B : Prop, A->B-> A/\B.
+intros.
+generalize H.
+intro.
+auto.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{One of the hypothesis is an equality between a variable and some term, I want to get rid of this variable, how can I do it?}
+
+You can use the {\subst} tactic. This will rewrite the equality everywhere and clear the assumption.
+
+\Question{What can I do if I get ``{\tt generated subgoal term has metavariables in it }''?}
+
+You should use the {\eapply} tactic, this will generate some goals containing metavariables.
+
+\Question{How can I instantiate some metavariable?}
+
+Just use the {\instantiate} tactic.
+
+
+\Question{What is the use of the {\pattern} tactic?}
+
+The {\pattern} tactic transforms the current goal, performing
+beta-expansion on all the applications featuring this tactic's
+argument. For instance, if the current goal includes a subterm {\tt
+phi(t)}, then {\tt pattern t} transforms the subterm into {\tt (fun
+x:A => phi(x)) t}. This can be useful when {\apply} fails on matching,
+to abstract the appropriate terms.
+
+\Question{What is the difference between assert, cut and generalize?}
+
+PS: Notice for people that are interested in proof rendering that \assert
+and {\pose} (and \cut) are not rendered the same as {\generalize} (see the
+HELM experimental rendering tool at \ahref{http://helm.cs.unibo.it/library.html}{\url{http://helm.cs.unibo.it}}, link
+HELM, link COQ Online). Indeed {\generalize} builds a beta-expanded term
+while \assert, {\pose} and {\cut} uses a let-in.
+
+\begin{verbatim}
+ (* Goal is T *)
+ generalize (H1 H2).
+ (* Goal is A->T *)
+ ... a proof of A->T ...
+\end{verbatim}
+
+is rendered into something like
+\begin{verbatim}
+ (h) ... the proof of A->T ...
+ we proved A->T
+ (h0) by (H1 H2) we proved A
+ by (h h0) we proved T
+\end{verbatim}
+while
+\begin{verbatim}
+ (* Goal is T *)
+ assert q := (H1 H2).
+ (* Goal is A *)
+ ... a proof of A ...
+ (* Goal is A |- T *)
+ ... a proof of T ...
+\end{verbatim}
+is rendered into something like
+\begin{verbatim}
+ (q) ... the proof of A ...
+ we proved A
+ ... the proof of T ...
+ we proved T
+\end{verbatim}
+Otherwise said, {\generalize} is not rendered in a forward-reasoning way,
+while {\assert} is.
+
+\Question{What can I do if \Coq can not infer some implicit argument ?}
+
+You can state explicitely what this implicit argument is. See \ref{implicit}.
+
+\Question{How can I explicit some implicit argument ?}\label{implicit}
+
+Just use \texttt{A:=term} where \texttt{A} is the argument.
+
+For instance if you want to use the existence of ``nil'' on nat*nat lists:
+\begin{verbatim}
+exists (nil (A:=(nat*nat))).
+\end{verbatim}
+
+\iffalse
+\Question{Is there anyway to do pattern matching with dependent types?}
+
+todo
+\fi
+
+\subsection{Proof management}
+
+
+\Question{How can I change the order of the subgoals?}
+
+You can use the {\Focus} command to concentrate on some goal. When the goal is proved you will see the remaining goals.
+
+\Question{How can I change the order of the hypothesis?}
+
+You can use the {\tt Move ... after} command.
+
+\Question{How can I change the name of an hypothesis?}
+
+You can use the {\tt Rename ... into} command.
+
+\Question{How can I delete some hypothesis?}
+
+You can use the {\tt Clear} command.
+
+\Question{How can use a proof which is not finished?}
+
+You can use the {\tt Admitted} command to state your current proof as an axiom.
+
+\Question{How can I state a conjecture?}
+
+You can use the {\tt Admitted} command to state your current proof as an axiom.
+
+\Question{What is the difference between a lemma, a fact and a theorem?}
+
+From {\Coq} point of view there are no difference. But some tools can
+have a different behavior when you use a lemma rather than a
+theorem. For instance {\tt coqdoc} will not generate documentation for
+the lemmas within your development.
+
+\Question{How can I organize my proofs?}
+
+You can organize your proofs using the section mechanism of \Coq. Have
+a look at the manual for further information.
+
+
+%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
+\section{Inductive and Co-inductive types}
+
+\subsection{General}
+
+\Question{How can I prove that two constructors are different?}
+
+You can use the {\discriminate} tactic.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Inductive toto : Set := | C1 : toto | C2 : toto.
+Goal C1 <> C2.
+discriminate.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{During an inductive proof, how to get rid of impossible cases of an inductive definition?}
+
+Use the {\inversion} tactic.
+
+
+\Question{How can I prove that 2 terms in an inductive set are equal? Or different?}
+
+Have a look at \coqtt{decide equality} and \coqtt{discriminate} in the \ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/main.html}{Reference Manual}.
+
+\Question{Why is the proof of \coqtt{0+n=n} on natural numbers
+trivial but the proof of \coqtt{n+0=n} is not?}
+
+ Since \coqtt{+} (\coqtt{plus}) on natural numbers is defined by analysis on its first argument
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Print plus.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+{\noindent} The expression \coqtt{0+n} evaluates to \coqtt{n}. As {\Coq} reasons
+modulo evaluation of expressions, \coqtt{0+n} and \coqtt{n} are
+considered equal and the theorem \coqtt{0+n=n} is an instance of the
+reflexivity of equality. On the other side, \coqtt{n+0} does not
+evaluate to \coqtt{n} and a proof by induction on \coqtt{n} is
+necessary to trigger the evaluation of \coqtt{+}.
+
+\Question{Why is dependent elimination in Prop not
+available by default?}
+
+
+This is just because most of the time it is not needed. To derive a
+dependent elimination principle in {\tt Prop}, use the command {\tt Scheme} and
+apply the elimination scheme using the \verb=using= option of
+\verb=elim=, \verb=destruct= or \verb=induction=.
+
+
+\Question{Argh! I cannot write expressions like ``~{\tt if n <= p then p else n}~'', as in any programming language}
+\label{minmax}
+
+The short answer : You should use {\texttt le\_lt\_dec n p} instead.\\
+
+That's right, you can't.
+If you type for instance the following ``definition'':
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Reset Initial.
+\end{coq_eval}
+\begin{coq_example}
+Definition max (n p : nat) := if n <= p then p else n.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+As \Coq~ says, the term ``~\texttt{n <= p}~'' is a proposition, i.e. a
+statement that belongs to the mathematical world. There are many ways to
+prove such a proposition, either by some computation, or using some already
+proven theoremas. For instance, proving $3-2 \leq 2^{45503}$ is very easy,
+using some theorems on arithmetical operations. If you compute both numbers
+before comparing them, you risk to use a lot of time and space.
+
+
+On the contrary, a function for computing the greatest of two natural numbers
+is an algorithm which, called on two natural numbers
+$n$ and $p$, determines wether $n\leq p$ or $p < n$.
+Such a function is a \emph{decision procedure} for the inequality of
+ \texttt{nat}. The possibility of writing such a procedure comes
+directly from de decidability of the order $\leq$ on natural numbers.
+
+
+When you write a piece of code like
+``~\texttt{if n <= p then \dots{} else \dots}~''
+in a
+programming language like \emph{ML} or \emph{Java}, a call to such a
+decision procedure is generated. The decision procedure is in general
+a primitive function, written in a low-level language, in the correctness
+of which you have to trust.
+
+The standard Library of the system \emph{Coq} contains a
+(constructive) proof of decidability of the order $\leq$ on
+\texttt{nat} : the function \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} of
+the module \texttt{Compare\_dec} of library \texttt{Arith}.
+
+The following code shows how to define correctly \texttt{min} and
+\texttt{max}, and prove some properties of these functions.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Require Import Compare_dec.
+
+Definition max (n p : nat) := if le_lt_dec n p then p else n.
+
+Definition min (n p : nat) := if le_lt_dec n p then n else p.
+
+Eval compute in (min 4 7).
+
+Theorem min_plus_max : forall n p, min n p + max n p = n + p.
+Proof.
+ intros n p;
+ unfold min, max;
+ case (le_lt_dec n p);
+ simpl; auto with arith.
+Qed.
+
+Theorem max_equiv : forall n p, max n p = p <-> n <= p.
+Proof.
+ unfold max; intros n p; case (le_lt_dec n p);simpl; auto.
+ intuition auto with arith.
+ split.
+ intro e; rewrite e; auto with arith.
+ intro H; absurd (p < p); eauto with arith.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{I wrote my own decision procedure for $\leq$, which
+is much faster than yours, but proving such theorems as
+ \texttt{max\_equiv} seems to be quite difficult}
+
+Your code is probably the following one:
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Fixpoint my_le_lt_dec (n p :nat) {struct n}: bool :=
+ match n, p with 0, _ => true
+ | S n', S p' => my_le_lt_dec n' p'
+ | _ , _ => false
+ end.
+
+Definition my_max (n p:nat) := if my_le_lt_dec n p then p else n.
+
+Definition my_min (n p:nat) := if my_le_lt_dec n p then n else p.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+For instance, the computation of \texttt{my\_max 567 321} is almost
+immediate, whereas one can't wait for the result of
+\texttt{max 56 32}, using \emph{Coq's} \texttt{le\_lt\_dec}.
+
+This is normal. Your definition is a simple recursive function which
+returns a boolean value. Coq's \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} is a \emph{certified
+function}, i.e. a complex object, able not only to tell wether $n\leq p$
+or $p<n$, but also of building a complete proof of the correct inequality.
+What make \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} inefficient for computing \texttt{min}
+and \texttt{max} is the building of a huge proof term.
+
+Nevertheless, \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} is very useful. Its type
+is a strong specification, using the
+\texttt{sumbool} type (look at the reference manual or chapter 9 of
+\cite{coqart}). Eliminations of the form
+``~\texttt{case (le\_lt\_dec n p)}~'' provide proofs of
+either $n \leq p$ or $p < n$, allowing to prove easily theorems as in
+question~\ref{minmax}. Unfortunately, this not the case of your
+\texttt{my\_le\_lt\_dec}, which returns a quite non-informative boolean
+value.
+
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Check le_lt_dec.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+You should keep in mind that \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} is useful to build
+certified programs which need to compare natural numbers, and is not
+designed to compare quickly two numbers.
+
+Nevertheless, the \emph{extraction} of \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} towards
+\emph{Ocaml} or \emph{Haskell}, is a reasonable program for comparing two
+natural numbers in Peano form in linear time.
+
+It is also possible to keep your boolean function as a decision procedure,
+but you have to establish yourself the relationship between \texttt{my\_le\_lt\_dec} and the propositions $n\leq p$ and $p<n$:
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Theorem my_le_lt_dec_true :
+ forall n p, my_le_lt_dec n p = true <-> n <= p.
+
+Theorem my_le_lt_dec_false :
+ forall n p, my_le_lt_dec n p = false <-> p < n.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+
+\subsection{Recursion}
+
+\Question{Why can't I define a non terminating program?}
+
+ Because otherwise the decidability of the type-checking
+algorithm (which involves evaluation of programs) is not ensured. On
+another side, if non terminating proofs were allowed, we could get a
+proof of {\tt False}:
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+(* This is fortunately not allowed! *)
+Fixpoint InfiniteProof (n:nat) : False := InfiniteProof n.
+Theorem Paradox : False.
+Proof (InfiniteProof O).
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+
+\Question{Why only structurally well-founded loops are allowed?}
+
+ The structural order on inductive types is a simple and
+powerful notion of termination. The consistency of the Calculus of
+Inductive Constructions relies on it and another consistency proof
+would have to be made for stronger termination arguments (such
+as the termination of the evaluation of CIC programs themselves!).
+
+In spite of this, all non-pathological termination orders can be mapped
+to a structural order. Tools to do this are provided in the file
+\vfile{\InitWf}{Wf} of the standard library of {\Coq}.
+
+\Question{How to define loops based on non structurally smaller
+recursive calls?}
+
+ The procedure is as follows (we consider the definition of {\tt
+mergesort} as an example).
+
+\begin{itemize}
+
+\item Define the termination order, say {\tt R} on the type {\tt A} of
+the arguments of the loop.
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Open Scope R_scope.
+Require Import List.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Definition R (a b:list nat) := length a < length b.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\item Prove that this order is well-founded (in fact that all elements in {\tt A} are accessible along {\tt R}).
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Lemma Rwf : well_founded R.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\item Define the step function (which needs proofs that recursive
+calls are on smaller arguments).
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Definition split (l : list nat)
+ : {l1: list nat | R l1 l} * {l2 : list nat | R l2 l}
+ := (* ... *) .
+Definition concat (l1 l2 : list nat) : list nat := (* ... *) .
+Definition merge_step (l : list nat) (f: forall l':list nat, R l' l -> list nat) :=
+ let (lH1,lH2) := (split l) in
+ let (l1,H1) := lH1 in
+ let (l2,H2) := lH2 in
+ concat (f l1 H1) (f l2 H2).
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\item Define the recursive function by fixpoint on the step function.
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Definition merge := Fix Rwf (fun _ => list nat) merge_step.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\end{itemize}
+
+\Question{What is behind the accessibility and well-foundedness proofs?}
+
+ Well-foundedness of some relation {\tt R} on some type {\tt A}
+is defined as the accessibility of all elements of {\tt A} along {\tt R}.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Print well_founded.
+Print Acc.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+The structure of the accessibility predicate is a well-founded tree
+branching at each node {\tt x} in {\tt A} along all the nodes {\tt x'}
+less than {\tt x} along {\tt R}. Any sequence of elements of {\tt A}
+decreasing along the order {\tt R} are branches in the accessibility
+tree. Hence any decreasing along {\tt R} is mapped into a structural
+decreasing in the accessibility tree of {\tt R}. This is emphasised in
+the definition of {\tt fix} which recurs not on its argument {\tt x:A}
+but on the accessibility of this argument along {\tt R}.
+
+See file \vfile{\InitWf}{Wf}.
+
+\Question{How to perform simultaneous double induction?}
+
+ In general a (simultaneous) double induction is simply solved by an
+induction on the first hypothesis followed by an inversion over the
+second hypothesis. Here is an example
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Reset Initial.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Inductive even : nat -> Prop :=
+ | even_O : even 0
+ | even_S : forall n:nat, even n -> even (S (S n)).
+
+Inductive odd : nat -> Prop :=
+ | odd_SO : odd 1
+ | odd_S : forall n:nat, odd n -> odd (S (S n)).
+
+Lemma not_even_and_odd : forall n:nat, even n -> odd n -> False.
+induction 1.
+ inversion 1.
+ inversion 1. apply IHeven; trivial.
+\end{coq_example}
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Qed.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+In case the type of the second induction hypothesis is not
+dependent, {\tt inversion} can just be replaced by {\tt destruct}.
+
+\Question{How to define a function by simultaneous double recursion?}
+
+ The same trick applies, you can even use the pattern-matching
+compilation algorithm to do the work for you. Here is an example:
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Fixpoint minus (n m:nat) {struct n} : nat :=
+ match n, m with
+ | O, _ => 0
+ | S k, O => S k
+ | S k, S l => minus k l
+ end.
+Print minus.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+In case of dependencies in the type of the induction objects
+$t_1$ and $t_2$, an extra argument stating $t_1=t_2$ must be given to
+the fixpoint definition
+
+\Question{How to perform nested and double induction?}
+
+ To reason by nested (i.e. lexicographic) induction, just reason by
+induction on the successive components.
+
+\smallskip
+
+Double induction (or induction on pairs) is a restriction of the
+lexicographic induction. Here is an example of double induction.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Lemma nat_double_ind :
+forall P : nat -> nat -> Prop, P 0 0 ->
+ (forall m n, P m n -> P m (S n)) ->
+ (forall m n, P m n -> P (S m) n) ->
+ forall m n, P m n.
+intros P H00 HmS HSn; induction m.
+(* case 0 *)
+induction n; [assumption | apply HmS; apply IHn].
+(* case Sm *)
+intro n; apply HSn; apply IHm.
+\end{coq_example}
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Qed.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\Question{How to define a function by nested recursion?}
+
+ The same trick applies. Here is the example of Ackermann
+function.
+
+\begin{coq_example}
+Fixpoint ack (n:nat) : nat -> nat :=
+ match n with
+ | O => S
+ | S n' =>
+ (fix ack' (m:nat) : nat :=
+ match m with
+ | O => ack n' 1
+ | S m' => ack n' (ack' m')
+ end)
+ end.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\subsection{Co-inductive types}
+
+\Question{I have a cofixpoint $t:=F(t)$ and I want to prove $t=F(t)$. How to do it?}
+
+Just case-expand $F({\tt t})$ then complete by a trivial case analysis.
+Here is what it gives on e.g. the type of streams on naturals
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Set Implicit Arguments.
+\end{coq_eval}
+\begin{coq_example}
+CoInductive Stream (A:Set) : Set :=
+ Cons : A -> Stream A -> Stream A.
+CoFixpoint nats (n:nat) : Stream nat := Cons n (nats (S n)).
+Lemma Stream_unfold :
+ forall n:nat, nats n = Cons n (nats (S n)).
+Proof.
+ intro;
+ change (nats n = match nats n with
+ | Cons x s => Cons x s
+ end).
+ case (nats n); reflexivity.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+
+\section{Syntax and notations}
+
+\Question{I do not want to type ``forall'' because it is too long, what can I do?}
+
+You can define your own notation for forall:
+\begin{verbatim}
+Notation "fa x : t, P" := (forall x:t, P) (at level 200, x ident).
+\end{verbatim}
+or if your are using {\CoqIde} you can define a pretty symbol for for all and an input method (see \ref{forallcoqide}).
+
+
+
+\Question{How can I define a notation for square?}
+
+You can use for instance:
+\begin{verbatim}
+Notation "x ^2" := (Rmult x x) (at level 20).
+\end{verbatim}
+Note that you can not use:
+\begin{texttt}
+Notation "x $^²$" := (Rmult x x) (at level 20).
+\end{texttt}
+because ``$^2$'' is an iso-latin character. If you really want this kind of notation you should use UTF-8.
+
+
+\Question{Why ``no associativity'' and ``left associativity'' at the same level does not work?}
+
+Because we relie on camlp4 for syntactical analysis and camlp4 does not really implement no associativity. By default, non associative operators are defined as right associative.
+
+
+
+\Question{How can I know the associativity associated with a level?}
+
+You can do ``Print Grammar constr'', and decode the output from camlp4, good luck !
+
+\section{Modules}
+
+
+
+
+%%%%%%%
+\section{\Ltac}
+
+\Question{What is {\Ltac}?}
+
+{\Ltac} is the tactic language for \Coq. It provides the user with a
+high-level ``toolbox'' for tactic creation.
+
+\Question{Why do I always get the same error message?}
+
+
+\Question{Is there any printing command in {\Ltac}?}
+
+You can use the {\idtac} tactic with a string argument. This string
+will be printed out. The same applies to the {\fail} tactic
+
+\Question{What is the syntax for let in {\Ltac}?}
+
+If $x_i$ are identifiers and $e_i$ and $expr$ are tactic expressions, then let reads:
+\begin{center}
+{\tt let $x_1$:=$e_1$ with $x_2$:=$e_2$\ldots with $x_n$:=$e_n$ in
+$expr$}.
+\end{center}
+Beware that if $expr$ is complex (i.e. features at least a sequence) parenthesis
+should be added around it. For example:
+\begin{coq_example}
+Ltac twoIntro := let x:=intro in (x;x).
+\end{coq_example}
+
+\Question{What is the syntax for pattern matching in {\Ltac}?}
+
+Pattern matching on a term $expr$ (non-linear first order unification)
+with patterns $p_i$ and tactic expressions $e_i$ reads:
+\begin{center}
+\hspace{10ex}
+{\tt match $expr$ with
+\hspace*{2ex}$p_1$ => $e_1$
+\hspace*{1ex}\textbar$p_2$ => $e_2$
+\hspace*{1ex}\ldots
+\hspace*{1ex}\textbar$p_n$ => $e_n$
+\hspace*{1ex}\textbar\ \textunderscore\ => $e_{n+1}$
+end.
+}
+\end{center}
+Underscore matches all terms.
+
+\Question{What is the semantics for ``match goal''?}
+
+The semantics of {\tt match goal} depends on whether it returns
+tactics or not. The {\tt match goal} expression matches the current
+goal against a series of patterns: {$hyp_1 {\ldots} hyp_n$ \textbar-
+$ccl$}. It uses a first-order unification algorithm and in case of
+success, if the right-hand-side is an expression, it tries to type it
+while if the right-hand-side is a tactic, it tries to apply it. If the
+typing or the tactic application fails, the {\tt match goal} tries all
+the possible combinations of $hyp_i$ before dropping the branch and
+moving to the next one. Underscore matches all terms.
+
+\Question{Why can't I use a ``match goal'' returning a tactic in a non
+tail-recursive position?}
+
+This is precisely because the semantics of {\tt match goal} is to
+apply the tactic on the right as soon as a pattern unifies what is
+meaningful only in tail-recursive uses.
+
+The semantics in non tail-recursive call could have been the one used
+for terms (i.e. fail if the tactic expression is not typable, but
+don't try to apply it). For uniformity of semantics though, this has
+been rejected.
+
+\Question{How can I generate a new name?}
+
+You can use the following syntax:
+{\tt let id:=fresh in \ldots}\\
+For example:
+\begin{coq_example}
+Ltac introIdGen := let id:=fresh in intro id.
+\end{coq_example}
+
+
+\iffalse
+\Question{How can I access the type of a term?}
+
+You can use typeof.
+todo
+\fi
+
+\Question{How can I define static and dynamic code?}
+
+\section{Tactics written in Ocaml}
+
+\Question{Can you show me an example of a tactic written in OCaml?}
+
+You have some examples of tactics written in Ocaml in the ``contrib'' directory of {\Coq} sources.
+
+
+
+
+\section{Case studies}
+
+
+\Question{How can I define vectors or lists of size n?}
+
+\Question{How to prove that 2 sets are different?}
+
+ You need to find a property true on one set and false on the
+other one. As an example we show how to prove that {\tt bool} and {\tt
+nat} are discriminable. As discrimination property we take the
+property to have no more than 2 elements.
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Theorem nat_bool_discr : bool <> nat.
+Proof.
+ pose (discr :=
+ fun X:Set =>
+ ~ (forall a b:X, ~ (forall x:X, x <> a -> x <> b -> False))).
+ intro Heq; assert (H: discr bool).
+ intro H; apply (H true false); destruct x; auto.
+ rewrite Heq in H; apply H; clear H.
+ destruct a; destruct b as [|n]; intro H0; eauto.
+ destruct n; [ apply (H0 2); discriminate | eauto ].
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\Question{Is there an axiom-free proof of Streicher's axiom $K$ for
+the equality on {\tt nat}?}
+\label{K-nat}
+
+Yes, because equality is decidable on {\tt nat}. Here is the proof.
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Require Import Eqdep_dec.
+Require Import Peano_dec.
+Theorem K_nat :
+ forall (x:nat) (P:x = x -> Prop), P (refl_equal x) -> forall p:x = x, P p.
+Proof.
+intros; apply K_dec_set with (p := p).
+apply eq_nat_dec.
+assumption.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+Similarly, we have
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Theorem eq_rect_eq_nat :
+ forall (p:nat) (Q:nat->Type) (x:Q p) (h:p=p), x = eq_rect p Q x p h.
+Proof.
+intros; apply K_nat with (p := h); reflexivity.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\Question{How to prove that two proofs of {\tt n<=m} on {\tt nat} are equal?}
+\label{le-uniqueness}
+
+This is provable without requiring any axiom because axiom $K$
+directly holds on {\tt nat}. Here is a proof using question \ref{K-nat}.
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Require Import Arith.
+Scheme le_ind' := Induction for le Sort Prop.
+Theorem le_uniqueness_proof : forall (n m : nat) (p q : n <= m), p = q.
+Proof.
+induction p using le_ind'; intro q.
+ replace (le_n n) with
+ (eq_rect _ (fun n0 => n <= n0) (le_n n) _ (refl_equal n)).
+ 2:reflexivity.
+ generalize (refl_equal n).
+ pattern n at 2 4 6 10, q; case q; [intro | intros m l e].
+ rewrite <- eq_rect_eq_nat; trivial.
+ contradiction (le_Sn_n m); rewrite <- e; assumption.
+ replace (le_S n m p) with
+ (eq_rect _ (fun n0 => n <= n0) (le_S n m p) _ (refl_equal (S m))).
+ 2:reflexivity.
+ generalize (refl_equal (S m)).
+ pattern (S m) at 1 3 4 6, q; case q; [intro Heq | intros m0 l HeqS].
+ contradiction (le_Sn_n m); rewrite Heq; assumption.
+ injection HeqS; intro Heq; generalize l HeqS.
+ rewrite <- Heq; intros; rewrite <- eq_rect_eq_nat.
+ rewrite (IHp l0); reflexivity.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+\Question{How to exploit equalities on sets}
+
+To extract information from an equality on sets, you need to
+find a predicate of sets satisfied by the elements of the sets. As an
+example, let's consider the following theorem.
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Theorem interval_discr :
+ forall m n:nat,
+ {x : nat | x <= m} = {x : nat | x <= n} -> m = n.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+We have a proof requiring the axiom of proof-irrelevance. We
+conjecture that proof-irrelevance can be circumvented by introducing a
+primitive definition of discrimination of the proofs of
+\verb!{x : nat | x <= m}!.
+
+\begin{latexonly}%
+The proof can be found in file {\tt interval$\_$discr.v} in this directory.
+%Here is the proof
+%\begin{small}
+%\begin{flushleft}
+%\begin{texttt}
+%\def_{\ifmmode\sb\else\subscr\fi}
+%\include{interval_discr.v}
+%%% WARNING semantics of \_ has changed !
+%\end{texttt}
+%$a\_b\_c$
+%\end{flushleft}
+%\end{small}
+\end{latexonly}%
+\begin{htmlonly}%
+\ahref{./interval_discr.v}{Here} is the proof.
+\end{htmlonly}
+
+\Question{I have a problem of dependent elimination on
+proofs, how to solve it?}
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Reset Initial.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Inductive Def1 : Set := c1 : Def1.
+Inductive DefProp : Def1 -> Prop :=
+ c2 : forall d:Def1, DefProp d.
+Inductive Comb : Set :=
+ c3 : forall d:Def1, DefProp d -> Comb.
+Lemma eq_comb :
+ forall (d1 d1':Def1) (d2:DefProp d1) (d2':DefProp d1'),
+ d1 = d1' -> c3 d1 d2 = c3 d1' d2'.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+ You need to derive the dependent elimination
+scheme for DefProp by hand using {\coqtt Scheme}.
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Abort.
+\end{coq_eval}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Scheme DefProp_elim := Induction for DefProp Sort Prop.
+Lemma eq_comb :
+ forall d1 d1':Def1,
+ d1 = d1' ->
+ forall (d2:DefProp d1) (d2':DefProp d1'), c3 d1 d2 = c3 d1' d2'.
+intros.
+destruct H.
+destruct d2 using DefProp_elim.
+destruct d2' using DefProp_elim.
+reflexivity.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+
+\Question{And what if I want to prove the following?}
+
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Inductive natProp : nat -> Prop :=
+ | p0 : natProp 0
+ | pS : forall n:nat, natProp n -> natProp (S n).
+Inductive package : Set :=
+ pack : forall n:nat, natProp n -> package.
+Lemma eq_pack :
+ forall n n':nat,
+ n = n' ->
+ forall (np:natProp n) (np':natProp n'), pack n np = pack n' np'.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+
+
+\begin{coq_eval}
+Abort.
+\end{coq_eval}
+\begin{coq_example*}
+Scheme natProp_elim := Induction for natProp Sort Prop.
+Definition pack_S : package -> package.
+destruct 1.
+apply (pack (S n)).
+apply pS; assumption.
+Defined.
+Lemma eq_pack :
+ forall n n':nat,
+ n = n' ->
+ forall (np:natProp n) (np':natProp n'), pack n np = pack n' np'.
+intros n n' Heq np np'.
+generalize dependent n'.
+induction np using natProp_elim.
+induction np' using natProp_elim; intros; auto.
+ discriminate Heq.
+induction np' using natProp_elim; intros; auto.
+ discriminate Heq.
+change (pack_S (pack n np) = pack_S (pack n0 np')).
+apply (f_equal (A:=package)).
+apply IHnp.
+auto.
+Qed.
+\end{coq_example*}
+
+
+
+
+
+
+
+\section{Publishing tools}
+
+\Question{How can I generate some latex from my development?}
+
+You can use {\tt coqdoc}.
+
+\Question{How can I generate some HTML from my development?}
+
+You can use {\tt coqdoc}.
+
+\Question{How can I generate some dependency graph from my development?}
+
+\Question{How can I cite some {\Coq} in my latex document?}
+
+You can use {\tt coq\_tex}.
+
+\Question{How can I cite the {\Coq} reference manual?}
+
+You can use this bibtex entry:
+\begin{verbatim}
+@Manual{Coq:manual,
+ title = {The Coq proof assistant reference manual},
+ author = {\mbox{The Coq development team}},
+ organization = {LogiCal Project},
+ note = {Version 8.0},
+ year = {2004},
+ url = "http://coq.inria.fr"
+}
+\end{verbatim}
+
+\Question{Where can I publish my developments in {\Coq}?}
+
+You can submit your developments as a user contribution to the {\Coq}
+development team. This ensures its liveness along the evolution and
+possible changes of {\Coq}.
+
+You can also submit your developments to the HELM/MoWGLI repository at
+the University of Bologna (see
+\ahref{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}{\url{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}}). For
+developments submitted in this database, it is possible to visualize
+the developments in natural language and execute various retrieving
+requests.
+
+\Question{How can I read my proof in natural language?}
+
+You can submit your proof to the HELM/MoWGLI repository and use the
+rendering tool provided by the server (see
+\ahref{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}{\url{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}}).
+
+\section{\CoqIde}
+
+\Question{What is {\CoqIde}?}
+
+{\CoqIde} is a gtk based GUI for \Coq.
+
+\Question{How to enable Emacs keybindings?}
+ Insert \texttt{gtk-key-theme-name = "Emacs"}
+ in your \texttt{.coqide-gtk2rc} file. It may be in the current dir
+ or in \verb#$HOME# dir. This is done by default.
+
+%$ juste pour que la coloration emacs marche
+
+\Question{How to enable antialiased fonts?}
+
+ Set the \verb#GDK_USE_XFT# variable to \verb#1#. This is by default with \verb#Gtk >= 2.2#.
+ If some of your fonts are not available, set \verb#GDK_USE_XFT# to \verb#0#.
+
+\Question{How to use those Forall and Exists pretty symbols?}\label{forallcoqide}
+ Thanks to the notation features in \Coq, you just need to insert these
+lines in your {\Coq} buffer:\\
+\begin{texttt}
+Notation "$\forall$ x : t, P" := (forall x:t, P) (at level 200, x ident).
+\end{texttt}\\
+\begin{texttt}
+Notation "$\exists$ x : t, P" := (exists x:t, P) (at level 200, x ident).
+\end{texttt}
+
+Copy/Paste of these lines from this file will not work outside of \CoqIde.
+You need to load a file containing these lines or to enter the $\forall$
+using an input method (see \ref{inputmeth}). To try it just use \verb#Require Import utf8# from inside
+\CoqIde.
+To enable these notations automatically start coqide with
+\begin{verbatim}
+ coqide -l utf8
+\end{verbatim}
+In the ide subdir of {\Coq} library, you will find a sample utf8.v with some
+pretty simple notations.
+
+\Question{How to define an input method for non ASCII symbols?}\label{inputmeth}
+
+\begin{itemize}
+\item First solution: type \verb#<CONTROL><SHIFT>2200# to enter a forall in the script widow.
+ 2200 is the hexadecimal code for forall in unicode charts and is encoded as
+ in UTF-8.
+ 2203 is for exists. See \ahref{http://www.unicode.org}{\url{http://www.unicode.org}} for more codes.
+\item Second solution: rebind \verb#<AltGr>a# to forall and \verb#<AltGr>e# to exists.
+ Under X11, you need to use something like
+\begin{verbatim}
+ xmodmap -e "keycode 24 = a A F13 F13"
+ xmodmap -e "keycode 26 = e E F14 F14"
+\end{verbatim}
+ and then to add
+\begin{verbatim}
+ bind "F13" {"insert-at-cursor" ("")}
+ bind "F14" {"insert-at-cursor" ("")}
+\end{verbatim}
+ to your "binding "text"" section in \verb#.coqiderc-gtk2rc.#
+ The strange ("") argument is the UTF-8 encoding for
+ 0x2200.
+ You can compute these encodings using the lablgtk2 toplevel with
+\begin{verbatim}
+Glib.Utf8.from_unichar 0x2200;;
+\end{verbatim}
+ Further symbols can be bound on higher Fxx keys or on even on other keys you
+ do not need .
+\end{itemize}
+
+\Question{How to build a custom {\CoqIde} with user ml code?}
+ Use
+ coqmktop -ide -byte m1.cmo...mi.cmo
+ or
+ coqmktop -ide -opt m1.cmx...mi.cmx
+
+\Question{How to customize the shortcuts for menus?}
+ Two solutions are offered:
+\begin{itemize}
+\item Edit \$HOME/.coqide.keys by hand or
+\item Add "gtk-can-change-accels = 1" in your .coqide-gtk2rc file. Then
+ from \CoqIde, you may select a menu entry and press the desired
+ shortcut.
+\end{itemize}
+
+\Question{What encoding should I use? What is this $\backslash$x\{iiii\} in my file?}
+ The encoding option is related to the way files are saved.
+ Keep it as UTF-8 until it becomes important for you to exchange files
+ with non UTF-8 aware applications.
+ If you choose something else than UTF-8, then missing characters will
+ be encoded by $\backslash$x\{....\} or $\backslash$x\{........\}
+ where each dot is an hex. digit.
+ The number between braces is the hexadecimal UNICODE index for the
+ missing character.
+
+
+
+
+\section{Extraction}
+
+\Question{What is program extraction?}
+
+Program extraction consist in generating a program from a constructive proof.
+
+\Question{Which language can I extract to?}
+
+You can extract your programs to Objective Caml and Haskell.
+
+\Question{How can I extract an incomplete proof?}
+
+You can provide programs for your axioms.
+
+
+
+%%%%%%%
+\section{Glossary}
+
+\Question{Can you explain me what an evaluable constant is?}
+
+An evaluable constant is a constant which is unfoldable.
+
+\Question{What is a goal?}
+
+The goal is the statement to be proved.
+
+\Question{What is a meta variable?}
+
+A meta variable in {\Coq} represents a ``hole'', i.e. a part of a proof
+that is still unknown.
+
+\Question{What is Gallina?}
+
+Gallina is the specification language of \Coq. Complete documentation
+of this language can be found in the Reference Manual.
+
+\Question{What is The Vernacular?}
+
+It is the language of commands of Gallina i.e. definitions, lemmas, {\ldots}
+
+
+\Question{What is a dependent type?}
+
+A dependant type is a type which depends on some term. For instance
+``vector of size n'' is a dependant type representing all the vectors
+of size $n$. Its type depends on $n$
+
+\Question{What is a proof by reflection?}
+
+This is a proof generated by some computation which is done using the
+internal reduction of {\Coq} (not using the tactic language of {\Coq}
+(\Ltac) nor the implementation language for \Coq). An example of
+tactic using the reflection mechanism is the {\ring} tactic. The
+reflection method consist in reflecting a subset of {\Coq} language (for
+example the arithmetical expressions) into an object of the \Coq
+language itself (in this case an inductive type denoting arithmetical
+expressions). For more information see~\cite{howe,harrison,boutin}
+and the last chapter of the Coq'Art.
+
+\Question{What is intuitionistic logic?}
+
+This is any logic which does not assume that ``A or not A''.
+
+
+\Question{What is proof-irrelevance?}
+
+See question \ref{proof-irrelevance}
+
+
+\Question{What is the difference between opaque and transparent?}{\label{opaque}}
+
+Opaque definitions can not be unfolded but transparent ones can.
+
+
+\section{Troubleshooting}
+
+\Question{What can I do when {\tt Qed.} is slow?}
+
+Sometime you can use the {\abstracttac} tactic, which makes as if you had
+stated some local lemma, this speeds up the typing process.
+
+\Question{Why \texttt{Reset Initial.} does not work when using \texttt{coqc}?}
+
+The initial state corresponds to the state of coqtop when the interactive
+session began. It does not make sense in files to compile.
+
+
+\Question{What can I do if I get ``No more subgoals but non-instantiated existential variables''?}
+
+This means that {\eauto} or {\eapply} didn't instantiate an
+existential variable which eventually got erased by some computation.
+You have to backtrack to the faulty occurrence of {\eauto} or
+{\eapply} and give the missing argument an explicit value.
+
+\Question{What can I do if I get ``Cannot solve a second-order unification problem''?}
+
+You can help {\Coq} using the {\pattern} tactic.
+
+\Question{Why does {\Coq} tell me that \texttt{\{x:A|(P x)\}} is not convertible with \texttt{(sig A P)}?}
+
+ This is because \texttt{\{x:A|P x\}} is a notation for
+\texttt{sig (fun x:A => P x)}. Since {\Coq} does not reason up to
+$\eta$-conversion, this is different from \texttt{sig P}.
+
+
+\Question{I copy-paste a term and {\Coq} says it is not convertible
+ to the original term. Sometimes it even says the copied term is not
+well-typed.}
+
+ This is probably due to invisible implicit information (implicit
+arguments, coercions and Cases annotations) in the printed term, which
+is not re-synthesised from the copied-pasted term in the same way as
+it is in the original term.
+
+ Consider for instance {\tt (@eq Type True True)}. This term is
+printed as {\tt True=True} and re-parsed as {\tt (@eq Prop True
+True)}. The two terms are not convertible (hence they fool tactics
+like {\tt pattern}).
+
+ There is currently no satisfactory answer to the problem. However,
+the command {\tt Set Printing All} is useful for diagnosing the
+problem.
+
+ Due to coercions, one may even face type-checking errors. In some
+rare cases, the criterion to hide coercions is a bit too loose, which
+may result in a typing error message if the parser is not able to find
+again the missing coercion.
+
+
+
+\section{Conclusion and Farewell.}
+\label{ccl}
+
+\Question{What if my question isn't answered here?}
+\label{lastquestion}
+
+Don't panic \verb+:-)+. You can try the {\Coq} manual~\cite{Coq:manual} for a technical
+description of the prover. The Coq'Art~\cite{Coq:coqart} is the first
+book written on {\Coq} and provides a comprehensive review of the
+theorem prover as well as a number of example and exercises. Finally,
+the tutorial~\cite{Coq:Tutorial} provides a smooth introduction to
+theorem proving in \Coq.
+
+
+%%%%%%%
+\newpage
+\nocite{LaTeX:intro}
+\nocite{LaTeX:symb}
+\bibliography{fk}
+
+%%%%%%%
+\typeout{*********************************************}
+\typeout{********* That makes \thequestion{\space} questions **********}
+\typeout{*********************************************}
+
+\end{document}