summaryrefslogtreecommitdiff
path: root/doc/refman/RefMan-cic.tex
blob: 18b6ed9c52a5161fce5b9cb63fccc51b93e4a8c1 (plain)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
\chapter{Calculus of Inductive Constructions}
\label{Cic}
\index{Cic@\textsc{CIC}}
\index{pCic@p\textsc{CIC}}
\index{Calculus of (Co)Inductive Constructions}

The underlying formal language of {\Coq} is a {\em Calculus of
  Constructions} with {\em Inductive Definitions}.  It is presented in
this chapter.  
For {\Coq} version V7, this Calculus was known as the
{\em Calculus of (Co)Inductive Constructions}\index{Calculus of
  (Co)Inductive Constructions} (\iCIC\ in short).
The underlying calculus of {\Coq} version V8.0 and up is a weaker
  calculus where the sort \Set{} satisfies predicative rules. 
We call this calculus the 
{\em Predicative Calculus of (Co)Inductive
  Constructions}\index{Predicative Calculus of
  (Co)Inductive Constructions} (\pCIC\ in short).
In section~\ref{impredicativity} we give the extra-rules for \iCIC. A
  compiling option of \Coq{} allows to type-check theories in this
  extended system.

In \CIC\, all objects have a {\em type}. There are types for functions (or
programs), there are atomic types (especially datatypes)... but also
types for proofs and types for the types themselves.
Especially, any object handled in the formalism must belong to a
type.  For instance, the statement {\it ``for all x, P''} is not
allowed in type theory; you must say instead: {\it ``for all x
belonging to T, P''}. The expression {\it ``x belonging to T''} is
written {\it ``x:T''}. One also says: {\it ``x has type T''}.
The terms of {\CIC} are detailed in section \ref{Terms}.

In \CIC\, there is an internal reduction mechanism. In particular, it
allows to decide if two programs are {\em intentionally} equal (one
says {\em convertible}). Convertibility is presented in section 
\ref{convertibility}.

The remaining sections are concerned with the type-checking of terms.
The beginner can skip them.

The reader seeking a background on the Calculus of Inductive
Constructions may read several papers.  Giménez~\cite{Gim98} provides
an introduction to inductive and coinductive definitions in Coq. In
their book~\cite{CoqArt}, Bertot and Castéran give a precise
description of the \CIC{} based on numerous practical examples.
Barras~\cite{Bar99}, Werner~\cite{Wer94} and
Paulin-Mohring~\cite{Moh97} are the most recent theses dealing with
Inductive Definitions. Coquand-Huet~\cite{CoHu85a,CoHu85b,CoHu86}
introduces the Calculus of Constructions. Coquand-Paulin~\cite{CoPa89}
extended this calculus to inductive definitions. The {\CIC} is a
formulation of type theory including the possibility of inductive
constructions, Barendregt~\cite{Bar91} studies the modern form of type
theory.

\section{The terms}\label{Terms}

In most type theories, one usually makes a syntactic distinction
between types and terms. This is not the case for \CIC\ which defines
both types and terms in the same syntactical structure. This is
because the type-theory itself forces terms and types to be defined in
a mutual recursive way and also because similar constructions can be
applied to both terms and types and consequently can share the same
syntactic structure.

Consider for instance the $\ra$ constructor and assume \nat\ is the
type of natural numbers. Then $\ra$ is used both to denote
$\nat\ra\nat$ which is the type of functions from \nat\ to \nat, and
to denote $\nat \ra \Prop$ which is the type of unary predicates over
the natural numbers. Consider abstraction which builds functions. It
serves to build ``ordinary'' functions as $\kw{fun}~x:\nat \Ra ({\tt mult} ~x~x)$ (assuming {\tt mult} is already defined) but may build also 
predicates over the natural numbers. For instance $\kw{fun}~x:\nat \Ra
(x=x)$ will
represent a predicate $P$, informally written in mathematics
$P(x)\equiv x=x$. If $P$ has type $\nat \ra \Prop$, $(P~x)$ is a
proposition, furthermore $\kw{forall}~x:\nat,(P~x)$ will represent the type of
functions which associate to each natural number $n$ an object of
type $(P~n)$ and consequently represent proofs of the formula
``$\forall x.P(x)$''.

\subsection{Sorts}\label{Sorts}
\index{Sorts}
Types are seen as terms of the language and then should belong to
another type. The type of a type is always a constant of the language
called a {\em sort}.

The two basic sorts in the language of \CIC\ are \Set\ and \Prop.

The sort \Prop\ intends to be the type of logical propositions.  If
$M$ is a logical proposition then it denotes a class, namely the class
of terms representing proofs of $M$. An object $m$ belonging to $M$
witnesses the fact that $M$ is true.  An object of type \Prop\ is
called a {\em proposition}.

The sort \Set\ intends to be the type of specifications. This includes
programs and the usual sets such as booleans, naturals, lists
etc.

These sorts themselves can be manipulated as ordinary terms.
Consequently sorts also should be given a type.  Because assuming
simply that \Set\ has type \Set\ leads to an inconsistent theory, we
have infinitely many sorts in the language of \CIC. These are, in
addition to \Set\ and \Prop\, a hierarchy of universes \Type$(i)$
for any integer $i$.  We call \Sort\ the set of sorts
which is defined by:
\[\Sort \equiv \{\Prop,\Set,\Type(i)| i \in \NN\} \]
\index{Type@{\Type}}
\index{Prop@{\Prop}}
\index{Set@{\Set}}
The sorts enjoy the following properties: {\Prop:\Type(0)}, {\Set:\Type(0)} and
  {\Type$(i)$:\Type$(i+1)$}.

The user will never mention explicitly the index $i$ when referring to
the universe \Type$(i)$. One only writes \Type. The
system itself generates for each instance of \Type\ a new
index for the universe and checks that the constraints between these
indexes can be solved. From the user point of view we consequently
have {\sf Type :Type}.

We shall make precise in the typing rules the constraints between the
indexes.

\subsection{Constants}
Besides the sorts, the language also contains constants denoting
objects in the environment. These constants may denote previously
defined objects but also objects related to inductive definitions
(either the type itself or one of its constructors or destructors).

\medskip\noindent {\bf Remark. } In other presentations of \CIC, 
the inductive objects are not seen as
external declarations but as first-class terms. Usually the
definitions are also completely ignored.  This is a nice theoretical
point of view but not so practical. An inductive definition is
specified by a possibly huge set of declarations, clearly we want to
share this specification among the various inductive objects and not
to duplicate it. So the specification should exist somewhere and the
various objects should refer to it.  We choose one more level of
indirection where the objects are just represented as constants and
the environment gives the information on the kind of object the
constant refers to.

\medskip
Our inductive objects will be manipulated as constants declared in the
environment. This roughly corresponds to the way they are actually
implemented in the \Coq\ system. It is simple to map this presentation
in a theory where inductive objects are represented by terms.

\subsection{Terms}

Terms are built from variables, global names, constructors,
abstraction, application, local declarations bindings (``let-in''
expressions) and product.

From a syntactic point of view, types cannot be distinguished from terms,
except that they cannot start by an abstraction, and that if a term is
a sort or a product, it should be a type.

More precisely the language of the {\em Calculus of Inductive
  Constructions} is built from the following rules:

\begin{enumerate}
\item the sorts {\sf Set, Prop, Type} are terms.
\item names for global constants of the environment are terms.
\item variables are terms.
\item if $x$ is a variable and $T$, $U$ are terms then $\forall~x:T,U$
  ($\kw{forall}~x:T,U$ in \Coq{} concrete syntax) is a term. If $x$
  occurs in $U$, $\forall~x:T,U$ reads as {\it ``for all x of type T,
    U''}. As $U$ depends on $x$, one says that $\forall~x:T,U$ is a
  {\em dependent product}. If $x$ doesn't occurs in $U$ then
  $\forall~x:T,U$ reads as {\it ``if T then U''}. A non dependent
  product can be written: $T \rightarrow U$.
\item if $x$ is a variable and $T$, $U$ are terms then $\lb~x:T \mto U$
  ($\kw{fun}~x:T\Ra U$ in \Coq{} concrete syntax) is a term. This is a
  notation for the $\lambda$-abstraction of
  $\lambda$-calculus\index{lambda-calculus@$\lambda$-calculus}
  \cite{Bar81}. The term $\lb~x:T \mto U$ is a function which maps
  elements of $T$ to $U$.
\item if $T$ and $U$ are terms then $(T\ U)$ is a term  
 ($T~U$ in \Coq{} concrete syntax).  The term $(T\ 
  U)$ reads as {\it ``T applied to U''}.
\item if $x$ is a variable, and $T$, $U$ are terms then
  $\kw{let}~x:=T~\kw{in}~U$ is a
  term which denotes the term $U$ where the variable $x$ is locally
  bound to $T$. This stands for the common ``let-in'' construction of
  functional programs such as ML or Scheme.
\end{enumerate}

\paragraph{Notations.} Application associates to the left such that
$(t~t_1\ldots t_n)$ represents $(\ldots (t~t_1)\ldots t_n)$. The
products and arrows associate to the right such that $\forall~x:A,B\ra C\ra
D$ represents $\forall~x:A,(B\ra (C\ra D))$.  One uses sometimes
$\forall~x~y:A,B$ or
$\lb~x~y:A\mto B$ to denote the abstraction or product of several variables
of the same type. The equivalent formulation is $\forall~x:A, \forall y:A,B$ or
$\lb~x:A \mto \lb y:A \mto B$

\paragraph{Free variables.}
The notion of free variables is defined as usual.  In the expressions
$\lb~x:T\mto U$ and $\forall x:T, U$ the occurrences of $x$ in $U$
are bound.  They are represented by de Bruijn indexes in the internal
structure of terms.

\paragraph{Substitution.} \index{Substitution}
The notion of substituting a term $t$ to free occurrences of a
variable $x$ in a term $u$ is defined as usual. The resulting term
is written $\subst{u}{x}{t}$.


\section{Typed terms}\label{Typed-terms}

As objects of type theory, terms are subjected to {\em type
discipline}. The well typing of a term depends on an environment which
consists in a global environment (see below) and a local context.

\paragraph{Local context.}
A {\em local context} (or shortly context) is an ordered list of
declarations of variables. The declaration of some variable $x$ is
either an assumption, written $x:T$ ($T$ is a type) or a definition,
written $x:=t:T$.  We use brackets to write contexts. A
typical example is $[x:T;y:=u:U;z:V]$.  Notice that the variables
declared in a context must be distinct. If $\Gamma$ declares some $x$,
we write $x \in\Gamma$. By writing $(x:T)\in\Gamma$ we mean that
either $x:T$ is an assumption in $\Gamma$ or that there exists some $t$ such
that $x:=t:T$ is a definition in $\Gamma$. If $\Gamma$ defines some
$x:=t:T$, we also write $(x:=t:T)\in\Gamma$.  Contexts must be
themselves {\em well formed}.  For the rest of the chapter, the
notation $\Gamma::(y:T)$ (resp $\Gamma::(y:=t:T)$) denotes the context
$\Gamma$ enriched with the declaration $y:T$ (resp $y:=t:T$). The
notation $[]$ denotes the empty context.  \index{Context}

% Does not seem to be used further...
% Si dans l'explication WF(E)[Gamma] concernant les constantes
% definies ds un contexte

We define the inclusion of two contexts $\Gamma$ and $\Delta$ (written
as $\Gamma \subset \Delta$) as the property, for all variable $x$,
type $T$ and term $t$, if $(x:T) \in \Gamma$ then $(x:T)\in \Delta$
and if $(x:=t:T) \in \Gamma$ then $(x:=t:T)\in \Delta$.  
%We write
% $|\Delta|$ for the length of the context $\Delta$, that is for the number
% of declarations (assumptions or definitions) in $\Delta$.

A variable $x$ is said to be free in $\Gamma$ if $\Gamma$ contains a
declaration $y:T$ such that $x$ is free in $T$.

\paragraph{Environment.}\index{Environment}
Because we are manipulating global declarations (constants and global
assumptions), we also need to consider a global environment $E$.

An environment is an ordered list of declarations of global
names. Declarations are either assumptions or ``standard''
definitions, that is abbreviations for well-formed terms
but also definitions of inductive objects. In the latter
case, an object in the environment will define one or more constants
(that is types and constructors, see section \ref{Cic-inductive-definitions}).

An assumption will be represented in the environment as
\Assum{\Gamma}{c}{T} which means that $c$ is assumed of some type $T$
well-defined in some context $\Gamma$. An (ordinary) definition will
be represented in the environment as \Def{\Gamma}{c}{t}{T} which means
that $c$ is a constant which is valid in some context $\Gamma$ whose
value is $t$ and type is $T$.

The rules for inductive definitions (see section
\ref{Cic-inductive-definitions}) have to be considered as assumption
rules to which the following definitions apply: if the name $c$ is
declared in $E$, we write $c \in E$ and if $c:T$ or $c:=t:T$ is
declared in $E$, we write $(c : T) \in E$.

\paragraph{Typing rules.}\label{Typing-rules}\index{Typing rules}
In the following, we assume $E$ is a valid environment wrt to
inductive definitions.  We define simultaneously two
judgments.  The first one \WTEG{t}{T} means the term $t$ is well-typed
and has type $T$ in the environment $E$ and context $\Gamma$.  The
second judgment \WFE{\Gamma} means that the environment $E$ is
well-formed and the context $\Gamma$ is a valid context in this
environment.  It also means a third property which makes sure that any
constant in $E$ was defined in an environment which is included in
$\Gamma$
\footnote{This requirement could be relaxed if we instead introduced
  an explicit mechanism for instantiating constants. At the external
  level, the Coq engine works accordingly to this view that all the
  definitions in the environment were built in a sub-context of the
  current context.}.

A term $t$ is well typed in an environment $E$ iff there exists a
context $\Gamma$ and a term $T$ such that the judgment \WTEG{t}{T} can
be derived from the following rules.
\begin{description}
\item[W-E] \inference{\WF{[]}{[]}}
\item[W-S]  % Ce n'est pas vrai : x peut apparaitre plusieurs fois dans Gamma
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s\in \Sort~~~~x \not\in
      \Gamma           % \cup E
      }
      {\WFE{\Gamma::(x:T)}}~~~~~
    \frac{\WTEG{t}{T}~~~~x \not\in
      \Gamma           % \cup E
     }{\WFE{\Gamma::(x:=t:T)}}}
\item[Def] \inference{\frac{\WTEG{t}{T}~~~c \notin E\cup \Gamma}
                      {\WF{E;\Def{\Gamma}{c}{t}{T}}{\Gamma}}}
\item[Ax] \index{Typing rules!Ax}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}}{\WTEG{\Prop}{\Type(p)}}~~~~~
\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}}{\WTEG{\Set}{\Type(q)}}}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}~~~~i<j}{\WTEG{\Type(i)}{\Type(j)}}}
\item[Var]\index{Typing rules!Var}
 \inference{\frac{ \WFE{\Gamma}~~~~~(x:T)\in\Gamma~~\mbox{or}~~(x:=t:T)\in\Gamma~\mbox{for some $t$}}{\WTEG{x}{T}}}
\item[Const]  \index{Typing rules!Const}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}~~~~(c:T) \in E}{\WTEG{c}{T}}}
\item[Prod]  \index{Typing rules!Prod}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s \in \Sort~~~
    \WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Prop}}
      { \WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Prop}}} 
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s\in\{\Prop, \Set\}~~~~~~
    \WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Set}}
      { \WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Set}}} 
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{\Type(i)}~~~~i\leq k~~~
    \WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Type(j)}~~~j \leq k}
    {\WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Type(k)}}}
\item[Lam]\index{Typing rules!Lam} 
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{s}~~~~ \WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{t}{U}}
        {\WTEG{\lb~x:T\mto t}{\forall x:T, U}}}
\item[App]\index{Typing rules!App}
 \inference{\frac{\WTEG{t}{\forall~x:U,T}~~~~\WTEG{u}{U}}
                 {\WTEG{(t\ u)}{\subst{T}{x}{u}}}}
\item[Let]\index{Typing rules!Let} 
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{t}{T}~~~~ \WTE{\Gamma::(x:=t:T)}{u}{U}}
        {\WTEG{\kw{let}~x:=t~\kw{in}~u}{\subst{U}{x}{t}}}}
\end{description}
    
\Rem We may have $\kw{let}~x:=t~\kw{in}~u$
well-typed without having $((\lb~x:T\mto u)~t)$ well-typed (where
$T$ is a type of $t$). This is because the value $t$ associated to $x$
may be used in a conversion rule (see section \ref{conv-rules}).

\section{Conversion rules}
\index{Conversion rules}
\label{conv-rules}
\paragraph{$\beta$-reduction.}
\label{beta}\index{beta-reduction@$\beta$-reduction}

We want to be able to identify some terms as we can identify the
application of a function to a given argument with its result. For
instance the identity function over a given type $T$ can be written
$\lb~x:T\mto x$. In any environment $E$ and context $\Gamma$, we want to identify any object $a$ (of type $T$) with the
application $((\lb~x:T\mto x)~a)$. We define for this a {\em reduction} (or a
{\em conversion}) rule we call $\beta$:
\[ \WTEGRED{((\lb~x:T\mto
  t)~u)}{\triangleright_{\beta}}{\subst{t}{x}{u}} \] 
We say that $\subst{t}{x}{u}$ is the {\em $\beta$-contraction} of
$((\lb~x:T\mto t)~u)$ and, conversely, that $((\lb~x:T\mto t)~u)$
is the {\em $\beta$-expansion} of $\subst{t}{x}{u}$.

According to $\beta$-reduction, terms of the {\em Calculus of
  Inductive Constructions} enjoy some fundamental properties such as
confluence, strong normalization, subject reduction. These results are
theoretically of great importance but we will not detail them here and
refer the interested reader to \cite{Coq85}.

\paragraph{$\iota$-reduction.}
\label{iota}\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}
A specific conversion rule is associated to the inductive objects in
the environment.  We shall give later on (section \ref{iotared}) the
precise rules but it just says that a destructor applied to an object
built from a constructor behaves as expected.  This reduction is
called $\iota$-reduction and is more precisely studied in
\cite{Moh93,Wer94}.


\paragraph{$\delta$-reduction.}
\label{delta}\index{delta-reduction@$\delta$-reduction}

We may have defined variables in contexts or constants in the global
environment. It is legal to identify such a reference with its value,
that is to expand (or unfold) it into its value. This
reduction is called $\delta$-reduction and shows as follows.

$$\WTEGRED{x}{\triangleright_{\delta}}{t}~~~~~\mbox{if $(x:=t:T)\in\Gamma$}~~~~~~~~~\WTEGRED{c}{\triangleright_{\delta}}{t}~~~~~\mbox{if $(c:=t:T)\in E$}$$


\paragraph{$\zeta$-reduction.}
\label{zeta}\index{zeta-reduction@$\zeta$-reduction}

Coq allows also to remove local definitions occurring in terms by
replacing the defined variable by its value. The declaration being
destroyed, this reduction differs from $\delta$-reduction. It is
called $\zeta$-reduction and shows as follows.

$$\WTEGRED{\kw{let}~x:=u~\kw{in}~t}{\triangleright_{\zeta}}{\subst{t}{x}{u}}$$

\paragraph{Convertibility.}
\label{convertibility}
\index{beta-reduction@$\beta$-reduction}\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}\index{delta-reduction@$\delta$-reduction}\index{zeta-reduction@$\zeta$-reduction}

Let us write $\WTEGRED{t}{\triangleright}{u}$ for the contextual closure of the relation $t$ reduces to $u$ in the environment $E$ and context $\Gamma$ with one of the previous reduction $\beta$, $\iota$, $\delta$ or $\zeta$.

We say that two terms $t_1$ and $t_2$ are {\em convertible} (or {\em
  equivalent)} in the environment $E$ and context $\Gamma$ iff there exists a term $u$ such that $\WTEGRED{t_1}{\triangleright \ldots \triangleright}{u}$
and $\WTEGRED{t_2}{\triangleright \ldots \triangleright}{u}$.
We then write $\WTEGCONV{t_1}{t_2}$.

The convertibility relation allows to introduce a new typing rule
which says that two convertible well-formed types have the same
inhabitants.

At the moment, we did not take into account one rule between universes
which says that any term in a universe of index $i$ is also a term in
the universe of index $i+1$. This property is included into the
conversion rule by extending the equivalence relation of
convertibility into an order inductively defined by:
\begin{enumerate}
\item if $\WTEGCONV{t}{u}$ then $\WTEGLECONV{t}{u}$,
\item if $i \leq j$ then $\WTEGLECONV{\Type(i)}{\Type(j)}$,
\item for any $i$, $\WTEGLECONV{\Prop}{\Type(i)}$,
\item for any $i$, $\WTEGLECONV{\Set}{\Type(i)}$,
\item if $\WTEGCONV{T}{U}$ and $\WTELECONV{\Gamma::(x:T)}{T'}{U'}$ then $\WTEGLECONV{\forall~x:T,T'}{\forall~x:U,U'}$.
\end{enumerate}

The conversion rule is now exactly:

\begin{description}\label{Conv}
\item[Conv]\index{Typing rules!Conv}
 \inference{
      \frac{\WTEG{U}{s}~~~~\WTEG{t}{T}~~~~\WTEGLECONV{T}{U}}{\WTEG{t}{U}}}
  \end{description}


\paragraph{$\eta$-conversion.
\label{eta}
\index{eta-conversion@$\eta$-conversion}
\index{eta-reduction@$\eta$-reduction}}

An other important rule is the $\eta$-conversion. It is to identify
terms over a dummy abstraction of a variable followed by an
application of this variable. Let $T$ be a type, $t$ be a term in
which the variable $x$ doesn't occurs free. We have
\[ \WTEGRED{\lb~x:T\mto (t\ x)}{\triangleright}{t} \]
Indeed, as $x$ doesn't occur free in $t$, for any $u$ one
applies to $\lb~x:T\mto (t\ x)$, it $\beta$-reduces to $(t\ u)$. So
$\lb~x:T\mto (t\ x)$ and $t$ can be identified.

\Rem The $\eta$-reduction is not taken into account in the
convertibility rule of \Coq.

\paragraph{Normal form.}\index{Normal form}\label{Normal-form}\label{Head-normal-form}\index{Head normal form}
A term which cannot be any more reduced is said to be in {\em normal
  form}. There are several ways (or strategies) to apply the reduction
rule. Among them, we have to mention the {\em head reduction} which
will play an important role (see chapter \ref{Tactics}). Any term can
be written as $\lb~x_1:T_1\mto \ldots \lb x_k:T_k \mto 
(t_0\ t_1\ldots t_n)$ where
$t_0$ is not an application. We say then that $t_0$ is the {\em head
  of $t$}. If we assume that $t_0$ is $\lb~x:T\mto u_0$ then one step of
$\beta$-head reduction of $t$ is:
\[\lb~x_1:T_1\mto \ldots \lb x_k:T_k\mto (\lb~x:T\mto u_0\ t_1\ldots t_n) 
~\triangleright ~ \lb~(x_1:T_1)\ldots(x_k:T_k)\mto 
(\subst{u_0}{x}{t_1}\ t_2 \ldots t_n)\]
Iterating the process of head reduction until the head of the reduced
term is no more an abstraction leads to the {\em $\beta$-head normal
  form} of $t$:
\[ t \triangleright \ldots \triangleright
\lb~x_1:T_1\mto \ldots\lb x_k:T_k\mto (v\ u_1
\ldots u_m)\]
where $v$ is not an abstraction (nor an application).  Note that the
head normal form must not be confused with the normal form since some
$u_i$ can be reducible.

Similar notions of head-normal forms involving $\delta$, $\iota$ and $\zeta$
reductions or any combination of those can also be defined.

\section{Derived rules for environments}

From the original rules of the type system, one can derive new rules
which change the context of definition of objects in the environment.
Because these rules correspond to elementary operations in the \Coq\ 
engine used in the discharge mechanism at the end of a section, we
state them explicitly.

\paragraph{Mechanism of substitution.}

One rule which can be proved valid, is to replace a term $c$ by its
value in the environment. As we defined the substitution of a term for
a variable in a term, one can define the substitution of a term for a
constant. One easily extends this substitution to contexts and
environments.

\paragraph{Substitution Property:} 
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;\Def{\Gamma}{c}{t}{T}; F}{\Delta}}
           {\WF{E; \subst{F}{c}{t}}{\subst{\Delta}{c}{t}}}}


\paragraph{Abstraction.}

One can modify the context of definition of a constant $c$ by
abstracting a constant with respect to the last variable $x$ of its
defining context. For doing that, we need to check that the constants
appearing in the body of the declaration do not depend on $x$, we need
also to modify the reference to the constant $c$ in the environment
and context by explicitly applying this constant to the variable $x$.
Because of the rules for building environments and terms we know the
variable $x$ is available at each stage where $c$ is mentioned.

\paragraph{Abstracting property:} 
 \inference{\frac{\WF{E; \Def{\Gamma::(x:U)}{c}{t}{T};
       F}{\Delta}~~~~\WFE{\Gamma}}
           {\WF{E;\Def{\Gamma}{c}{\lb~x:U\mto t}{\forall~x:U,T};
  \subst{F}{c}{(c~x)}}{\subst{\Delta}{c}{(c~x)}}}}

\paragraph{Pruning the context.} 
We said the judgment \WFE{\Gamma} means that the defining contexts of
constants in $E$ are included in $\Gamma$. If one abstracts or
substitutes the constants with the above rules then it may happen
that the context $\Gamma$ is now bigger than the one needed for
defining the constants in $E$. Because defining contexts are growing
in $E$, the minimum context needed for defining the constants in $E$
is the same as the one for the last constant. One can consequently
derive the following property.

\paragraph{Pruning property:}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E; \Def{\Delta}{c}{t}{T}}{\Gamma}}
                {\WF{E;\Def{\Delta}{c}{t}{T}}{\Delta}}}


\section{Inductive Definitions}\label{Cic-inductive-definitions}

A (possibly mutual) inductive definition is specified by giving the
names and the type of the inductive sets or families to be
defined and the names and types of the constructors of the inductive
predicates.  An inductive declaration in the environment can
consequently be represented with two contexts (one for inductive
definitions, one for constructors).

Stating the rules for inductive definitions in their general form
needs quite tedious definitions. We shall try to give a concrete
understanding of the rules by precising them on running examples.  We
take as examples the type of natural numbers, the type of
parameterized lists over a type $A$, the relation which states that
a list has some given length and the mutual inductive definition of trees and
forests. 

\subsection{Representing an inductive definition}
\subsubsection{Inductive definitions without parameters}
As for constants, inductive definitions can be defined in a non-empty
context. \\
We write \NInd{\Gamma}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} an inductive
definition valid in a context $\Gamma$, a
context of definitions $\Gamma_I$ and a context of constructors
$\Gamma_C$.
\paragraph{Examples.}
The inductive declaration for the type of natural numbers will be:
\[\NInd{}{\nat:\Set}{\nO:\nat,\nS:\nat\ra\nat}\]
In a context with a variable $A:\Set$, the lists of elements in $A$ is
represented by:
\[\NInd{A:\Set}{\List:\Set}{\Nil:\List,\cons : A \ra \List \ra
  \List}\]
 Assuming 
  $\Gamma_I$ is $[I_1:A_1;\ldots;I_k:A_k]$, and $\Gamma_C$ is
  $[c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n]$, the general typing rules are:

\bigskip
\inference{\frac{\NInd{\Gamma}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} \in E
    ~~j=1\ldots k}{(I_j:A_j) \in E}}

\inference{\frac{\NInd{\Gamma}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} \in E
    ~~~~i=1.. n}
   {(c_i:C_i)\in E}}

\subsubsection{Inductive definitions with parameters}

We have to slightly complicate the representation above in order to handle
the delicate problem of parameters. 
Let us explain that on the example of \List. As they were defined
above, the type \List\ can only be used in an environment where we
have a variable $A:\Set$. Generally one want to consider lists of
elements in different types. For constants this is easily done by abstracting
the value over the parameter. In the case of inductive definitions we
have to handle the abstraction over several objects.

One possible way to do that would be to define the type \List\
inductively as being an inductive family of type $\Set\ra\Set$:
\[\NInd{}{\List:\Set\ra\Set}{\Nil:(A:\Set)(\List~A),\cons : (A:\Set)A
  \ra (\List~A) \ra (\List~A)}\]
There are drawbacks to this point of view. The
information which says that $(\List~\nat)$ is an inductively defined
\Set\ has been lost.
%\footnote{
%The interested reader may look at the compare the above definition with the two 
%following ones which have very different logical meaning:\\
%$\NInd{}{\List:\Set}{\Nil:\List,\cons : (A:\Set)A
%  \ra \List \ra \List}$ \\
%$\NInd{}{\List:\Set\ra\Set}{\Nil:(A:\Set)(\List~A),\cons : (A:\Set)A
%  \ra (\List~A\ra A) \ra (\List~A)}$.}

In the system, we keep track in the syntax of the context of
parameters. The idea of these parameters is that they can be
instantiated and still we have an inductive definition for which we
know the specification.

Formally the representation of an inductive declaration
will be 
\Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} for an inductive
definition valid in a context $\Gamma$ with parameters $\Gamma_P$, a
context of definitions $\Gamma_I$ and a context of constructors
$\Gamma_C$.
The occurrences of the variables of $\Gamma_P$ in the contexts
$\Gamma_I$ and $\Gamma_C$ are bound.

The definition \Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} will be
well-formed exactly when \NInd{\Gamma,\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} is.
If $\Gamma_P$ is $[p_1:P_1;\ldots;p_r:P_r]$, an object in 
\Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} applied to $q_1,\ldots,q_r$
will behave as the corresponding object of 
\NInd{\Gamma}{\substs{\Gamma_I}{p_i}{q_i}{i=1..r}}{\substs{\Gamma_C}{p_i}{q_i}{i=1..r}}.

\paragraph{Examples}
The declaration for parameterized lists is:
\[\Ind{}{A:\Set}{\List:\Set}{\Nil:\List,\cons : A \ra \List \ra
  \List}\]

The declaration for the length of lists is:
\[\Ind{}{A:\Set}{\Length:(\List~A)\ra \nat\ra\Prop}
      {\LNil:(\Length~(\Nil~A)~\nO),\\ 
     \LCons :\forall a:A, \forall l:(\List~A),\forall n:\nat, (\Length~l~n)\ra (\Length~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~n))}\]

The declaration for a mutual inductive definition of forests and trees is:
\[\NInd{}{\tree:\Set,\forest:\Set}
      {\\~~\node:\forest \ra \tree,
       \emptyf:\forest,\consf:\tree \ra \forest \ra \forest\-}\]
  
These representations are the ones obtained as the result of the \Coq\ 
declaration:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive nat : Set :=
  | O : nat
  | S : nat -> nat.
Inductive list (A:Set) : Set :=
  | nil : list A
  | cons : A -> list A -> list A.
\end{coq_example*}
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive Length (A:Set) : list A -> nat -> Prop :=
  | Lnil : Length A (nil A) O
  | Lcons :
      forall (a:A) (l:list A) (n:nat),
        Length A l n -> Length A (cons A a l) (S n).
Inductive tree : Set :=
    node : forest -> tree
with forest : Set :=
  | emptyf : forest
  | consf : tree -> forest -> forest.
\end{coq_example*}
The inductive declaration in \Coq\ is slightly different from the one
we described theoretically. The difference is that in the type of
constructors the inductive definition is explicitly applied to the
parameters variables. The \Coq\ type-checker verifies that all
parameters are applied in the correct manner in each recursive call.
In particular, the following definition will not be accepted because 
there is an occurrence of \List\ which is not applied to the parameter
variable:
\begin{coq_eval}
Set Printing Depth 50.
(********** The following is not correct and should produce **********)
(********* Error: The 1st argument of list' must be A in ... *********)
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example}
Inductive list' (A:Set) : Set :=
  | nil' : list' A
  | cons' : A -> list' (A -> A) -> list' A.
\end{coq_example}

\subsection{Types of inductive objects}
We have to give the type of constants in an environment $E$ which
contains an inductive declaration.

\begin{description}
\item[Ind-Const] Assuming $\Gamma_P$ is $[p_1:P_1;\ldots;p_r:P_r]$,
  $\Gamma_I$ is $[I_1:A_1;\ldots;I_k:A_k]$, and $\Gamma_C$ is
  $[c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n]$,
   
\inference{\frac{\Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} \in E
    ~~j=1\ldots k}{(I_j:\forall~p_1:P_1,\ldots\forall p_r:P_r,A_j) \in E}}

\inference{\frac{\Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} \in E
    ~~~~i=1.. n}
   {(c_i:\forall~p_1:P_1,\ldots \forall p_r:P_r,\subst{C_i}{I_j}{(I_j~p_1\ldots
       p_r)}_{j=1\ldots k})\in E}}
\end{description}

\paragraph{Example.}
We have $(\List:\Set \ra \Set), (\cons:\forall~A:\Set,A\ra(\List~A)\ra
(\List~A))$, \\ 
$(\Length:\forall~A:\Set, (\List~A)\ra\nat\ra\Prop)$, $\tree:\Set$ and $\forest:\Set$.

From now on, we write $\ListA$ instead of $(\List~A)$ and $\LengthA$
for $(\Length~A)$.

%\paragraph{Parameters.}
%%The parameters introduce a distortion between the inside specification
%%of the inductive declaration where parameters are supposed to be
%%instantiated (this representation is appropriate for checking the
%%correctness or deriving the destructor principle) and the outside
%%typing rules where the inductive objects are seen as objects
%%abstracted with respect to the parameters.

%In the definition of \List\ or \Length\, $A$ is a parameter because
%what is effectively inductively defined is $\ListA$ or $\LengthA$ for
%a given $A$ which is constant in the type of constructors.  But when
%we define $(\LengthA~l~n)$, $l$ and $n$ are not parameters because the
%constructors manipulate different instances of this family.

\subsection{Well-formed inductive definitions}
We cannot accept any inductive declaration because some of them lead
to inconsistent systems. We restrict ourselves to definitions which
satisfy a syntactic criterion of positivity. Before giving the formal
rules, we need a few definitions:

\paragraph{Definitions}\index{Positivity}\label{Positivity}

A type $T$ is an {\em arity of sort $s$}\index{Arity} if it converts
to the sort $s$ or to a product $\forall~x:T,U$ with $U$ an arity
of sort $s$. (For instance $A\ra \Set$ or $\forall~A:\Prop,A\ra
\Prop$ are arities of sort respectively \Set\ and \Prop).  A {\em type
  of constructor of $I$}\index{Type of constructor} is either a term
$(I~t_1\ldots ~t_n)$ or $\fa x:T,C$ with $C$ a {\em type of constructor
  of $I$}.

\smallskip

The type of constructor $T$ will be said to {\em satisfy the positivity
condition} for a constant $X$ in the following cases:

\begin{itemize}
\item $T=(X~t_1\ldots ~t_n)$ and $X$ does not occur free in
any $t_i$
\item $T=\forall~x:U,V$ and $X$ occurs only strictly positively in $U$ and
the type $V$ satisfies the positivity condition for $X$
\end{itemize}

The constant $X$ {\em occurs strictly positively} in $T$ in the
following cases:

\begin{itemize}
\item $X$ does not occur in $T$
\item $T$ converts to $(X~t_1 \ldots ~t_n)$ and $X$ does not occur in
  any of $t_i$
\item $T$ converts to $\forall~x:U,V$ and $X$ does not occur in
  type $U$ but occurs strictly positively in type $V$
\item $T$ converts to $(I~a_1 \ldots ~a_m ~ t_1 \ldots ~t_p)$ where
  $I$ is the name of an inductive declaration of the form
  $\Ind{\Gamma}{p_1:P_1;\ldots;p_m:P_m}{I:A}{c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n}$
  (in particular, it is not mutually defined and it has $m$
  parameters) and $X$ does not occur in any of the $t_i$, and the
  types of constructor $C_i\{p_j/a_j\}_{j=1\ldots m}$ of $I$ satisfy
  the nested positivity condition for $X$
%\item more generally, when $T$ is not a type, $X$ occurs strictly
%positively in $T[x:U]u$ if $X$ does not occur in $U$ but occurs
%strictly positively in $u$
\end{itemize}

The type of constructor $T$ of $I$ {\em satisfies the nested
positivity condition} for a constant $X$ in the following
cases:

\begin{itemize}
\item $T=(I~t_1\ldots ~t_n)$ and $X$ does not occur in
any $t_i$
\item $T=\forall~x:U,V$ and $X$ occurs only strictly positively in $U$ and
the type $V$ satisfies the nested positivity condition for $X$
\end{itemize}

\paragraph{Example}

$X$ occurs strictly positively in $A\ra X$ or $X*A$ or $({\tt list}
X)$ but not in $X \ra A$ or $(X \ra A)\ra A$ nor $({\tt neg}~A)$
assuming the notion of product and lists were already defined and {\tt
  neg} is an inductive definition with declaration \Ind{}{A:\Set}{{\tt
    neg}:\Set}{{\tt neg}:(A\ra{\tt False}) \ra {\tt neg}}.  Assuming
$X$ has arity ${\tt nat \ra Prop}$ and {\tt ex} is the inductively
defined existential quantifier, the occurrence of $X$ in ${\tt (ex~
  nat~ \lb~n:nat\mto (X~ n))}$ is also strictly positive.

\paragraph{Correctness rules.}
We shall now describe the rules allowing the introduction of a new
inductive definition.

\begin{description}
\item[W-Ind] Let $E$ be an environment and
  $\Gamma,\Gamma_P,\Gamma_I,\Gamma_C$ are contexts such that
  $\Gamma_I$ is $[I_1:A_1;\ldots;I_k:A_k]$ and $\Gamma_C$ is
  $[c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n]$. 
\inference{
  \frac{
  (\WTE{\Gamma;\Gamma_P}{A_j}{s'_j})_{j=1\ldots  k}
  ~~ (\WTE{\Gamma;\Gamma_P;\Gamma_I}{C_i}{s_{p_i}})_{i=1\ldots  n}
}
  {\WF{E;\Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}}{\Gamma}}}
providing the following side conditions hold:
\begin{itemize}
\item $k>0$, $I_j$, $c_i$ are different names for $j=1\ldots  k$ and $i=1\ldots  n$,
\item for $j=1\ldots  k$ we have $A_j$ is an arity of sort $s_j$ and $I_j
  \notin \Gamma \cup E$,
\item for $i=1\ldots  n$ we have $C_i$ is a type of constructor of
  $I_{p_i}$ which satisfies the positivity condition for $I_1 \ldots  I_k$
  and $c_i \notin \Gamma \cup E$.
\end{itemize}
\end{description}
One can remark that there is a constraint between the sort of the
arity of the inductive type and the sort of the type of its
constructors which will always be satisfied for the impredicative sort
(\Prop) but may fail to define inductive definition 
on sort \Set{} and generate constraints between universes for
inductive definitions in types.

\paragraph{Examples}
It is well known that existential quantifier can be encoded as an
inductive definition.
The following declaration introduces the second-order existential
quantifier $\exists X.P(X)$.
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive exProp (P:Prop->Prop) : Prop 
  := exP_intro : forall X:Prop, P X -> exProp P.
\end{coq_example*}
The same definition on \Set{} is not allowed and fails~:
\begin{coq_eval}
(********** The following is not correct and should produce **********)
(*** Error: Large non-propositional inductive types must be in Type***)
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example}
Inductive exSet (P:Set->Prop) : Set 
  := exS_intro : forall X:Set, P X -> exSet P.
\end{coq_example}
It is possible to declare the same inductive definition in the
universe \Type. 
The \texttt{exType} inductive definition has type  $(\Type_i \ra\Prop)\ra
\Type_j$ with the constraint that the parameter \texttt{X} of \texttt{exT\_intro} has type $\Type_k$ with $k<j$ and $k\leq i$.
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive exType (P:Type->Prop) : Type
  := exT_intro : forall X:Type, P X -> exType P.
\end{coq_example*}
%We shall assume for the following definitions that, if necessary, we
%annotated the type of constructors such that we know if the argument
%is recursive or not.  We shall write the type $(x:_R T)C$ if it is 
%a recursive argument and $(x:_P T)C$ if the argument is not recursive.

\subsection{Destructors}
The specification of inductive definitions with arities and
constructors is quite natural.  But we still have to say how to use an
object in an inductive type.

This problem is rather delicate. There are actually several different
ways to do that. Some of them are logically equivalent but not always
equivalent from the computational point of view or from the user point
of view.

From the computational point of view, we want to be able to define a
function whose domain is an inductively defined type by using a
combination of case analysis over the possible constructors of the
object and recursion.

Because we need to keep a consistent theory and also we prefer to keep
a strongly normalizing reduction, we cannot accept any sort of
recursion (even terminating). So the basic idea is to restrict
ourselves to primitive recursive functions and functionals.

For instance, assuming a parameter $A:\Set$ exists in the context, we
want to build a function \length\ of type $\ListA\ra \nat$ which
computes the length of the list, so such that $(\length~\Nil) = \nO$
and $(\length~(\cons~A~a~l)) = (\nS~(\length~l))$.  We want these
equalities to be recognized implicitly and taken into account in the
conversion rule.

From the logical point of view, we have built a type family by giving
a set of constructors.  We want to capture the fact that we do not
have any other way to build an object in this type. So when trying to
prove a property $(P~m)$ for $m$ in an inductive definition it is
enough to enumerate all the cases where $m$ starts with a different
constructor.

In case the inductive definition is effectively a recursive one, we
want to capture the extra property that we have built the smallest
fixed point of this recursive equation.  This says that we are only
manipulating finite objects. This analysis provides induction
principles.

For instance, in order to prove $\forall l:\ListA,(\LengthA~l~(\length~l))$
it is enough to prove:

\noindent $(\LengthA~\Nil~(\length~\Nil))$ and

\smallskip
$\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, (\LengthA~l~(\length~l)) \ra
(\LengthA~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\length~(\cons~A~a~l)))$.
\smallskip

\noindent which given the conversion equalities satisfied by \length\ is the
same as proving:
$(\LengthA~\Nil~\nO)$ and $\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, 
(\LengthA~l~(\length~l)) \ra
(\LengthA~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~(\length~l)))$.

One conceptually simple way to do that, following the basic scheme
proposed by Martin-L\"of in his Intuitionistic Type Theory, is to
introduce for each inductive definition an elimination operator. At
the logical level it is a proof of the usual induction principle and
at the computational level it implements a generic operator for doing
primitive recursion over the structure.

But this operator is rather tedious to implement and use. We choose in
this version of Coq to factorize the operator for primitive recursion
into two more primitive operations as was first suggested by Th. Coquand
in~\cite{Coq92}.  One is the definition by pattern-matching. The second one is a definition by guarded fixpoints. 

\subsubsection{The {\tt match\ldots with \ldots end} construction.}
\label{Caseexpr}
\index{match@{\tt match\ldots with\ldots end}}

The basic idea of this destructor operation is that we have an object
$m$ in an inductive type $I$ and we want to prove a property $(P~m)$
which in general depends on $m$. For this, it is enough to prove the
property for $m = (c_i~u_1\ldots  u_{p_i})$ for each constructor of $I$.

The \Coq{} term for this proof will be written~:
\[\kw{match}~m~\kw{with}~ (c_1~x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1}) \Ra f_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
  (c_n~x_{n1}...x_{np_n}) \Ra f_n~ \kw{end}\]
In this expression, if
$m$ is a term built from a constructor $(c_i~u_1\ldots u_{p_i})$ then
the expression will behave as it is specified with $i$-th branch and
will reduce to $f_i$ where the $x_{i1}$\ldots $x_{ip_i}$ are replaced
by the $u_1\ldots u_p$ according to the $\iota$-reduction.

Actually, for type-checking a \kw{match\ldots with\ldots end}
expression we also need to know the predicate $P$ to be proved by case
analysis.  \Coq{} can sometimes infer this predicate but sometimes
not. The concrete syntax for describing this predicate uses the
\kw{as\ldots return} construction. 
The predicate is made explicit using the syntax~:
\[\kw{match}~m~\kw{as}~ x~ \kw{return}~ (P~ x) ~\kw{with}~ (c_1~x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1}) \Ra f_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
  (c_n~x_{n1}...x_{np_n}) \Ra f_n \kw{end}\]
For the purpose of presenting the inference rules, we use a more
compact notation~:
\[ \Case{(\lb x \mto P)}{m}{ \lb x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1} \mto f_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
  \lb x_{n1}...x_{np_n} \mto f_n}\]

This is the basic idea which is generalized to the case where $I$ is
an inductively defined $n$-ary relation (in which case the property
$P$ to be proved will be a $n+1$-ary relation).


\paragraph{Non-dependent elimination.}
When defining a function by case analysis, we build an object of type $I
\ra C$ and the minimality principle on an inductively defined logical
predicate of type $A \ra \Prop$ is often used to prove a property
$\forall x:A,(I~x)\ra (C~x)$.  This is a particular case of the dependent
principle that we stated before with a predicate which does not depend
explicitly on the object in the inductive definition.

For instance, a function testing whether a list is empty 
can be
defined as:

\[\lb~l:\ListA \mto\Case{\bool}{l}{\Nil~ \Ra~\true~ |~ (\cons~a~m)~ \Ra~\false}\]
%\noindent {\bf Remark. } 

% In the system \Coq\ the expression above, can be
% written without mentioning
% the dummy abstraction:
% \Case{\bool}{l}{\Nil~ \mbox{\tt =>}~\true~ |~ (\cons~a~m)~
%  \mbox{\tt =>}~ \false}

\paragraph{Allowed elimination sorts.}
\index{Elimination sorts}

An important question for building the typing rule for \kw{match} is
what can be the type of $P$ with respect to the type of the inductive
definitions.

We define now a relation \compat{I:A}{B} between an inductive
definition $I$ of type $A$, an arity $B$ which says that an object in
the inductive definition $I$ can be eliminated for proving a property
$P$ of type $B$.

The case of inductive definitions in sorts \Set\ or \Type{} is simple.
There is no restriction on the sort of the predicate to be
eliminated. 

\paragraph{Notations.}
The \compat{I:A}{B} is defined as the smallest relation satisfying the
following rules:
We write \compat{I}{B} for \compat{I:A}{B} where $A$ is the type of
$I$.

\begin{description}
\item[Prod] \inference{\frac{\compat{(I~x):A'}{B'}}
                      {\compat{I:(x:A)A'}{(x:A)B'}}}
\item[\Set \& \Type] \inference{\frac{
    s_1 \in \{\Set,\Type(j)\}, 
    s_2 \in \Sort}{\compat{I:s_1}{I\ra s_2}}}
\end{description}

The case of Inductive Definitions of sort \Prop{} is a bit more
complicated, because of our interpretation of this sort. The only
harmless allowed elimination, is the one when predicate $P$ is also of
sort \Prop.
\begin{description}
\item[\Prop] \inference{\compat{I:\Prop}{I\ra\Prop}}
\end{description}
\Prop{} is the type of logical propositions, the proofs of properties
$P$ in \Prop{} could not be used for computation and are consequently
ignored by the extraction mechanism.
Assume $A$ and $B$ are two propositions, and the logical disjunction
$A\vee B$ is defined inductively by~:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive or (A B:Prop) : Prop :=
  lintro : A -> or A B | rintro : B -> or A B.
\end{coq_example*}
The following definition which computes a boolean value by case over
the proof of \texttt{or A B} is not accepted~:
\begin{coq_eval}
(***************************************************************)
(*** This example should fail with ``Incorrect elimination'' ***)
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example}
Definition choice (A B: Prop) (x:or A B) := 
   match x with lintro a => true | rintro b => false end.
\end{coq_example}
From the computational point of view, the structure of the proof of
\texttt{(or A B)} in this term is needed for computing the boolean
value.

In general, if $I$ has type \Prop\ then $P$ cannot have type $I\ra
\Set$, because it will mean to build an informative proof of type
$(P~m)$ doing a case analysis over a non-computational object that
will disappear in the extracted program.  But the other way is safe
with respect to our interpretation we can have $I$ a computational
object and $P$ a non-computational one, it just corresponds to proving
a logical property of a computational object.

% Also if $I$ is in one of the sorts \{\Prop, \Set\}, one cannot in
% general allow an elimination over a bigger sort such as \Type.  But
% this operation is safe whenever $I$ is a {\em small inductive} type,
% which means that all the types of constructors of
% $I$ are small with the following definition:\\
% $(I~t_1\ldots t_s)$ is a {\em small type of constructor} and
% $\forall~x:T,C$ is a small type of constructor if $C$ is and if $T$
% has type \Prop\ or \Set.  \index{Small inductive type}

% We call this particular elimination which gives the possibility to
% compute a type by induction on the structure of a term, a {\em strong
%   elimination}\index{Strong elimination}.

In the same spirit, elimination on $P$ of type $I\ra
\Type$ cannot be allowed because it trivially implies the elimination
on $P$ of type $I\ra \Set$ by cumulativity. It also implies that there
is two proofs of the same property which are provably different,
contradicting the proof-irrelevance property which is sometimes a
useful axiom~:
\begin{coq_example}
Axiom proof_irrelevance : forall (P : Prop) (x y : P), x=y.
\end{coq_example}
\begin{coq_eval}
Reset proof_irrelevance.
\end{coq_eval}
The elimination of an inductive definition of type \Prop\ on a
predicate $P$ of type $I\ra \Type$ leads to a paradox when applied to 
impredicative inductive definition like the second-order existential
quantifier \texttt{exProp} defined above, because it give access to
the two projections on this type.

%\paragraph{Warning: strong elimination}
%\index{Elimination!Strong elimination}
%In previous versions of Coq, for a small inductive definition, only the
%non-informative strong elimination on \Type\ was allowed, because
%strong elimination on \Typeset\ was not compatible with the current
%extraction procedure. In this version, strong elimination on \Typeset\
%is accepted but a dummy element is extracted from it and may generate
%problems if extracted terms are explicitly used such as in the 
%{\tt Program} tactic or when extracting ML programs.

\paragraph{Empty and singleton elimination}
\index{Elimination!Singleton elimination}
\index{Elimination!Empty elimination}

There are special inductive definitions in \Prop\ for which more
eliminations are allowed. 
\begin{description}
\item[\Prop-extended] 
\inference{
   \frac{I \mbox{~is an empty or singleton
       definition}~~~s\in\Sort}{\compat{I:\Prop}{I\ra s}}
}
\end{description}

% A {\em singleton definition} has always an informative content,
% even if it is a proposition.

A {\em singleton
definition} has only one constructor and all the arguments of this
constructor have type \Prop. In that case, there is a canonical
way to interpret the informative extraction on an object in that type,
such that the elimination on any sort $s$ is legal.  Typical examples are
the conjunction of non-informative propositions and the equality. 
If there is an hypothesis $h:a=b$ in the context, it can be used for
rewriting not only in logical propositions but also in any type.
% In that case, the term \verb!eq_rec! which was defined as an axiom, is
% now a term of the calculus.
\begin{coq_example}
Print eq_rec.
Extraction eq_rec.
\end{coq_example}
An empty definition has no constructors, in that case also,
elimination on any sort is allowed.

\paragraph{Type of branches.}
Let $c$ be a term of type $C$, we assume $C$ is a type of constructor
for an inductive definition $I$. Let $P$ be a term that represents the
property to be proved.
We assume $r$ is the number of parameters.

We define a new type \CI{c:C}{P} which represents the type of the
branch corresponding to the $c:C$ constructor.
\[
\begin{array}{ll}
\CI{c:(I_i~p_1\ldots p_r\ t_1 \ldots t_p)}{P} &\equiv (P~t_1\ldots ~t_p~c) \\[2mm]
\CI{c:\forall~x:T,C}{P} &\equiv \forall~x:T,\CI{(c~x):C}{P} 
\end{array}
\]
We write \CI{c}{P} for \CI{c:C}{P} with $C$ the type of $c$.

\paragraph{Examples.}
For $\ListA$ the type of $P$ will be $\ListA\ra s$ for $s \in \Sort$. \\ 
$ \CI{(\cons~A)}{P} \equiv
\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA,(P~(\cons~A~a~l))$.

For $\LengthA$, the type of $P$ will be
$\forall l:\ListA,\forall n:\nat, (\LengthA~l~n)\ra \Prop$ and the expression
\CI{(\LCons~A)}{P} is defined as:\\ 
$\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat, \forall
h:(\LengthA~l~n), (P~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~n)~(\LCons~A~a~l~n~l))$.\\ 
If $P$ does not depend on its third argument, we find the more natural
expression:\\ 
$\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat,
(\LengthA~l~n)\ra(P~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~n))$.

\paragraph{Typing rule.}

Our very general destructor for inductive definition enjoys the
following typing rule
% , where we write 
% \[
% \Case{P}{c}{[x_{11}:T_{11}]\ldots[x_{1p_1}:T_{1p_1}]g_1\ldots
%   [x_{n1}:T_{n1}]\ldots[x_{np_n}:T_{np_n}]g_n}
% \]
% for 
% \[
% \Case{P}{c}{(c_1~x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1}) \Ra g_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
% (c_n~x_{n1}...x_{np_n}) \Ra g_n }
% \]

\begin{description}
\item[match] \label{elimdep} \index{Typing rules!match}
\inference{
\frac{\WTEG{c}{(I~q_1\ldots  q_r~t_1\ldots  t_s)}~~
  \WTEG{P}{B}~~\compat{(I~q_1\ldots  q_r)}{B}
 ~~
(\WTEG{f_i}{\CI{(c_{p_i}~q_1\ldots  q_r)}{P}})_{i=1\ldots  l}}
{\WTEG{\Case{P}{c}{f_1\ldots  f_l}}{(P\ t_1\ldots  t_s\ c)}}}%\\[3mm]

provided $I$ is an inductive type in a declaration
\Ind{\Delta}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} with $|\Gamma_P| = r$,
$\Gamma_C = [c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n]$ and $c_{p_1}\ldots  c_{p_l}$ are the
only constructors of $I$.
\end{description}

\paragraph{Example.}
For \List\ and \Length\ the typing rules for the {\tt match} expression
are (writing just $t:M$ instead of \WTEG{t}{M}, the environment and
context being the same in all the judgments).

\[\frac{l:\ListA~~P:\ListA\ra s~~~f_1:(P~(\Nil~A))~~
      f_2:\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, (P~(\cons~A~a~l))}
    {\Case{P}{l}{f_1~f_2}:(P~l)}\]

\[\frac{
     \begin{array}[b]{@{}c@{}} 
H:(\LengthA~L~N) \\ P:\forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat, (\LengthA~l~n)\ra
  \Prop\\
 f_1:(P~(\Nil~A)~\nO~\LNil) \\
   f_2:\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat, \forall
  h:(\LengthA~l~n), (P~(\cons~A~a~n)~(\nS~n)~(\LCons~A~a~l~n~h)) 
      \end{array}}
    {\Case{P}{H}{f_1~f_2}:(P~L~N~H)}\]

\paragraph{Definition of $\iota$-reduction.}\label{iotared}
\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}
We still have to define the $\iota$-reduction in the general case.

A $\iota$-redex is a term of the following form:
\[\Case{P}{(c_{p_i}~q_1\ldots  q_r~a_1\ldots  a_m)}{f_1\ldots 
    f_l}\]
with $c_{p_i}$ the $i$-th constructor of the inductive type $I$ with $r$
parameters.

The $\iota$-contraction of this term is $(f_i~a_1\ldots a_m)$ leading
to the general reduction rule:
\[ \Case{P}{(c_{p_i}~q_1\ldots  q_r~a_1\ldots  a_m)}{f_1\ldots 
    f_n} \triangleright_{\iota} (f_i~a_1\ldots a_m) \]

\subsection{Fixpoint definitions}
\label{Fix-term} \index{Fix@{\tt Fix}}
The second operator for elimination is fixpoint definition. 
This fixpoint may involve several mutually recursive definitions.
The basic concrete syntax for a recursive set of mutually recursive 
declarations is (with $\Gamma_i$ contexts)~: 
\[\kw{fix}~f_1 (\Gamma_1) :A_1:=t_1~\kw{with} \ldots \kw{with}~ f_n
(\Gamma_n) :A_n:=t_n\]
The terms are obtained by projections from this set of declarations
and are written 
\[\kw{fix}~f_1 (\Gamma_1) :A_1:=t_1~\kw{with} \ldots \kw{with}~ f_n
(\Gamma_n) :A_n:=t_n~\kw{for}~f_i\]
In the inference rules, we represent such a
term by 
\[\Fix{f_i}{f_1:A_1':=t_1' \ldots f_n:A_n':=t_n'}\]
with $t_i'$ (resp. $A_i'$) representing the term $t_i$ abstracted
(resp. generalized) with
respect to the bindings in the context $\Gamma_i$, namely
$t_i'=\lb \Gamma_i \mto t_i$ and $A_i'=\forall \Gamma_i, A_i$.

\subsubsection{Typing rule}
The typing rule is the expected one for a fixpoint.

\begin{description}
\item[Fix] \index{Typing rules!Fix}
\inference{\frac{(\WTEG{A_i}{s_i})_{i=1\ldots n}~~~~
            (\WTE{\Gamma,f_1:A_1,\ldots,f_n:A_n}{t_i}{A_i})_{i=1\ldots n}}
         {\WTEG{\Fix{f_i}{f_1:A_1:=t_1 \ldots f_n:A_n:=t_n}}{A_i}}}
\end{description}

Any fixpoint definition cannot be accepted because non-normalizing terms
will lead to proofs of absurdity.

The basic scheme of recursion that should be allowed is the one needed for 
defining primitive
recursive functionals. In that case the fixpoint enjoys a special
syntactic restriction, namely one of the arguments belongs to an
inductive type, the function starts with a case analysis and recursive
calls are done on variables coming from patterns and representing subterms.

For instance in the case of natural numbers, a proof of the induction
principle of type 
\[\forall P:\nat\ra\Prop, (P~\nO)\ra((n:\nat)(P~n)\ra(P~(\nS~n)))\ra
\forall n:\nat, (P~n)\]
can be represented by the term:
\[\begin{array}{l}
\lb P:\nat\ra\Prop\mto\lb f:(P~\nO)\mto \lb g:(\forall n:\nat,
(P~n)\ra(P~(\nS~n))) \mto\\
\Fix{h}{h:\forall n:\nat, (P~n):=\lb n:\nat\mto \Case{P}{n}{f~\lb
    p:\nat\mto (g~p~(h~p))}}
\end{array}
\]

Before accepting a fixpoint definition as being correctly typed, we
check that the definition is ``guarded''. A precise analysis of this
notion can be found in~\cite{Gim94}.

The first stage is to precise on which argument the fixpoint will be
decreasing. The type of this argument should be an inductive
definition.

For doing this the syntax of fixpoints is extended and becomes 
 \[\Fix{f_i}{f_1/k_1:A_1:=t_1 \ldots f_n/k_n:A_n:=t_n}\]
where $k_i$ are positive integers.
Each $A_i$ should be a type (reducible to a term) starting with at least
$k_i$ products $\forall y_1:B_1,\ldots \forall y_{k_i}:B_{k_i}, A'_i$ 
and $B_{k_i}$
being an instance of an inductive definition.

Now in the definition $t_i$, if $f_j$ occurs then it should be applied
to at least $k_j$ arguments and the $k_j$-th argument should be
syntactically recognized as structurally smaller than $y_{k_i}$


The definition of being structurally smaller is a bit technical.
One needs first to  define the notion of 
{\em recursive arguments of a constructor}\index{Recursive arguments}.
For an inductive definition \Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C},
the type of a constructor $c$ have the form
$\forall p_1:P_1,\ldots \forall p_r:P_r, 
\forall x_1:T_1, \ldots \forall x_r:T_r, (I_j~p_1\ldots 
p_r~t_1\ldots  t_s)$ the recursive arguments will correspond to $T_i$ in
which one of the $I_l$ occurs.


The main rules for being structurally smaller are the following:\\
Given a variable $y$ of type an inductive
definition in a declaration 
\Ind{\Gamma}{\Gamma_P}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
where $\Gamma_I$ is $[I_1:A_1;\ldots;I_k:A_k]$, and $\Gamma_C$ is
  $[c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n]$.
The terms structurally smaller than $y$ are:
\begin{itemize}
\item $(t~u), \lb x:u \mto t$ when $t$ is structurally smaller than $y$ .
\item \Case{P}{c}{f_1\ldots f_n} when each $f_i$ is structurally
  smaller than $y$. \\
  If $c$ is $y$ or is structurally smaller than $y$, its type is an inductive
  definition $I_p$ part of the inductive
  declaration corresponding to $y$. 
  Each $f_i$ corresponds to a type of constructor $C_q \equiv
  \forall y_1:B_1, \ldots \forall y_k:B_k, (I~a_1\ldots a_k)$ 
  and can consequently be
  written $\lb y_1:B'_1\mto \ldots \lb y_k:B'_k\mto g_i$.
  ($B'_i$ is obtained from $B_i$ by substituting parameters variables)
  the variables $y_j$ occurring
  in $g_i$ corresponding to recursive arguments $B_i$ (the ones in
  which one of the $I_l$ occurs) are structurally smaller than $y$.
\end{itemize}
The following definitions are correct, we enter them using the
{\tt Fixpoint} command as described in section~\ref{Fixpoint} and show
the internal representation.
\begin{coq_example}
Fixpoint plus (n m:nat) {struct n} : nat :=
  match n with
  | O => m
  | S p => S (plus p m)
  end.
Print plus.
Fixpoint lgth (A:Set) (l:list A) {struct l} : nat :=
  match l with
  | nil => O
  | cons a l' => S (lgth A l')
  end.
Print lgth.
Fixpoint sizet (t:tree) : nat := let (f) := t in S (sizef f)
 with sizef (f:forest) : nat :=
  match f with
  | emptyf => O
  | consf t f => plus (sizet t) (sizef f)
  end.
Print sizet.
\end{coq_example}


\subsubsection{Reduction rule}
\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}
Let $F$ be the set of declarations: $f_1/k_1:A_1:=t_1 \ldots
f_n/k_n:A_n:=t_n$.
The reduction for fixpoints is:
\[ (\Fix{f_i}{F}~a_1\ldots
a_{k_i}) \triangleright_{\iota} \substs{t_i}{f_k}{\Fix{f_k}{F}}{k=1\ldots n}\]
when $a_{k_i}$ starts with a constructor.
This last restriction is needed in order to keep strong normalization
and corresponds to the reduction for primitive recursive operators.

We can illustrate this behavior on examples.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall n m:nat, plus (S n) m = S (plus n m).
reflexivity.
Abort.
Goal forall f:forest, sizet (node f) = S (sizef f).
reflexivity.
Abort.
\end{coq_example}
But assuming the definition of a son function from \tree\ to \forest:
\begin{coq_example}
Definition sont (t:tree) : forest 
   := let (f) := t in f.
\end{coq_example}
The following is not a conversion but can be proved after a case analysis.
\begin{coq_eval}
(******************************************************************)
(** Error: Impossible to unify ....                              **)
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall t:tree, sizet t = S (sizef (sont t)).
reflexivity. (** this one fails **)
destruct t.
reflexivity.
\end{coq_example}
\begin{coq_eval}
Abort.
\end{coq_eval}

% La disparition de Program devrait rendre la construction Match obsolete
% \subsubsection{The {\tt Match \ldots with \ldots end} expression}
% \label{Matchexpr}
% %\paragraph{A unary {\tt Match\ldots with \ldots end}.}
% \index{Match...with...end@{\tt Match \ldots with \ldots end}}
% The {\tt Match} operator which was a primitive notion in older
% presentations of the Calculus of Inductive Constructions is now just a
% macro definition which generates the good combination of {\tt Case}
% and {\tt Fix} operators in order to generate an operator for primitive
% recursive definitions. It always considers an inductive definition as 
% a single inductive definition.

% The following examples illustrates this feature.
% \begin{coq_example}
% Definition nat_pr : (C:Set)C->(nat->C->C)->nat->C 
%   :=[C,x,g,n]Match n with x g end.
% Print nat_pr.
% \end{coq_example}
% \begin{coq_example}
% Definition forest_pr 
%   : (C:Set)C->(tree->forest->C->C)->forest->C
%   := [C,x,g,n]Match n with x g end.
% \end{coq_example}

% Cet exemple faisait error (HH le 12/12/96), j'ai change pour une
% version plus simple
%\begin{coq_example}
%Definition forest_pr 
%  : (P:forest->Set)(P emptyf)->((t:tree)(f:forest)(P f)->(P (consf t f)))
%    ->(f:forest)(P f)
%  := [C,x,g,n]Match n with x g end.
%\end{coq_example}

\subsubsection{Mutual induction}

The principles of mutual induction can be automatically generated 
using the {\tt Scheme} command described in section~\ref{Scheme}.

\section{Coinductive types}
The implementation contains also coinductive definitions, which are
types inhabited by infinite objects. 
More information on coinductive definitions can be found
in~\cite{Gimenez95b,Gim98}.
%They are described inchapter~\ref{Coinductives}.

\section{\iCIC : the Calculus of Inductive Construction with
  impredicative \Set}\label{impredicativity}

\Coq{} can be used as a type-checker for \iCIC{}, the original 
Calculus of Inductive Constructions with an impredicative sort \Set{}
by using the compiler option \texttt{-impredicative-set}.

For example, using the ordinary \texttt{coqtop} command, the following
is rejected.
\begin{coq_eval}
(** This example should fail *******************************
    Error: The term forall X:Set, X -> X has type Type
    while it is expected to have type Set
***)
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example}
Definition id: Set := forall X:Set,X->X.
\end{coq_example}
while it will type-check, if one use instead the \texttt{coqtop
  -impredicative-set} command.

The major change in the theory concerns the rule for product formation
in the sort \Set, which is extended to a domain in any sort~:
\begin{description}
\item [Prod]  \index{Typing rules!Prod (impredicative Set)}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s\in\Sort~~~~~~
    \WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Set}}
      { \WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Set}}} 
\end{description}
This extension has consequences on the inductive definitions which are
allowed. 
In the impredicative system, one can build so-called {\em large inductive
  definitions} like the example of second-order existential
quantifier (\texttt{exSet}).

There should be restrictions on the eliminations which can be
performed on such definitions. The eliminations rules in the
impredicative system for sort \Set{} become~:
\begin{description}
\item[\Set] \inference{\frac{s \in
      \{\Prop, \Set\}}{\compat{I:\Set}{I\ra s}}
~~~~\frac{I \mbox{~is a small inductive definition}~~~~s \in
      \{\Type(i)\}}
         {\compat{I:\Set}{I\ra s}}}
\end{description}
     


% $Id: RefMan-cic.tex 8609 2006-02-24 13:32:57Z notin,no-port-forwarding,no-agent-forwarding,no-X11-forwarding,no-pty $ 

%%% Local Variables: 
%%% mode: latex
%%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual"
%%% End: