\chapter{Detailed examples of tactics} \label{Tactics-examples} This chapter presents detailed examples of certain tactics, to illustrate their behavior. \section{\tt refine} \tacindex{refine} \label{refine-example} This tactic applies to any goal. It behaves like {\tt exact} with a big difference : the user can leave some holes (denoted by \texttt{\_} or {\tt (\_:}{\it type}{\tt )}) in the term. {\tt refine} will generate as many subgoals as they are holes in the term. The type of holes must be either synthesized by the system or declared by an explicit cast like \verb|(\_:nat->Prop)|. This low-level tactic can be useful to advanced users. %\firstexample \Example \begin{coq_example*} Inductive Option : Set := | Fail : Option | Ok : bool -> Option. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example} Definition get : forall x:Option, x <> Fail -> bool. refine (fun x:Option => match x return x <> Fail -> bool with | Fail => _ | Ok b => fun _ => b end). intros; absurd (Fail = Fail); trivial. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} Defined. \end{coq_example*} % \example{Using Refine to build a poor-man's ``Cases'' tactic} % \texttt{Refine} is actually the only way for the user to do % a proof with the same structure as a {\tt Cases} definition. Actually, % the tactics \texttt{case} (see \ref{case}) and \texttt{Elim} (see % \ref{elim}) only allow one step of elementary induction. % \begin{coq_example*} % Require Bool. % Require Arith. % \end{coq_example*} % %\begin{coq_eval} % %Abort. % %\end{coq_eval} % \begin{coq_example} % Definition one_two_or_five := [x:nat] % Cases x of % (1) => true % | (2) => true % | (5) => true % | _ => false % end. % Goal (x:nat)(Is_true (one_two_or_five x)) -> x=(1)\/x=(2)\/x=(5). % \end{coq_example} % A traditional script would be the following: % \begin{coq_example*} % Destruct x. % Tauto. % Destruct n. % Auto. % Destruct n0. % Auto. % Destruct n1. % Tauto. % Destruct n2. % Tauto. % Destruct n3. % Auto. % Intros; Inversion H. % \end{coq_example*} % With the tactic \texttt{Refine}, it becomes quite shorter: % \begin{coq_example*} % Restart. % \end{coq_example*} % \begin{coq_example} % Refine [x:nat] % <[y:nat](Is_true (one_two_or_five y))->(y=(1)\/y=(2)\/y=(5))> % Cases x of % (1) => [H]? % | (2) => [H]? % | (5) => [H]? % | n => [H](False_ind ? H) % end; Auto. % \end{coq_example} % \begin{coq_eval} % Abort. % \end{coq_eval} \section{\tt eapply} \tacindex{eapply} \label{eapply-example} \Example Assume we have a relation on {\tt nat} which is transitive: \begin{coq_example*} Variable R : nat -> nat -> Prop. Hypothesis Rtrans : forall x y z:nat, R x y -> R y z -> R x z. Variables n m p : nat. Hypothesis Rnm : R n m. Hypothesis Rmp : R m p. \end{coq_example*} Consider the goal {\tt (R n p)} provable using the transitivity of {\tt R}: \begin{coq_example*} Goal R n p. \end{coq_example*} The direct application of {\tt Rtrans} with {\tt apply} fails because no value for {\tt y} in {\tt Rtrans} is found by {\tt apply}: \begin{coq_eval} Set Printing Depth 50. (********** The following is not correct and should produce **********) (**** Error: generated subgoal (R n ?17) has metavariables in it *****) \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} apply Rtrans. \end{coq_example} A solution is to rather apply {\tt (Rtrans n m p)}. \begin{coq_example} apply (Rtrans n m p). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} More elegantly, {\tt apply Rtrans with (y:=m)} allows to only mention the unknown {\tt m}: \begin{coq_example} apply Rtrans with (y := m). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} Another solution is to mention the proof of {\tt (R x y)} in {\tt Rtrans}... \begin{coq_example} apply Rtrans with (1 := Rnm). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} ... or the proof of {\tt (R y z)}: \begin{coq_example} apply Rtrans with (2 := Rmp). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} On the opposite, one can use {\tt eapply} which postpone the problem of finding {\tt m}. Then one can apply the hypotheses {\tt Rnm} and {\tt Rmp}. This instantiates the existential variable and completes the proof. \begin{coq_example} eapply Rtrans. apply Rnm. apply Rmp. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset R. \end{coq_eval} \section{{\tt Scheme}} \comindex{Scheme} \label{Scheme-examples} \firstexample \example{Induction scheme for \texttt{tree} and \texttt{forest}} The definition of principle of mutual induction for {\tt tree} and {\tt forest} over the sort {\tt Set} is defined by the command: \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Variables A B : Set. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Inductive tree : Set := node : A -> forest -> tree with forest : Set := | leaf : B -> forest | cons : tree -> forest -> forest. Scheme tree_forest_rec := Induction for tree Sort Set with forest_tree_rec := Induction for forest Sort Set. \end{coq_example*} You may now look at the type of {\tt tree\_forest\_rec}: \begin{coq_example} Check tree_forest_rec. \end{coq_example} This principle involves two different predicates for {\tt trees} and {\tt forests}; it also has three premises each one corresponding to a constructor of one of the inductive definitions. The principle {\tt tree\_forest\_rec} shares exactly the same premises, only the conclusion now refers to the property of forests. \begin{coq_example} Check forest_tree_rec. \end{coq_example} \example{Predicates {\tt odd} and {\tt even} on naturals} Let {\tt odd} and {\tt even} be inductively defined as: \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Open Scope nat_scope. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Inductive odd : nat -> Prop := oddS : forall n:nat, even n -> odd (S n) with even : nat -> Prop := | evenO : even 0 | evenS : forall n:nat, odd n -> even (S n). \end{coq_example*} The following command generates a powerful elimination principle: \begin{coq_example} Scheme odd_even := Minimality for odd Sort Prop with even_odd := Minimality for even Sort Prop. \end{coq_example} The type of {\tt odd\_even} for instance will be: \begin{coq_example} Check odd_even. \end{coq_example} The type of {\tt even\_odd} shares the same premises but the conclusion is {\tt (n:nat)(even n)->(Q n)}. \section{{\tt Functional Scheme} and {\tt functional induction}} \comindex{Functional Scheme}\tacindex{functional induction} \label{FunScheme-examples} \firstexample \example{Induction scheme for \texttt{div2}} We define the function \texttt{div2} as follows: \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Require Import Arith. Fixpoint div2 (n:nat) : nat := match n with | O => 0 | S O => 0 | S (S n') => S (div2 n') end. \end{coq_example*} The definition of a principle of induction corresponding to the recursive structure of \texttt{div2} is defined by the command: \begin{coq_example} Functional Scheme div2_ind := Induction for div2 Sort Prop. \end{coq_example} You may now look at the type of {\tt div2\_ind}: \begin{coq_example} Check div2_ind. \end{coq_example} We can now prove the following lemma using this principle: \begin{coq_example*} Lemma div2_le' : forall n:nat, div2 n <= n. intro n. pattern n , (div2 n). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} apply div2_ind; intros. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} auto with arith. auto with arith. simpl; auto with arith. Qed. \end{coq_example*} We can use directly the \texttt{functional induction} (\ref{FunInduction}) tactic instead of the pattern/apply trick: \begin{coq_example*} Reset div2_le'. Lemma div2_le : forall n:nat, div2 n <= n. intro n. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} functional induction (div2 n). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} auto with arith. auto with arith. auto with arith. Qed. \end{coq_example*} \Rem There is a difference between obtaining an induction scheme for a function by using \texttt{Function} (section~\ref{Function}) and by using \texttt{Functional Scheme} after a normal definition using \texttt{Fixpoint} or \texttt{Definition}. See \ref{Function} for details. \example{Induction scheme for \texttt{tree\_size}} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} We define trees by the following mutual inductive type: \begin{coq_example*} Variable A : Set. Inductive tree : Set := node : A -> forest -> tree with forest : Set := | empty : forest | cons : tree -> forest -> forest. \end{coq_example*} We define the function \texttt{tree\_size} that computes the size of a tree or a forest. Note that we use \texttt{Function} which generally produces better principles. \begin{coq_example*} Function tree_size (t:tree) : nat := match t with | node A f => S (forest_size f) end with forest_size (f:forest) : nat := match f with | empty => 0 | cons t f' => (tree_size t + forest_size f') end. \end{coq_example*} Remark: \texttt{Function} generates itself non mutual induction principles {\tt tree\_size\_ind} and {\tt forest\_size\_ind}: \begin{coq_example} Check tree_size_ind. \end{coq_example} The definition of mutual induction principles following the recursive structure of \texttt{tree\_size} and \texttt{forest\_size} is defined by the command: \begin{coq_example*} Functional Scheme tree_size_ind2 := Induction for tree_size Sort Prop with forest_size_ind2 := Induction for forest_size Sort Prop. \end{coq_example*} You may now look at the type of {\tt tree\_size\_ind2}: \begin{coq_example} Check tree_size_ind2. \end{coq_example} \section{{\tt inversion}} \tacindex{inversion} \label{inversion-examples} \subsection*{Generalities about inversion} When working with (co)inductive predicates, we are very often faced to some of these situations: \begin{itemize} \item we have an inconsistent instance of an inductive predicate in the local context of hypotheses. Thus, the current goal can be trivially proved by absurdity. \item we have a hypothesis that is an instance of an inductive predicate, and the instance has some variables whose constraints we would like to derive. \end{itemize} The inversion tactics are very useful to simplify the work in these cases. Inversion tools can be classified in three groups: \begin{enumerate} \item tactics for inverting an instance without stocking the inversion lemma in the context; this includes the tactics (\texttt{dependent}) \texttt{inversion} and (\texttt{dependent}) \texttt{inversion\_clear}. \item commands for generating and stocking in the context the inversion lemma corresponding to an instance; this includes \texttt{Derive} (\texttt{Dependent}) \texttt{Inversion} and \texttt{Derive} (\texttt{Dependent}) \texttt{Inversion\_clear}. \item tactics for inverting an instance using an already defined inversion lemma; this includes the tactic \texttt{inversion \ldots using}. \end{enumerate} As inversion proofs may be large in size, we recommend the user to stock the lemmas whenever the same instance needs to be inverted several times. \firstexample \example{Non-dependent inversion} Let's consider the relation \texttt{Le} over natural numbers and the following variables: \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Inductive Le : nat -> nat -> Set := | LeO : forall n:nat, Le 0 n | LeS : forall n m:nat, Le n m -> Le (S n) (S m). Variable P : nat -> nat -> Prop. Variable Q : forall n m:nat, Le n m -> Prop. \end{coq_example*} For example, consider the goal: \begin{coq_eval} Lemma ex : forall n m:nat, Le (S n) m -> P n m. intros. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. \end{coq_example} To prove the goal we may need to reason by cases on \texttt{H} and to derive that \texttt{m} is necessarily of the form $(S~m_0)$ for certain $m_0$ and that $(Le~n~m_0)$. Deriving these conditions corresponds to prove that the only possible constructor of \texttt{(Le (S n) m)} is \texttt{LeS} and that we can invert the \texttt{->} in the type of \texttt{LeS}. This inversion is possible because \texttt{Le} is the smallest set closed by the constructors \texttt{LeO} and \texttt{LeS}. \begin{coq_example} inversion_clear H. \end{coq_example} Note that \texttt{m} has been substituted in the goal for \texttt{(S m0)} and that the hypothesis \texttt{(Le n m0)} has been added to the context. Sometimes it is interesting to have the equality \texttt{m=(S m0)} in the context to use it after. In that case we can use \texttt{inversion} that does not clear the equalities: \begin{coq_example*} Undo. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} inversion H. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} \example{Dependent Inversion} Let us consider the following goal: \begin{coq_eval} Lemma ex_dep : forall (n m:nat) (H:Le (S n) m), Q (S n) m H. intros. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. \end{coq_example} As \texttt{H} occurs in the goal, we may want to reason by cases on its structure and so, we would like inversion tactics to substitute \texttt{H} by the corresponding term in constructor form. Neither \texttt{Inversion} nor {\tt Inversion\_clear} make such a substitution. To have such a behavior we use the dependent inversion tactics: \begin{coq_example} dependent inversion_clear H. \end{coq_example} Note that \texttt{H} has been substituted by \texttt{(LeS n m0 l)} and \texttt{m} by \texttt{(S m0)}. \example{using already defined inversion lemmas} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} For example, to generate the inversion lemma for the instance \texttt{(Le (S n) m)} and the sort \texttt{Prop} we do: \begin{coq_example*} Derive Inversion_clear leminv with (forall n m:nat, Le (S n) m) Sort Prop. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} Check leminv. \end{coq_example} Then we can use the proven inversion lemma: \begin{coq_example} Show. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example} inversion H using leminv. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \section{\tt autorewrite} \label{autorewrite-example} Here are two examples of {\tt autorewrite} use. The first one ({\em Ackermann function}) shows actually a quite basic use where there is no conditional rewriting. The second one ({\em Mac Carthy function}) involves conditional rewritings and shows how to deal with them using the optional tactic of the {\tt Hint~Rewrite} command. \firstexample \example{Ackermann function} %Here is a basic use of {\tt AutoRewrite} with the Ackermann function: \begin{coq_example*} Require Import Arith. Variable Ack : nat -> nat -> nat. Axiom Ack0 : forall m:nat, Ack 0 m = S m. Axiom Ack1 : forall n:nat, Ack (S n) 0 = Ack n 1. Axiom Ack2 : forall n m:nat, Ack (S n) (S m) = Ack n (Ack (S n) m). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} Hint Rewrite Ack0 Ack1 Ack2 : base0. Lemma ResAck0 : Ack 3 2 = 29. autorewrite with base0 using try reflexivity. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \example{Mac Carthy function} %The Mac Carthy function shows a more complex case: \begin{coq_example*} Require Import Omega. Variable g : nat -> nat -> nat. Axiom g0 : forall m:nat, g 0 m = m. Axiom g1 : forall n m:nat, (n > 0) -> (m > 100) -> g n m = g (pred n) (m - 10). Axiom g2 : forall n m:nat, (n > 0) -> (m <= 100) -> g n m = g (S n) (m + 11). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} Hint Rewrite g0 g1 g2 using omega : base1. Lemma Resg0 : g 1 110 = 100. autorewrite with base1 using reflexivity || simpl. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Lemma Resg1 : g 1 95 = 91. autorewrite with base1 using reflexivity || simpl. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \section{\tt quote} \tacindex{quote} \label{quote-examples} The tactic \texttt{quote} allows to use Barendregt's so-called 2-level approach without writing any ML code. Suppose you have a language \texttt{L} of 'abstract terms' and a type \texttt{A} of 'concrete terms' and a function \texttt{f : L -> A}. If \texttt{L} is a simple inductive datatype and \texttt{f} a simple fixpoint, \texttt{quote f} will replace the head of current goal by a convertible term of the form \texttt{(f t)}. \texttt{L} must have a constructor of type: \texttt{A -> L}. Here is an example: \begin{coq_example} Require Import Quote. Parameters A B C : Prop. Inductive formula : Type := | f_and : formula -> formula -> formula (* binary constructor *) | f_or : formula -> formula -> formula | f_not : formula -> formula (* unary constructor *) | f_true : formula (* 0-ary constructor *) | f_const : Prop -> formula (* contructor for constants *). Fixpoint interp_f (f: formula) : Prop := match f with | f_and f1 f2 => interp_f f1 /\ interp_f f2 | f_or f1 f2 => interp_f f1 \/ interp_f f2 | f_not f1 => ~ interp_f f1 | f_true => True | f_const c => c end. Goal A /\ (A \/ True) /\ ~ B /\ (A <-> A). quote interp_f. \end{coq_example} The algorithm to perform this inversion is: try to match the term with right-hand sides expression of \texttt{f}. If there is a match, apply the corresponding left-hand side and call yourself recursively on sub-terms. If there is no match, we are at a leaf: return the corresponding constructor (here \texttt{f\_const}) applied to the term. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{quote: not a simple fixpoint} \\ Happens when \texttt{quote} is not able to perform inversion properly. \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{Introducing variables map} The normal use of \texttt{quote} is to make proofs by reflection: one defines a function \texttt{simplify : formula -> formula} and proves a theorem \texttt{simplify\_ok: (f:formula)(interp\_f (simplify f)) -> (interp\_f f)}. Then, one can simplify formulas by doing: \begin{verbatim} quote interp_f. apply simplify_ok. compute. \end{verbatim} But there is a problem with leafs: in the example above one cannot write a function that implements, for example, the logical simplifications $A \land A \ra A$ or $A \land \lnot A \ra \texttt{False}$. This is because the \Prop{} is impredicative. It is better to use that type of formulas: \begin{coq_eval} Reset formula. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Inductive formula : Set := | f_and : formula -> formula -> formula | f_or : formula -> formula -> formula | f_not : formula -> formula | f_true : formula | f_atom : index -> formula. \end{coq_example*} \texttt{index} is defined in module \texttt{quote}. Equality on that type is decidable so we are able to simplify $A \land A$ into $A$ at the abstract level. When there are variables, there are bindings, and \texttt{quote} provides also a type \texttt{(varmap A)} of bindings from \texttt{index} to any set \texttt{A}, and a function \texttt{varmap\_find} to search in such maps. The interpretation function has now another argument, a variables map: \begin{coq_example} Fixpoint interp_f (vm: varmap Prop) (f:formula) {struct f} : Prop := match f with | f_and f1 f2 => interp_f vm f1 /\ interp_f vm f2 | f_or f1 f2 => interp_f vm f1 \/ interp_f vm f2 | f_not f1 => ~ interp_f vm f1 | f_true => True | f_atom i => varmap_find True i vm end. \end{coq_example} \noindent\texttt{quote} handles this second case properly: \begin{coq_example} Goal A /\ (B \/ A) /\ (A \/ ~ B). quote interp_f. \end{coq_example} It builds \texttt{vm} and \texttt{t} such that \texttt{(f vm t)} is convertible with the conclusion of current goal. \subsection{Combining variables and constants} One can have both variables and constants in abstracts terms; that is the case, for example, for the \texttt{ring} tactic (chapter \ref{ring}). Then one must provide to \texttt{quote} a list of \emph{constructors of constants}. For example, if the list is \texttt{[O S]} then closed natural numbers will be considered as constants and other terms as variables. Example: \begin{coq_eval} Reset formula. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Inductive formula : Type := | f_and : formula -> formula -> formula | f_or : formula -> formula -> formula | f_not : formula -> formula | f_true : formula | f_const : Prop -> formula (* constructor for constants *) | f_atom : index -> formula. Fixpoint interp_f (vm: (* constructor for variables *) varmap Prop) (f:formula) {struct f} : Prop := match f with | f_and f1 f2 => interp_f vm f1 /\ interp_f vm f2 | f_or f1 f2 => interp_f vm f1 \/ interp_f vm f2 | f_not f1 => ~ interp_f vm f1 | f_true => True | f_const c => c | f_atom i => varmap_find True i vm end. Goal A /\ (A \/ True) /\ ~ B /\ (C <-> C). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} quote interp_f [ A B ]. Undo. quote interp_f [ B C iff ]. \end{coq_example} \Warning Since function inversion is undecidable in general case, don't expect miracles from it! % \SeeAlso file \texttt{theories/DEMOS/DemoQuote.v} \SeeAlso comments of source file \texttt{tactics/contrib/polynom/quote.ml} \SeeAlso the \texttt{ring} tactic (Chapter~\ref{ring}) \section{Using the tactical language} \subsection{About the cardinality of the set of natural numbers} A first example which shows how to use the pattern matching over the proof contexts is the proof that natural numbers have more than two elements. The proof of such a lemma can be done as %shown on Figure~\ref{cnatltac}. follows: %\begin{figure} %\begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Require Import Arith. Require Import List. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Lemma card_nat : ~ (exists x : nat, exists y : nat, forall z:nat, x = z \/ y = z). Proof. red; intros (x, (y, Hy)). elim (Hy 0); elim (Hy 1); elim (Hy 2); intros; match goal with | [_:(?a = ?b),_:(?a = ?c) |- _ ] => cut (b = c); [ discriminate | apply trans_equal with a; auto ] end. Qed. \end{coq_example*} %\end{centerframe} %\caption{A proof on cardinality of natural numbers} %\label{cnatltac} %\end{figure} We can notice that all the (very similar) cases coming from the three eliminations (with three distinct natural numbers) are successfully solved by a {\tt match goal} structure and, in particular, with only one pattern (use of non-linear matching). \subsection{Permutation on closed lists} Another more complex example is the problem of permutation on closed lists. The aim is to show that a closed list is a permutation of another one. First, we define the permutation predicate as shown in table~\ref{permutpred}. \begin{figure} \begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example*} Section Sort. Variable A : Set. Inductive permut : list A -> list A -> Prop := | permut_refl : forall l, permut l l | permut_cons : forall a l0 l1, permut l0 l1 -> permut (a :: l0) (a :: l1) | permut_append : forall a l, permut (a :: l) (l ++ a :: nil) | permut_trans : forall l0 l1 l2, permut l0 l1 -> permut l1 l2 -> permut l0 l2. End Sort. \end{coq_example*} \end{centerframe} \caption{Definition of the permutation predicate} \label{permutpred} \end{figure} A more complex example is the problem of permutation on closed lists. The aim is to show that a closed list is a permutation of another one. First, we define the permutation predicate as shown on Figure~\ref{permutpred}. \begin{figure} \begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example} Ltac Permut n := match goal with | |- (permut _ ?l ?l) => apply permut_refl | |- (permut _ (?a :: ?l1) (?a :: ?l2)) => let newn := eval compute in (length l1) in (apply permut_cons; Permut newn) | |- (permut ?A (?a :: ?l1) ?l2) => match eval compute in n with | 1 => fail | _ => let l1' := constr:(l1 ++ a :: nil) in (apply (permut_trans A (a :: l1) l1' l2); [ apply permut_append | compute; Permut (pred n) ]) end end. Ltac PermutProve := match goal with | |- (permut _ ?l1 ?l2) => match eval compute in (length l1 = length l2) with | (?n = ?n) => Permut n end end. \end{coq_example} \end{centerframe} \caption{Permutation tactic} \label{permutltac} \end{figure} Next, we can write naturally the tactic and the result can be seen on Figure~\ref{permutltac}. We can notice that we use two toplevel definitions {\tt PermutProve} and {\tt Permut}. The function to be called is {\tt PermutProve} which computes the lengths of the two lists and calls {\tt Permut} with the length if the two lists have the same length. {\tt Permut} works as expected. If the two lists are equal, it concludes. Otherwise, if the lists have identical first elements, it applies {\tt Permut} on the tail of the lists. Finally, if the lists have different first elements, it puts the first element of one of the lists (here the second one which appears in the {\tt permut} predicate) at the end if that is possible, i.e., if the new first element has been at this place previously. To verify that all rotations have been done for a list, we use the length of the list as an argument for {\tt Permut} and this length is decremented for each rotation down to, but not including, 1 because for a list of length $n$, we can make exactly $n-1$ rotations to generate at most $n$ distinct lists. Here, it must be noticed that we use the natural numbers of {\Coq} for the rotation counter. On Figure~\ref{ltac}, we can see that it is possible to use usual natural numbers but they are only used as arguments for primitive tactics and they cannot be handled, in particular, we cannot make computations with them. So, a natural choice is to use {\Coq} data structures so that {\Coq} makes the computations (reductions) by {\tt eval compute in} and we can get the terms back by {\tt match}. With {\tt PermutProve}, we can now prove lemmas as % shown on Figure~\ref{permutlem}. follows: %\begin{figure} %\begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example*} Lemma permut_ex1 : permut nat (1 :: 2 :: 3 :: nil) (3 :: 2 :: 1 :: nil). Proof. PermutProve. Qed. Lemma permut_ex2 : permut nat (0 :: 1 :: 2 :: 3 :: 4 :: 5 :: 6 :: 7 :: 8 :: 9 :: nil) (0 :: 2 :: 4 :: 6 :: 8 :: 9 :: 7 :: 5 :: 3 :: 1 :: nil). Proof. PermutProve. Qed. \end{coq_example*} %\end{centerframe} %\caption{Examples of {\tt PermutProve} use} %\label{permutlem} %\end{figure} \subsection{Deciding intuitionistic propositional logic} \begin{figure}[b] \begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example} Ltac Axioms := match goal with | |- True => trivial | _:False |- _ => elimtype False; assumption | _:?A |- ?A => auto end. \end{coq_example} \end{centerframe} \caption{Deciding intuitionistic propositions (1)} \label{tautoltaca} \end{figure} \begin{figure} \begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example} Ltac DSimplif := repeat (intros; match goal with | id:(~ _) |- _ => red in id | id:(_ /\ _) |- _ => elim id; do 2 intro; clear id | id:(_ \/ _) |- _ => elim id; intro; clear id | id:(?A /\ ?B -> ?C) |- _ => cut (A -> B -> C); [ intro | intros; apply id; split; assumption ] | id:(?A \/ ?B -> ?C) |- _ => cut (B -> C); [ cut (A -> C); [ intros; clear id | intro; apply id; left; assumption ] | intro; apply id; right; assumption ] | id0:(?A -> ?B),id1:?A |- _ => cut B; [ intro; clear id0 | apply id0; assumption ] | |- (_ /\ _) => split | |- (~ _) => red end). Ltac TautoProp := DSimplif; Axioms || match goal with | id:((?A -> ?B) -> ?C) |- _ => cut (B -> C); [ intro; cut (A -> B); [ intro; cut C; [ intro; clear id | apply id; assumption ] | clear id ] | intro; apply id; intro; assumption ]; TautoProp | id:(~ ?A -> ?B) |- _ => cut (False -> B); [ intro; cut (A -> False); [ intro; cut B; [ intro; clear id | apply id; assumption ] | clear id ] | intro; apply id; red; intro; assumption ]; TautoProp | |- (_ \/ _) => (left; TautoProp) || (right; TautoProp) end. \end{coq_example} \end{centerframe} \caption{Deciding intuitionistic propositions (2)} \label{tautoltacb} \end{figure} The pattern matching on goals allows a complete and so a powerful backtracking when returning tactic values. An interesting application is the problem of deciding intuitionistic propositional logic. Considering the contraction-free sequent calculi {\tt LJT*} of Roy~Dyckhoff (\cite{Dyc92}), it is quite natural to code such a tactic using the tactic language as shown on Figures~\ref{tautoltaca} and~\ref{tautoltacb}. The tactic {\tt Axioms} tries to conclude using usual axioms. The tactic {\tt DSimplif} applies all the reversible rules of Dyckhoff's system. Finally, the tactic {\tt TautoProp} (the main tactic to be called) simplifies with {\tt DSimplif}, tries to conclude with {\tt Axioms} and tries several paths using the backtracking rules (one of the four Dyckhoff's rules for the left implication to get rid of the contraction and the right or). For example, with {\tt TautoProp}, we can prove tautologies like those: % on Figure~\ref{tautolem}. %\begin{figure}[tbp] %\begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example*} Lemma tauto_ex1 : forall A B:Prop, A /\ B -> A \/ B. Proof. TautoProp. Qed. Lemma tauto_ex2 : forall A B:Prop, (~ ~ B -> B) -> (A -> B) -> ~ ~ A -> B. Proof. TautoProp. Qed. \end{coq_example*} %\end{centerframe} %\caption{Proofs of tautologies with {\tt TautoProp}} %\label{tautolem} %\end{figure} \subsection{Deciding type isomorphisms} A more tricky problem is to decide equalities between types and modulo isomorphisms. Here, we choose to use the isomorphisms of the simply typed $\lb{}$-calculus with Cartesian product and $unit$ type (see, for example, \cite{RC95}). The axioms of this $\lb{}$-calculus are given by table~\ref{isosax}. \begin{figure} \begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Open Scope type_scope. Section Iso_axioms. Variables A B C : Set. Axiom Com : A * B = B * A. Axiom Ass : A * (B * C) = A * B * C. Axiom Cur : (A * B -> C) = (A -> B -> C). Axiom Dis : (A -> B * C) = (A -> B) * (A -> C). Axiom P_unit : A * unit = A. Axiom AR_unit : (A -> unit) = unit. Axiom AL_unit : (unit -> A) = A. Lemma Cons : B = C -> A * B = A * C. Proof. intro Heq; rewrite Heq; apply refl_equal. Qed. End Iso_axioms. \end{coq_example*} \end{centerframe} \caption{Type isomorphism axioms} \label{isosax} \end{figure} A more tricky problem is to decide equalities between types and modulo isomorphisms. Here, we choose to use the isomorphisms of the simply typed $\lb{}$-calculus with Cartesian product and $unit$ type (see, for example, \cite{RC95}). The axioms of this $\lb{}$-calculus are given on Figure~\ref{isosax}. \begin{figure}[ht] \begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example} Ltac DSimplif trm := match trm with | (?A * ?B * ?C) => rewrite <- (Ass A B C); try MainSimplif | (?A * ?B -> ?C) => rewrite (Cur A B C); try MainSimplif | (?A -> ?B * ?C) => rewrite (Dis A B C); try MainSimplif | (?A * unit) => rewrite (P_unit A); try MainSimplif | (unit * ?B) => rewrite (Com unit B); try MainSimplif | (?A -> unit) => rewrite (AR_unit A); try MainSimplif | (unit -> ?B) => rewrite (AL_unit B); try MainSimplif | (?A * ?B) => (DSimplif A; try MainSimplif) || (DSimplif B; try MainSimplif) | (?A -> ?B) => (DSimplif A; try MainSimplif) || (DSimplif B; try MainSimplif) end with MainSimplif := match goal with | |- (?A = ?B) => try DSimplif A; try DSimplif B end. Ltac Length trm := match trm with | (_ * ?B) => let succ := Length B in constr:(S succ) | _ => constr:1 end. Ltac assoc := repeat rewrite <- Ass. \end{coq_example} \end{centerframe} \caption{Type isomorphism tactic (1)} \label{isosltac1} \end{figure} \begin{figure}[ht] \begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example} Ltac DoCompare n := match goal with | [ |- (?A = ?A) ] => apply refl_equal | [ |- (?A * ?B = ?A * ?C) ] => apply Cons; let newn := Length B in DoCompare newn | [ |- (?A * ?B = ?C) ] => match eval compute in n with | 1 => fail | _ => pattern (A * B) at 1; rewrite Com; assoc; DoCompare (pred n) end end. Ltac CompareStruct := match goal with | [ |- (?A = ?B) ] => let l1 := Length A with l2 := Length B in match eval compute in (l1 = l2) with | (?n = ?n) => DoCompare n end end. Ltac IsoProve := MainSimplif; CompareStruct. \end{coq_example} \end{centerframe} \caption{Type isomorphism tactic (2)} \label{isosltac2} \end{figure} The tactic to judge equalities modulo this axiomatization can be written as shown on Figures~\ref{isosltac1} and~\ref{isosltac2}. The algorithm is quite simple. Types are reduced using axioms that can be oriented (this done by {\tt MainSimplif}). The normal forms are sequences of Cartesian products without Cartesian product in the left component. These normal forms are then compared modulo permutation of the components (this is done by {\tt CompareStruct}). The main tactic to be called and realizing this algorithm is {\tt IsoProve}. % Figure~\ref{isoslem} gives Here are examples of what can be solved by {\tt IsoProve}. %\begin{figure}[ht] %\begin{centerframe} \begin{coq_example*} Lemma isos_ex1 : forall A B:Set, A * unit * B = B * (unit * A). Proof. intros; IsoProve. Qed. Lemma isos_ex2 : forall A B C:Set, (A * unit -> B * (C * unit)) = (A * unit -> (C -> unit) * C) * (unit -> A -> B). Proof. intros; IsoProve. Qed. \end{coq_example*} %\end{centerframe} %\caption{Type equalities solved by {\tt IsoProve}} %\label{isoslem} %\end{figure} %%% Local Variables: %%% mode: latex %%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual" %%% End: