1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
1481
1482
1483
1484
1485
1486
1487
1488
1489
1490
1491
1492
1493
1494
1495
1496
1497
1498
1499
1500
1501
1502
1503
1504
1505
1506
1507
1508
1509
1510
1511
1512
1513
1514
1515
1516
1517
1518
1519
1520
1521
1522
1523
1524
1525
1526
1527
1528
1529
1530
1531
1532
1533
1534
1535
1536
1537
1538
1539
1540
1541
1542
1543
1544
1545
1546
1547
1548
1549
1550
1551
1552
1553
1554
1555
1556
1557
1558
1559
1560
1561
1562
1563
1564
1565
1566
1567
1568
1569
1570
1571
1572
1573
1574
1575
1576
1577
1578
1579
1580
1581
1582
1583
1584
1585
1586
1587
1588
1589
1590
1591
1592
1593
1594
1595
1596
1597
1598
1599
1600
1601
1602
1603
1604
1605
1606
1607
1608
1609
1610
1611
1612
1613
1614
1615
1616
1617
1618
1619
1620
1621
1622
1623
1624
1625
1626
1627
1628
1629
1630
1631
1632
1633
1634
1635
1636
1637
1638
1639
1640
1641
1642
1643
1644
1645
1646
1647
1648
1649
1650
1651
1652
1653
1654
1655
1656
1657
1658
1659
1660
1661
1662
1663
1664
1665
1666
1667
1668
1669
1670
1671
1672
1673
1674
1675
1676
1677
1678
1679
1680
1681
1682
1683
1684
1685
1686
1687
1688
1689
1690
1691
1692
1693
1694
1695
1696
1697
1698
1699
1700
1701
1702
1703
1704
1705
1706
1707
1708
1709
1710
1711
1712
1713
1714
1715
1716
1717
1718
1719
1720
1721
1722
1723
1724
1725
1726
1727
1728
1729
1730
1731
1732
1733
1734
1735
1736
1737
1738
1739
1740
1741
1742
1743
1744
1745
1746
1747
1748
1749
1750
1751
1752
1753
1754
1755
1756
1757
1758
1759
1760
1761
1762
1763
1764
1765
1766
1767
1768
1769
1770
1771
1772
1773
1774
1775
1776
1777
1778
1779
1780
1781
1782
1783
1784
1785
1786
1787
1788
1789
1790
1791
1792
1793
1794
1795
1796
1797
1798
1799
1800
1801
1802
1803
1804
1805
1806
1807
1808
1809
1810
1811
1812
1813
1814
1815
1816
1817
1818
1819
1820
1821
1822
1823
1824
1825
1826
1827
1828
1829
1830
1831
1832
1833
1834
1835
1836
1837
1838
1839
1840
1841
1842
1843
1844
1845
1846
1847
1848
1849
1850
1851
1852
1853
1854
1855
1856
1857
1858
1859
1860
1861
1862
1863
1864
1865
1866
1867
1868
1869
1870
1871
1872
1873
1874
1875
1876
1877
1878
1879
1880
1881
1882
1883
1884
1885
1886
1887
1888
1889
|
\chapter[Calculus of Inductive Constructions]{Calculus of Inductive Constructions
\label{Cic}
\index{Cic@\textsc{CIC}}
\index{Calculus of Inductive Constructions}}
The underlying formal language of {\Coq} is a {\em Calculus of
Inductive Constructions} (\CIC) whose inference rules are presented in
this chapter. The history of this formalism as well as pointers to related work
are provided in a separate chapter; see {\em Credits}.
\section[The terms]{The terms\label{Terms}}
The expressions of the {\CIC} are {\em terms} and all terms have a {\em type}.
There are types for functions (or
programs), there are atomic types (especially datatypes)... but also
types for proofs and types for the types themselves.
Especially, any object handled in the formalism must belong to a
type. For instance, universal quantification is relative to a type and
takes the form {\it ``for all x
of type T, P''}. The expression {\it ``x of type T''} is
written {\it ``x:T''}. Informally, {\it ``x:T''} can be thought as
{\it ``x belongs to T''}.
The types of types are {\em sorts}. Types and sorts are themselves
terms so that terms, types and sorts are all components of a common
syntactic language of terms which is described in
Section~\label{cic:terms} but, first, we describe sorts.
\subsection[Sorts]{Sorts\label{Sorts}
\index{Sorts}}
All sorts have a type and there is an infinite well-founded
typing hierarchy of sorts whose base sorts are {\Prop} and {\Set}.
The sort {\Prop} intends to be the type of logical propositions. If
$M$ is a logical proposition then it denotes the class of terms
representing proofs of $M$. An object $m$ belonging to $M$ witnesses
the fact that $M$ is provable. An object of type {\Prop} is called a
proposition.
The sort {\Set} intends to be the type of small sets. This includes data
types such as booleans and naturals, but also products, subsets, and
function types over these data types.
{\Prop} and {\Set} themselves can be manipulated as ordinary
terms. Consequently they also have a type. Because assuming simply
that {\Set} has type {\Set} leads to an inconsistent theory~\cite{Coq86}, the
language of {\CIC} has infinitely many sorts. There are, in addition
to {\Set} and {\Prop} a hierarchy of universes {\Type$(i)$} for any
integer $i$.
Like {\Set}, all of the sorts {\Type$(i)$} contain small sets such as
booleans, natural numbers, as well as products, subsets and function
types over small sets. But, unlike {\Set}, they also contain large
sets, namely the sorts {\Set} and {\Type$(j)$} for $j<i$, and all
products, subsets and function types over these sorts.
Formally, we call {\Sort} the set of sorts which is defined by:
\index{Type@{\Type}}%
\index{Prop@{\Prop}}%
\index{Set@{\Set}}%
\[\Sort \equiv \{\Prop,\Set,\Type(i)\;|\; i \in \NN\} \]
Their properties, such as:
{\Prop:\Type$(1)$}, {\Set:\Type$(1)$}, and {\Type$(i)$:\Type$(i+1)$},
are defined in Section~\ref{subtyping-rules}.
% TODO: Somewhere in the document we should explain:
% - what concrete actions (in *.v files) cause creation of new universes
% - different kinds of relationships between universes (i.e. "max" and "succ")
% - what are all the actions (in *.v files) from which those relationships arise
The user does not have to mention explicitly the index $i$ when referring to
the universe \Type$(i)$. One only writes \Type. The
system itself generates for each instance of \Type\ a new
index for the universe and checks that the constraints between these
indexes can be solved. From the user point of view we consequently
have {\Type}:{\Type}.
We shall make precise in the typing rules the constraints between the
indexes.
\paragraph{Implementation issues}
In practice, the {\Type} hierarchy is implemented using
{\em algebraic universes}\index{algebraic universe}.
An algebraic universe $u$ is either a variable (a qualified
identifier with a number) or a successor of an algebraic universe (an
expression $u+1$), or an upper bound of algebraic universes (an
expression $max(u_1,...,u_n)$), or the base universe (the expression
$0$) which corresponds, in the arity of sort-polymorphic inductive
types (see Section \ref{Sort-polymorphism-inductive}),
to the predicative sort {\Set}. A graph of constraints between
the universe variables is maintained globally. To ensure the existence
of a mapping of the universes to the positive integers, the graph of
constraints must remain acyclic. Typing expressions that violate the
acyclicity of the graph of constraints results in a \errindex{Universe
inconsistency} error (see also Section~\ref{PrintingUniverses}).
% TODO: The concept of 'universe inconsistency' deserves more attention.
% Somewhere in the document we should:
% - give concrete examples when universe inconsistency arises
% - explain why it arised
% - how can a user identify the "vicious cycle".
% QUESTION: Is the presentation of universes as totally ordered a necessary or advantageous step?
% QUESTION: Shouldn't the explanation of universes in this chapter
% be consolidatd with Chapter 29: Polymorphic Universes?
%% HH: This looks to me more like source of confusion than helpful
%% \subsection{Constants}
%% Constants refers to
%% objects in the global environment. These constants may denote previously
%% defined objects, but also objects related to inductive definitions
%% (either the type itself or one of its constructors or destructors).
%% \medskip\noindent {\bf Remark. } In other presentations of \CIC,
%% the inductive objects are not seen as
%% external declarations but as first-class terms. Usually the
%% definitions are also completely ignored. This is a nice theoretical
%% point of view but not so practical. An inductive definition is
%% specified by a possibly huge set of declarations, clearly we want to
%% share this specification among the various inductive objects and not
%% to duplicate it. So the specification should exist somewhere and the
%% various objects should refer to it. We choose one more level of
%% indirection where the objects are just represented as constants and
%% the environment gives the information on the kind of object the
%% constant refers to.
%% \medskip
%% Our inductive objects will be manipulated as constants declared in the
%% environment. This roughly corresponds to the way they are actually
%% implemented in the \Coq\ system. It is simple to map this presentation
%% in a theory where inductive objects are represented by terms.
\subsection{Terms}
\label{cic:terms}
Terms are built from sorts, variables, constants,
%constructors, inductive types,
abstractions, applications, local definitions,
%case analysis, fixpoints, cofixpoints
and products.
From a syntactic point of view, types cannot be distinguished from terms,
except that they cannot start by an abstraction or a constructor.
More precisely the language of the {\em Calculus of Inductive
Constructions} is built from the following rules.
\begin{enumerate}
\item the sorts {\Set}, {\Prop}, ${\Type(i)}$ are terms.
\item variables, hereafter ranged over by letters $x$, $y$, etc., are terms
\item constants, hereafter ranged over by letters $c$, $d$, etc., are terms.
%\item constructors, hereafter ranged over by letter $C$, are terms.
%\item inductive types, hereafter ranged over by letter $I$, are terms.
\item\index{products} if $x$ is a variable and $T$, $U$ are terms then $\forall~x:T,U$
($\kw{forall}~x:T,~U$ in \Coq{} concrete syntax) is a term. If $x$
occurs in $U$, $\forall~x:T,U$ reads as {\it ``for all x of type T,
U''}. As $U$ depends on $x$, one says that $\forall~x:T,U$ is a
{\em dependent product}. If $x$ does not occur in $U$ then
$\forall~x:T,U$ reads as {\it ``if T then U''}. A {\em non dependent
product} can be written: $T \ra U$.
\item if $x$ is a variable and $T$, $u$ are terms then $\lb x:T \mto u$
($\kw{fun}~x:T~ {\tt =>}~ u$ in \Coq{} concrete syntax) is a term. This is a
notation for the $\lambda$-abstraction of
$\lambda$-calculus\index{lambda-calculus@$\lambda$-calculus}
\cite{Bar81}. The term $\lb x:T \mto u$ is a function which maps
elements of $T$ to the expression $u$.
\item if $t$ and $u$ are terms then $(t\ u)$ is a term
($t~u$ in \Coq{} concrete syntax). The term $(t\
u)$ reads as {\it ``t applied to u''}.
\item if $x$ is a variable, and $t$, $T$ and $u$ are terms then
$\kw{let}~x:=t:T~\kw{in}~u$ is a
term which denotes the term $u$ where the variable $x$ is locally
bound to $t$ of type $T$. This stands for the common ``let-in''
construction of functional programs such as ML or Scheme.
%\item case ...
%\item fixpoint ...
%\item cofixpoint ...
\end{enumerate}
\paragraph{Free variables.}
The notion of free variables is defined as usual. In the expressions
$\lb x:T\mto U$ and $\forall x:T, U$ the occurrences of $x$ in $U$
are bound.
% TODO: what is the best play to say that "terms are considered equal up to α-conversion"?
\paragraph[Substitution.]{Substitution.\index{Substitution}}
The notion of substituting a term $t$ to free occurrences of a
variable $x$ in a term $u$ is defined as usual. The resulting term
is written $\subst{u}{x}{t}$.
\paragraph[The logical vs programming readings.]{The logical vs programming readings.}
The constructions of the {\CIC} can be used to express both logical
and programming notions, accordingly to the Curry-Howard
correspondence between proofs and programs, and between propositions
and types~\cite{Cur58,How80,Bru72}.
For instance, let us assume that \nat\ is the type of natural numbers
with zero element written $0$ and that ${\tt True}$ is the always true
proposition. Then $\ra$ is used both to denote $\nat\ra\nat$ which is
the type of functions from \nat\ to \nat, to denote ${\tt True}\ra{\tt
True}$ which is an implicative proposition, to denote $\nat \ra
\Prop$ which is the type of unary predicates over the natural numbers,
etc.
Let us assume that ${\tt mult}$ is a function of type $\nat\ra\nat\ra
\nat$ and ${\tt eqnat}$ a predicate of type $\nat\ra\nat\ra \Prop$.
The $\lambda$-abstraction can serve to build ``ordinary'' functions as
in $\lambda x:\nat.({\tt mult}~x~x)$ (i.e. $\kw{fun}~x:\nat ~{\tt =>}~
{\tt mult} ~x~x$ in {\Coq} notation) but may build also predicates
over the natural numbers. For instance $\lambda x:\nat.({\tt eqnat}~
x~0)$ (i.e. $\kw{fun}~x:\nat ~{\tt =>}~ {\tt eqnat}~ x~0$ in {\Coq}
notation) will represent the predicate of one variable $x$ which
asserts the equality of $x$ with $0$. This predicate has type $\nat
\ra \Prop$ and it can be applied to any expression of type ${\nat}$,
say $t$, to give an object $P~t$ of type \Prop, namely a proposition.
Furthermore $\kw{forall}~x:\nat,\,P\;x$ will represent the type of
functions which associate to each natural number $n$ an object of type
$(P~n)$ and consequently represent the type of proofs of the formula
``$\forall x.\,P(x)$''.
\section[Typing rules]{Typing rules\label{Typed-terms}}
As objects of type theory, terms are subjected to {\em type
discipline}. The well typing of a term depends on
a global environment and a local context.
\paragraph{Local context.\index{Local context}}
A {\em local context} is an ordered list of
{\em local declarations\index{declaration!local}} of names which we call {\em variables\index{variable}}.
The declaration of some variable $x$ is
either a {\em local assumption\index{assumption!local}}, written $x:T$ ($T$ is a type) or a {\em local definition\index{definition!local}},
written $x:=t:T$. We use brackets to write local contexts. A
typical example is $[x:T;y:=u:U;z:V]$. Notice that the variables
declared in a local context must be distinct. If $\Gamma$ declares some $x$,
we write $x \in \Gamma$. By writing $(x:T) \in \Gamma$ we mean that
either $x:T$ is an assumption in $\Gamma$ or that there exists some $t$ such
that $x:=t:T$ is a definition in $\Gamma$. If $\Gamma$ defines some
$x:=t:T$, we also write $(x:=t:T) \in \Gamma$.
For the rest of the chapter, the
notation $\Gamma::(y:T)$ (resp. $\Gamma::(y:=t:T)$) denotes the local context
$\Gamma$ enriched with the declaration $y:T$ (resp. $y:=t:T$). The
notation $[]$ denotes the empty local context.
% Does not seem to be used further...
% Si dans l'explication WF(E)[Gamma] concernant les constantes
% definies ds un contexte
%We define the inclusion of two local contexts $\Gamma$ and $\Delta$ (written
%as $\Gamma \subset \Delta$) as the property, for all variable $x$,
%type $T$ and term $t$, if $(x:T) \in \Gamma$ then $(x:T) \in \Delta$
%and if $(x:=t:T) \in \Gamma$ then $(x:=t:T) \in \Delta$.
%We write
% $|\Delta|$ for the length of the context $\Delta$, that is for the number
% of declarations (assumptions or definitions) in $\Delta$.
\paragraph[Global environment.]{Global environment.\index{Global environment}}
%Because we are manipulating global declarations (global constants and global
%assumptions), we also need to consider a global environment $E$.
A {\em global environment} is an ordered list of {\em global declarations\index{declaration!global}}.
Global declarations are either {\em global assumptions\index{assumption!global}} or {\em global
definitions\index{definition!global}}, but also declarations of inductive objects. Inductive objects themselves declare both inductive or coinductive types and constructors
(see Section~\ref{Cic-inductive-definitions}).
A {\em global assumption} will be represented in the global environment as
$(c:T)$ which assumes the name $c$ to be of some type $T$.
A {\em global definition} will
be represented in the global environment as $c:=t:T$ which defines
the name $c$ to have value $t$ and type $T$.
We shall call such names {\em constants}.
The rules for inductive definitions (see Section
\ref{Cic-inductive-definitions}) have to be considered as assumption
rules to which the following definitions apply: if the name $c$ is
declared in $E$, we write $c \in E$ and if $c:T$ or $c:=t:T$ is
declared in $E$, we write $(c : T) \in E$.
\paragraph[Typing rules.]{Typing rules.\label{Typing-rules}\index{Typing rules}}
In the following, we define simultaneously two
judgments. The first one \WTEG{t}{T} means the term $t$ is well-typed
and has type $T$ in the global environment $E$ and local context $\Gamma$. The
second judgment \WFE{\Gamma} means that the global environment $E$ is
well-formed and the local context $\Gamma$ is a valid local context in this
global environment.
% HH: This looks to me complicated. I think it would be better to talk
% about ``discharge'' as a transformation of global environments,
% rather than as keeping a local context next to global constants.
%
%% It also means a third property which makes sure that any
%%constant in $E$ was defined in an environment which is included in
%%$\Gamma$
%%\footnote{This requirement could be relaxed if we instead introduced
%% an explicit mechanism for instantiating constants. At the external
%% level, the Coq engine works accordingly to this view that all the
%% definitions in the environment were built in a local sub-context of the
%% current local context.}.
A term $t$ is well typed in a global environment $E$ iff there exists a
local context $\Gamma$ and a term $T$ such that the judgment \WTEG{t}{T} can
be derived from the following rules.
\begin{description}
\item[W-Empty] \inference{\WF{[]}{}}
% QUESTION: Why in W-Local-Assum and W-Local-Def we do not need x ∉ E hypothesis?
\item[W-Local-Assum] % Ce n'est pas vrai : x peut apparaitre plusieurs fois dans Gamma
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s \in \Sort~~~~x \not\in \Gamma % \cup E
}{\WFE{\Gamma::(x:T)}}}
\item[W-Local-Def]
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{t}{T}~~~~x \not\in \Gamma % \cup E
}{\WFE{\Gamma::(x:=t:T)}}}
% QUESTION: Why in W-Global-Assum and W-Global-Def we do not need x ∉ Γ hypothesis?
\item[W-Global-Assum] \inference{\frac{\WTE{}{T}{s}~~~~s \in \Sort~~~~c \notin E}
{\WF{E;c:T}{}}}
\item[W-Global-Def] \inference{\frac{\WTE{}{t}{T}~~~c \notin E}
{\WF{E;c:=t:T}{}}}
% QUESTION: Why, in case of W-Local-Assum and W-Global-Assum we need s ∈ S hypothesis.
% QUESTION: At the moment, enrichment of a local context is denoted with ∷
% whereas enrichment of the global environment is denoted with ;
% Is it necessary to use two different notations?
% Couldn't we use ∷ also for enrichment of the global context?
\item[Ax-Prop] \index{Typing rules!Ax-Prop}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}}{\WTEG{\Prop}{\Type(1)}}}
\item[Ax-Set] \index{Typing rules!Ax-Set}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}}{\WTEG{\Set}{\Type(1)}}}
\item[Ax-Type] \index{Typing rules!Ax-Type}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}}{\WTEG{\Type(i)}{\Type(i+1)}}}
\item[Var]\index{Typing rules!Var}
\inference{\frac{ \WFE{\Gamma}~~~~~(x:T) \in \Gamma~~\mbox{or}~~(x:=t:T) \in \Gamma~\mbox{for some $t$}}{\WTEG{x}{T}}}
\item[Const] \index{Typing rules!Const}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}~~~~(c:T) \in E~~\mbox{or}~~(c:=t:T) \in E~\mbox{for some $t$} }{\WTEG{c}{T}}}
\item[Prod-Prop] \index{Typing rules!Prod-Prop}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s \in \Sort~~~
\WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Prop}}
{ \WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Prop}}}
\item[Prod-Set] \index{Typing rules!Prod-Set}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s \in\{\Prop, \Set\}~~~~~~
\WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Set}}
{ \WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Set}}}
\item[Prod-Type] \index{Typing rules!Prod-Type}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{\Type(i)}~~~~
\WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Type(i)}}
{\WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Type(i)}}}
\item[Lam]\index{Typing rules!Lam}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{s}~~~~ \WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{t}{U}}
{\WTEG{\lb x:T\mto t}{\forall x:T, U}}}
\item[App]\index{Typing rules!App}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{t}{\forall~x:U,T}~~~~\WTEG{u}{U}}
{\WTEG{(t\ u)}{\subst{T}{x}{u}}}}
\item[Let]\index{Typing rules!Let}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{t}{T}~~~~ \WTE{\Gamma::(x:=t:T)}{u}{U}}
{\WTEG{\letin{x}{t:T}{u}}{\subst{U}{x}{t}}}}
\end{description}
\Rem Prod$_1$ and Prod$_2$ typing-rules make sense if we consider the semantic
difference between {\Prop} and {\Set}:
\begin{itemize}
\item All values of a type that has a sort {\Set} are extractable.
\item No values of a type that has a sort {\Prop} are extractable.
\end{itemize}
\Rem We may have $\kw{let}~x:=t:T~\kw{in}~u$
well-typed without having $((\lb x:T\mto u)~t)$ well-typed (where
$T$ is a type of $t$). This is because the value $t$ associated to $x$
may be used in a conversion rule (see Section~\ref{conv-rules}).
% QUESTION: I do not understand. How would that be possible?
\section[Conversion rules]{Conversion rules\index{Conversion rules}
\label{conv-rules}}
In \CIC, there is an internal reduction mechanism. In particular, it
can decide if two programs are {\em intentionally} equal (one
says {\em convertible}). Convertibility is described in this section.
\paragraph[$\beta$-reduction.]{$\beta$-reduction.\label{beta}\index{beta-reduction@$\beta$-reduction}}
We want to be able to identify some terms as we can identify the
application of a function to a given argument with its result. For
instance the identity function over a given type $T$ can be written
$\lb x:T\mto x$. In any global environment $E$ and local context $\Gamma$, we want to identify any object $a$ (of type $T$) with the
application $((\lb x:T\mto x)~a)$. We define for this a {\em reduction} (or a
{\em conversion}) rule we call $\beta$:
\[ \WTEGRED{((\lb x:T\mto
t)~u)}{\triangleright_{\beta}}{\subst{t}{x}{u}} \]
We say that $\subst{t}{x}{u}$ is the {\em $\beta$-contraction} of
$((\lb x:T\mto t)~u)$ and, conversely, that $((\lb x:T\mto t)~u)$
is the {\em $\beta$-expansion} of $\subst{t}{x}{u}$.
According to $\beta$-reduction, terms of the {\em Calculus of
Inductive Constructions} enjoy some fundamental properties such as
confluence, strong normalization, subject reduction. These results are
theoretically of great importance but we will not detail them here and
refer the interested reader to \cite{Coq85}.
\paragraph[$\iota$-reduction.]{$\iota$-reduction.\label{iota}\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}}
A specific conversion rule is associated to the inductive objects in
the global environment. We shall give later on (see Section~\ref{iotared}) the
precise rules but it just says that a destructor applied to an object
built from a constructor behaves as expected. This reduction is
called $\iota$-reduction and is more precisely studied in
\cite{Moh93,Wer94}.
\paragraph[$\delta$-reduction.]{$\delta$-reduction.\label{delta}\index{delta-reduction@$\delta$-reduction}}
We may have variables defined in local contexts or constants defined in the global
environment. It is legal to identify such a reference with its value,
that is to expand (or unfold) it into its value. This
reduction is called $\delta$-reduction and shows as follows.
$$\WTEGRED{x}{\triangleright_{\delta}}{t}~~~~~\mbox{if $(x:=t:T) \in \Gamma$}~~~~~~~~~\WTEGRED{c}{\triangleright_{\delta}}{t}~~~~~\mbox{if $(c:=t:T) \in E$}$$
\paragraph[$\zeta$-reduction.]{$\zeta$-reduction.\label{zeta}\index{zeta-reduction@$\zeta$-reduction}}
{\Coq} allows also to remove local definitions occurring in terms by
replacing the defined variable by its value. The declaration being
destroyed, this reduction differs from $\delta$-reduction. It is
called $\zeta$-reduction and shows as follows.
$$\WTEGRED{\kw{let}~x:=u~\kw{in}~t}{\triangleright_{\zeta}}{\subst{t}{x}{u}}$$
\paragraph{$\eta$-expansion.%
\label{eta}%
\index{eta-expansion@$\eta$-expansion}%
%\index{eta-reduction@$\eta$-reduction}
}%
Another important concept is $\eta$-expansion. It is legal to identify any
term $t$ of functional type $\forall x:T, U$ with its so-called
$\eta$-expansion $\lb x:T\mto (t\ x)$ for $x$ an arbitrary variable
name fresh in $t$.
\Rem We deliberately do not define $\eta$-reduction:
\def\noeta{\hskip-.1em\not\triangleright_\eta}
$$\lb x:T\mto (t\ x)\hskip.1em\noeta\hskip.3em t$$
This is because, in general, the type of $t$ need not to be convertible to the type of $\lb x:T\mto (t\ x)$.
E.g., if we take $f$ such that:
$$f\hskip.5em:\hskip.5em\forall x:Type(2),Type(1)$$
then
$$\lb x:Type(1),(f\, x)\hskip.5em:\hskip.5em\forall x:Type(1),Type(1)$$
We could not allow
$$\lb x:Type(1),(f\,x)\hskip.5em\noeta\hskip.6em f$$
because the type of the reduced term $\forall x:Type(2),Type(1)$
would not be convertible to the type of the original term $\forall x:Type(1),Type(1)$.
\paragraph[Convertibility.]{Convertibility.\label{convertibility}
\index{beta-reduction@$\beta$-reduction}\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}\index{delta-reduction@$\delta$-reduction}\index{zeta-reduction@$\zeta$-reduction}}
Let us write $\WTEGRED{t}{\triangleright}{u}$ for the contextual closure of the relation $t$ reduces to $u$ in the global environment $E$ and local context $\Gamma$ with one of the previous reduction $\beta$, $\iota$, $\delta$ or $\zeta$.
We say that two terms $t_1$ and $t_2$ are {\em
$\beta\iota\delta\zeta\eta$-convertible}, or simply {\em
convertible}, or {\em equivalent}, in the global environment $E$ and
local context $\Gamma$ iff there exist terms $u_1$ and $u_2$ such that
$\WTEGRED{t_1}{\triangleright \ldots \triangleright}{u_1}$ and
$\WTEGRED{t_2}{\triangleright \ldots \triangleright}{u_2}$ and either
$u_1$ and $u_2$ are identical, or they are convertible up to
$\eta$-expansion, i.e. $u_1$ is $\lb x:T\mto u'_1$ and $u_2\,x$ is
recursively convertible to $u'_1$, or, symmetrically, $u_2$ is $\lb
x:T\mto u'_2$ and $u_1\,x$ is recursively convertible to $u'_2$. We
then write $\WTEGCONV{t_1}{t_2}$.
The convertibility relation allows introducing a new typing rule
which says that two convertible well-formed types have the same
inhabitants.
\section[Subtyping rules]{Subtyping rules\index{Subtyping rules}
\label{subtyping-rules}}
At the moment, we did not take into account one rule between universes
which says that any term in a universe of index $i$ is also a term in
the universe of index $i+1$ (this is the {\em cumulativity} rule of
{\CIC}). This property extends the equivalence relation of
convertibility into a {\em subtyping} relation inductively defined by:
\begin{enumerate}
\item if $\WTEGCONV{t}{u}$ then $\WTEGLECONV{t}{u}$,
\item if $i \leq j$ then $\WTEGLECONV{\Type(i)}{\Type(j)}$,
\item for any $i$, $\WTEGLECONV{\Set}{\Type(i)}$,
\item $\WTEGLECONV{\Prop}{\Set}$, hence, by transitivity,
$\WTEGLECONV{\Prop}{\Type(i)}$, for any $i$
\item if $\WTEGCONV{T}{U}$ and $\WTELECONV{\Gamma::(x:T)}{T'}{U'}$ then $\WTEGLECONV{\forall~x:T, T'}{\forall~x:U, U'}$.
\end{enumerate}
The conversion rule up to subtyping is now exactly:
\begin{description}\label{Conv}
\item[Conv]\index{Typing rules!Conv}
\inference{
\frac{\WTEG{U}{s}~~~~\WTEG{t}{T}~~~~\WTEGLECONV{T}{U}}{\WTEG{t}{U}}}
\end{description}
\paragraph[Normal form.]{Normal form.\index{Normal form}\label{Normal-form}\label{Head-normal-form}\index{Head normal form}}
A term which cannot be any more reduced is said to be in {\em normal
form}. There are several ways (or strategies) to apply the reduction
rules. Among them, we have to mention the {\em head reduction} which
will play an important role (see Chapter~\ref{Tactics}). Any term can
be written as $\lb x_1:T_1\mto \ldots \lb x_k:T_k \mto
(t_0\ t_1\ldots t_n)$ where
$t_0$ is not an application. We say then that $t_0$ is the {\em head
of $t$}. If we assume that $t_0$ is $\lb x:T\mto u_0$ then one step of
$\beta$-head reduction of $t$ is:
\[\lb x_1:T_1\mto \ldots \lb x_k:T_k\mto (\lb x:T\mto u_0\ t_1\ldots t_n)
~\triangleright ~ \lb (x_1:T_1)\ldots(x_k:T_k)\mto
(\subst{u_0}{x}{t_1}\ t_2 \ldots t_n)\]
Iterating the process of head reduction until the head of the reduced
term is no more an abstraction leads to the {\em $\beta$-head normal
form} of $t$:
\[ t \triangleright \ldots \triangleright
\lb x_1:T_1\mto \ldots\lb x_k:T_k\mto (v\ u_1
\ldots u_m)\]
where $v$ is not an abstraction (nor an application). Note that the
head normal form must not be confused with the normal form since some
$u_i$ can be reducible.
Similar notions of head-normal forms involving $\delta$, $\iota$ and $\zeta$
reductions or any combination of those can also be defined.
\section[Inductive definitions]{Inductive Definitions\label{Cic-inductive-definitions}}
% Here we assume that the reader knows what is an inductive definition.
Formally, we can represent any {\em inductive definition\index{definition!inductive}} as \Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} where:
\begin{itemize}
\item $\Gamma_I$ determines the names and types of inductive types;
\item $\Gamma_C$ determines the names and types of constructors of these inductive types;
\item $p$ determines the number of parameters of these inductive types.
\end{itemize}
These inductive definitions, together with global assumptions and global definitions, then form the global environment.
\vskip.5em
\noindent Additionally, for any $p$ there always exists $\Gamma_P=[a_1:A_1;\dots;a_p:A_p]$
such that each $(t:T)\in\Gamma_I\cup\Gamma_C$ can be written as:
$\forall\Gamma_P, T^\prime$.
\vskip.5em
\noindent $\Gamma_P$ is called {\em context of parameters\index{context of parameters}}.
\subsection*{Examples}
If we take the following inductive definition (denoted in concrete syntax):
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive bool : Set :=
| true : bool
| false : bool.
\end{coq_example*}
then:
\def\colon{@{\hskip.5em:\hskip.5em}}
\def\GammaI{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\bool & \Set
\end{array}
\right]}
\def\GammaC{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\true & \bool\\
\false & \bool
\end{array}
\right]}
\newcommand\ind[3]{$\mathsf{Ind}~[#1]\left(\hskip-.4em
\begin{array}{r @{\mathrm{~:=~}} l}
#2 & #3 \\
\end{array}
\hskip-.4em
\right)$}
\begin{itemize}
\item $p = 0$
\item $\Gamma_I = \GammaI$
\item $\Gamma_C = \GammaC$
\end{itemize}
and thus it enriches the global environment with the following entry:
\vskip.5em
\ind{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
\vskip.5em
\noindent that is:
\vskip.5em
\ind{0}{\GammaI}{\GammaC}
\vskip.5em
\noindent In this case, $\Gamma_P=[\,]$.
\vskip1em\hrule\vskip1em
\noindent If we take the followig inductive definition:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive nat : Set :=
| O : nat
| S : nat -> nat.
\end{coq_example*}
then:
\def\GammaI{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\nat & \Set
\end{array}
\right]}
\def\GammaC{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\nO & \nat\\
\nS & \nat\ra\nat
\end{array}
\right]}
\begin{itemize}
\item $p = 0$
\item $\Gamma_I = \GammaI$
\item $\Gamma_C = \GammaC$
\end{itemize}
and thus it enriches the global environment with the following entry:
\vskip.5em
\ind{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
\vskip.5em
\noindent that is:
\vskip.5em
\ind{0}{\GammaI}{\GammaC}
\vskip.5em
\noindent In this case, $\Gamma_P=[\,]$.
\vskip1em\hrule\vskip1em
\noindent If we take the following inductive definition:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive list (A : Type) : Type :=
| nil : list A
| cons : A -> list A -> list A.
\end{coq_example*}
then:
\def\GammaI{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\List & \Type\ra\Type
\end{array}
\right]}
\def\GammaC{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\Nil & \forall~A\!:\!\Type,~\List~A\\
\cons & \forall~A\!:\!\Type,~A\ra\List~A\ra\List~A
\end{array}
\right]}
\begin{itemize}
\item $p = 1$
\item $\Gamma_I = \GammaI$
\item $\Gamma_C = \GammaC$
\end{itemize}
and thus it enriches the global environment with the following entry:
\vskip.5em
\ind{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
\vskip.5em
\noindent that is:
\vskip.5em
\ind{1}{\GammaI}{\GammaC}
\vskip.5em
\noindent In this case, $\Gamma_P=[A:\Type]$.
\vskip1em\hrule\vskip1em
\noindent If we take the following inductive definition:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive even : nat -> Prop :=
| even_O : even 0
| even_S : forall n, odd n -> even (S n)
with odd : nat -> Prop :=
| odd_S : forall n, even n -> odd (S n).
\end{coq_example*}
then:
\def\GammaI{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\even & \nat\ra\Prop \\
\odd & \nat\ra\Prop
\end{array}
\right]}
\def\GammaC{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\evenO & \even~\nO \\
\evenS & \forall n : \nat, \odd~n \ra \even~(\nS~n)
\end{array}
\right]}
\begin{itemize}
\item $p = 1$
\item $\Gamma_I = \GammaI$
\item $\Gamma_C = \GammaC$
\end{itemize}
and thus it enriches the global environment with the following entry:
\vskip.5em
\ind{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
\vskip.5em
\noindent that is:
\vskip.5em
\ind{1}{\GammaI}{\GammaC}
\vskip.5em
\noindent In this case, $\Gamma_P=[A:\Type]$.
\vskip1em\hrule\vskip1em
\noindent If we take the following inductive definition:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive has_length (A : Type) : list A -> nat -> Prop :=
| nil_hl : has_length A (nil A) O
| cons_hl : forall (a:A) (l:list A) (n:nat),
has_length A l n -> has_length A (cons A a l) (S n).
\end{coq_example*}
then:
\def\GammaI{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\haslength & \forall~A\!:\!\Type,~\List~A\ra\nat\ra\Prop
\end{array}
\right]}
\def\GammaC{\left[\begin{array}{r c l}
\nilhl & \hskip.1em:\hskip.1em & \forall~A\!:\!\Type,~\haslength~A~(\Nil~A)~\nO\\
\conshl & \hskip.1em:\hskip.1em & \forall~A\!:\!\Type,~\forall~a\!:\!A,~\forall~l\!:\!\List~A,~\forall~n\!:\!\nat,\\
& & \haslength~A~l~n\ra \haslength~A~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~n)
\end{array}
\right]}
\begin{itemize}
\item $p = 1$
\item $\Gamma_I = \GammaI$
\item $\Gamma_C = \GammaC$
\end{itemize}
and thus it enriches the global environment with the following entry:
\vskip.5em
\ind{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
%\vskip.5em
%\noindent that is:
%\vskip.5em
%\ind{1}{\GammaI}{\GammaC}
\vskip.5em
\noindent In this case, $\Gamma_P=[A:\Type]$.
\vskip1em\hrule\vskip1em
\noindent If we take the following inductive definition:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive tree : Set :=
| node : forest -> tree
with forest : Set :=
| emptyf : forest
| consf : tree -> forest -> forest.
\end{coq_example*}
then:
\def\GammaI{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\tree & \Set\\
\forest & \Set
\end{array}
\right]}
\def\GammaC{\left[\begin{array}{r \colon l}
\node & \forest\ra\tree\\
\emptyf & \forest\\
\consf & \tree\ra\forest\ra\forest
\end{array}
\right]}
\begin{itemize}
\item $p = 0$
\item $\Gamma_I = \GammaI$
\item $\Gamma_C = \GammaC$
\end{itemize}
and thus it enriches the global environment with the following entry:
\vskip.5em
\ind{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
\vskip.5em
\noindent that is:
\vskip.5em
\ind{0}{\GammaI}{\GammaC}
\vskip.5em
\noindent In this case, $\Gamma_P=[\,]$.
\subsection{Types of inductive objects}
We have to give the type of constants in a global environment $E$ which
contains an inductive declaration.
\begin{description}
\item[Ind] \index{Typing rules!Ind}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}\hskip2em\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} \in E\hskip2em(a:A)\in\Gamma_I}{\WTEG{a}{A}}}
\item[Constr] \index{Typing rules!Constr}
\inference{\frac{\WFE{\Gamma}\hskip2em\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} \in E\hskip2em(c:C)\in\Gamma_C}{\WTEG{c}{C}}}
\end{description}
\paragraph{Example.}
Provided that our environment $E$ contains inductive definitions we showed before,
these two inference rules above enable us to conclude that:
\vskip.5em
\def\prefix{E[\Gamma]\vdash\hskip.25em}
$\begin{array}{@{} l}
\prefix\even : \nat\ra\Prop\\
\prefix\odd : \nat\ra\Prop\\
\prefix\evenO : \even~\nO\\
\prefix\evenS : \forall~n:\nat, \odd~n \ra \even~(\nS~n)\\
\prefix\oddS : \forall~n:\nat, \even~n \ra \odd~(\nS~n)
\end{array}$
%\paragraph{Parameters.}
%%The parameters introduce a distortion between the inside specification
%%of the inductive declaration where parameters are supposed to be
%%instantiated (this representation is appropriate for checking the
%%correctness or deriving the destructor principle) and the outside
%%typing rules where the inductive objects are seen as objects
%%abstracted with respect to the parameters.
%In the definition of \List\ or \haslength\, $A$ is a parameter because
%what is effectively inductively defined is $\ListA$ or $\haslengthA$ for
%a given $A$ which is constant in the type of constructors. But when
%we define $(\haslengthA~l~n)$, $l$ and $n$ are not parameters because the
%constructors manipulate different instances of this family.
\subsection{Well-formed inductive definitions}
We cannot accept any inductive declaration because some of them lead
to inconsistent systems.
% TODO: The statement above deserves explanation.
We restrict ourselves to definitions which
satisfy a syntactic criterion of positivity. Before giving the formal
rules, we need a few definitions:
\paragraph[Definition]{Definition\index{Arity}\label{Arity}}
A type $T$ is an {\em arity of sort $s$} if it converts
to the sort $s$ or to a product $\forall~x:T,U$ with $U$ an arity
of sort $s$.
\paragraph[Examples]{Examples}
$A\ra \Set$ is an arity of sort $\Set$.
$\forall~A:\Prop,A\ra \Prop$ is an arity of sort \Prop.
\paragraph[Definition]{Definition}
A type $T$ is an {\em arity} if there is a $s\in\Sort$
such that $T$ is an arity of sort $s$.
\paragraph[Examples]{Examples}
$A\ra \Set$ and $\forall~A:\Prop,A\ra \Prop$ are arities.
\paragraph[Definition]{Definition\index{type of constructor}}
We say that $T$ is a {\em type of constructor of $I$\index{type of constructor}}
in one of the following two cases:
\begin{itemize}
\item $T$ is $(I~t_1\ldots ~t_n)$
\item $T$ is $\forall x:U,T^\prime$ where $T^\prime$ is also a type of constructor of $I$
\end{itemize}
% QUESTION: Are we above sufficiently precise?
% Shouldn't we say also what is "n"?
% "n" couldn't be "0", could it?
\paragraph[Examples]{Examples}
$\nat$ and $\nat\ra\nat$ are types of constructors of $\nat$.\\
$\forall A:\Type,\List~A$ and $\forall A:\Type,A\ra\List~A\ra\List~A$ are constructors of $\List$.
\paragraph[Definition]{Definition\index{Positivity}\label{Positivity}}
The type of constructor $T$ will be said to {\em satisfy the positivity
condition} for a constant $X$ in the following cases:
% QUESTION: Why is this property called "positivity"?
\begin{itemize}
\item $T=(X~t_1\ldots ~t_n)$ and $X$ does not occur free in
% QUESTIONS: What is the meaning of 'n' above?
any $t_i$
\item $T=\forall~x:U,V$ and $X$ occurs only strictly positively in $U$ and
the type $V$ satisfies the positivity condition for $X$
\end{itemize}
The constant $X$ {\em occurs strictly positively} in $T$ in the
following cases:
\begin{itemize}
\item $X$ does not occur in $T$
\item $T$ converts to $(X~t_1 \ldots ~t_n)$ and $X$ does not occur in
% QUESTIONS: What is the meaning of 'n' above?
any of $t_i$
\item $T$ converts to $\forall~x:U,V$ and $X$ does not occur in
type $U$ but occurs strictly positively in type $V$
\item $T$ converts to $(I~a_1 \ldots ~a_m ~ t_1 \ldots ~t_p)$ where
% QUESTIONS: What is the meaning of 'p' above?
$I$ is the name of an inductive declaration of the form
$\Ind{\Gamma}{m}{I:A}{c_1:\forall p_1:P_1,\ldots \forall
p_m:P_m,C_1;\ldots;c_n:\forall p_1:P_1,\ldots \forall
p_m:P_m,C_n}$
(in particular, it is not mutually defined and it has $m$
parameters) and $X$ does not occur in any of the $t_i$, and the
(instantiated) types of constructor $C_i\{p_j/a_j\}_{j=1\ldots m}$
of $I$ satisfy
the nested positivity condition for $X$
%\item more generally, when $T$ is not a type, $X$ occurs strictly
%positively in $T[x:U]u$ if $X$ does not occur in $U$ but occurs
%strictly positively in $u$
\end{itemize}
The type of constructor $T$ of $I$ {\em satisfies the nested
positivity condition} for a constant $X$ in the following
cases:
\begin{itemize}
\item $T=(I~b_1\ldots b_m~u_1\ldots ~u_{p})$, $I$ is an inductive
definition with $m$ parameters and $X$ does not occur in
any $u_i$
% QUESTIONS: What is the meaning of 'p' above?
\item $T=\forall~x:U,V$ and $X$ occurs only strictly positively in $U$ and
the type $V$ satisfies the nested positivity condition for $X$
\end{itemize}
\newcommand\vv{\textSFxi} % │
\newcommand\hh{\textSFx} % ─
\newcommand\vh{\textSFviii} % ├
\newcommand\hv{\textSFii} % └
\newlength\framecharacterwidth
\settowidth\framecharacterwidth{\hh}
\newcommand\ws{\hbox{}\hskip\the\framecharacterwidth}
\newcommand\ruleref[1]{\hskip.25em\dots\hskip.2em{\em (bullet #1)}}
\paragraph{Example}~\\
\vskip-.5em
\noindent$X$ occurs strictly positively in $A\ra X$\ruleref5\\
\vv\\
\vh\hh\ws $X$does not occur in $A$\ruleref3\\
\vv\\
\hv\hh\ws $X$ occurs strictly positively in $X$\ruleref4
\paragraph{Example}~\\
\vskip-.5em
\noindent $X$ occurs strictly positively in $X*A$\\
\vv\\
\hv\hh $X$ occurs strictly positively in $(\Prod~X~A)$\ruleref6\\
\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\vv\ws\verb|Inductive prod (A B : Type) : Type :=|\\
\ws\ws\vv\ws\verb| pair : A -> B -> prod A B.|\\
\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\vh\hh $X$ does not occur in any (real) arguments of $\Prod$ in the original term $(\Prod~X~A)$\\
\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\hv\ws the (instantiated) type $\Prod~X~A$ of constructor $\Pair$,\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws satisfies the nested positivity condition for $X$\ruleref7\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\hv\ws $X$ does not occur in any (real) arguments of $(\Prod~X~A)$
\paragraph{Example}~\\
\vskip-.5em
\noindent $X$ occurs strictly positively in $\ListA$\ruleref6\\
\vv\\
\vv\ws\verb|Inductive list (A:Type) : Type :=|\\
\vv\ws\verb$ | nil : list A$\\
\vv\ws\verb$ | cons : A -> list A -> list A$\\
\vv\\
\vh\hh $X$ does not occur in any arguments of $\List$\\
\vv\\
\hv\hh\ws Every instantiated constructor of $\ListA$ satisfies the nested positivity condition for $X$\\
\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\vh\hh\ws concerning type $\ListA$ of constructor $\Nil$:\\
\ws\ws\ws\vv\ws\ws Type $\ListA$ of constructor $\Nil$ satisfies the nested positivity condition for $X$\\
\ws\ws\ws\vv\ws\ws because $X$ does not appear in any (real) arguments of the type of that constructor\\
\ws\ws\ws\vv\ws\ws (primarily because $\List$ does not have any (real) arguments)\ruleref7\\
\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\hv\hh\ws concerning type $\forall~A\ra\ListA\ra\ListA$ of constructor $\cons$:\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws Type $\forall~A:\Type,A\ra\ListA\ra\ListA$ of constructor $\cons$\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws satisfies the nested positivity condition for $X$\ruleref8\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vh\hh\ws $X$ occurs only strictly positively in $\Type$\ruleref3\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\hv\hh\ws $X$ satisfies the nested positivity condition for $A\ra\ListA\ra\ListA$\ruleref8\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vh\hh\ws $X$ occurs only strictly positively in $A$\ruleref3\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\hv\hh\ws $X$ satisfies the nested positivity condition for $\ListA\ra\ListA$\ruleref8\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vh\ws $X$ occurs only strictly positively in $\ListA$\ruleref3\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\vv\\
\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\ws\hv\ws $X$ satisfies the nested positivity condition for $\ListA$\ruleref7
\paragraph{Correctness rules.}
We shall now describe the rules allowing the introduction of a new
inductive definition.
\begin{description}
\item[W-Ind] Let $E$ be a global environment and
$\Gamma_P,\Gamma_I,\Gamma_C$ are contexts such that
$\Gamma_I$ is $[I_1:\forall \Gamma_P,A_1;\ldots;I_k:\forall
\Gamma_P,A_k]$ and $\Gamma_C$ is
$[c_1:\forall \Gamma_P,C_1;\ldots;c_n:\forall \Gamma_P,C_n]$.
\inference{
\frac{
(\WTE{\Gamma_P}{A_j}{s'_j})_{j=1\ldots k}
~~ (\WTE{\Gamma_I;\Gamma_P}{C_i}{s_{q_i}})_{i=1\ldots n}
}
{\WF{E;\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}}{\Gamma}}}
provided that the following side conditions hold:
\begin{itemize}
\item $k>0$ and all of $I_j$ and $c_i$ are distinct names for $j=1\ldots k$ and $i=1\ldots n$,
\item $p$ is the number of parameters of \NInd{}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
and $\Gamma_P$ is the context of parameters,
\item for $j=1\ldots k$ we have that $A_j$ is an arity of sort $s_j$ and $I_j
\notin \Gamma \cup E$,
\item for $i=1\ldots n$ we have that $C_i$ is a type of constructor of
$I_{q_i}$ which satisfies the positivity condition for $I_1 \ldots I_k$
and $c_i \notin \Gamma \cup E$.
\end{itemize}
\end{description}
One can remark that there is a constraint between the sort of the
arity of the inductive type and the sort of the type of its
constructors which will always be satisfied for the impredicative sort
{\Prop} but may fail to define inductive definition
on sort \Set{} and generate constraints between universes for
inductive definitions in the {\Type} hierarchy.
\paragraph{Examples.}
It is well known that existential quantifier can be encoded as an
inductive definition.
The following declaration introduces the second-order existential
quantifier $\exists X.P(X)$.
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive exProp (P:Prop->Prop) : Prop
:= exP_intro : forall X:Prop, P X -> exProp P.
\end{coq_example*}
The same definition on \Set{} is not allowed and fails:
% (********** The following is not correct and should produce **********)
% (*** Error: Large non-propositional inductive types must be in Type***)
\begin{coq_example}
Fail Inductive exSet (P:Set->Prop) : Set
:= exS_intro : forall X:Set, P X -> exSet P.
\end{coq_example}
It is possible to declare the same inductive definition in the
universe \Type.
The \texttt{exType} inductive definition has type $(\Type_i \ra\Prop)\ra
\Type_j$ with the constraint that the parameter \texttt{X} of \texttt{exT\_intro} has type $\Type_k$ with $k<j$ and $k\leq i$.
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive exType (P:Type->Prop) : Type
:= exT_intro : forall X:Type, P X -> exType P.
\end{coq_example*}
%We shall assume for the following definitions that, if necessary, we
%annotated the type of constructors such that we know if the argument
%is recursive or not. We shall write the type $(x:_R T)C$ if it is
%a recursive argument and $(x:_P T)C$ if the argument is not recursive.
\paragraph[Sort-polymorphism of inductive types.]{Sort-polymorphism of inductive types.\index{Sort-polymorphism of inductive types}}
\label{Sort-polymorphism-inductive}
Inductive types declared in {\Type} are
polymorphic over their arguments in {\Type}.
If $A$ is an arity of some sort and $s$ is a sort, we write $A_{/s}$ for the arity
obtained from $A$ by replacing its sort with $s$. Especially, if $A$
is well-typed in some global environment and local context, then $A_{/s}$ is typable
by typability of all products in the Calculus of Inductive Constructions.
The following typing rule is added to the theory.
\begin{description}
\item[Ind-Family] Let $\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}$ be an
inductive definition. Let $\Gamma_P = [p_1:P_1;\ldots;p_{p}:P_{p}]$
be its local context of parameters, $\Gamma_I = [I_1:\forall
\Gamma_P,A_1;\ldots;I_k:\forall \Gamma_P,A_k]$ its context of
definitions and $\Gamma_C = [c_1:\forall
\Gamma_P,C_1;\ldots;c_n:\forall \Gamma_P,C_n]$ its context of
constructors, with $c_i$ a constructor of $I_{q_i}$.
Let $m \leq p$ be the length of the longest prefix of parameters
such that the $m$ first arguments of all occurrences of all $I_j$ in
all $C_k$ (even the occurrences in the hypotheses of $C_k$) are
exactly applied to $p_1~\ldots~p_m$ ($m$ is the number of {\em
recursively uniform parameters} and the $p-m$ remaining parameters
are the {\em recursively non-uniform parameters}). Let $q_1$,
\ldots, $q_r$, with $0\leq r\leq m$, be a (possibly) partial
instantiation of the recursively uniform parameters of
$\Gamma_P$. We have:
\inference{\frac
{\left\{\begin{array}{l}
\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} \in E\\
(E[] \vdash q_l : P'_l)_{l=1\ldots r}\\
(\WTEGLECONV{P'_l}{\subst{P_l}{p_u}{q_u}_{u=1\ldots l-1}})_{l=1\ldots r}\\
1 \leq j \leq k
\end{array}
\right.}
{E[] \vdash (I_j\,q_1\,\ldots\,q_r:\forall [p_{r+1}:P_{r+1};\ldots;p_{p}:P_{p}], (A_j)_{/s_j})}
}
provided that the following side conditions hold:
\begin{itemize}
\item $\Gamma_{P'}$ is the context obtained from $\Gamma_P$ by
replacing each $P_l$ that is an arity with $P'_l$ for $1\leq l \leq r$ (notice that
$P_l$ arity implies $P'_l$ arity since $\WTEGLECONV{P'_l}{ \subst{P_l}{p_u}{q_u}_{u=1\ldots l-1}}$);
\item there are sorts $s_i$, for $1 \leq i \leq k$ such that, for
$\Gamma_{I'} = [I_1:\forall
\Gamma_{P'},(A_1)_{/s_1};\ldots;I_k:\forall \Gamma_{P'},(A_k)_{/s_k}]$
we have $(\WTE{\Gamma_{I'};\Gamma_{P'}}{C_i}{s_{q_i}})_{i=1\ldots n}$;
\item the sorts are such that all eliminations, to {\Prop}, {\Set} and
$\Type(j)$, are allowed (see section~\ref{elimdep}).
\end{itemize}
\end{description}
Notice that if $I_j\,q_1\,\ldots\,q_r$ is typable using the rules {\bf
Ind-Const} and {\bf App}, then it is typable using the rule {\bf
Ind-Family}. Conversely, the extended theory is not stronger than the
theory without {\bf Ind-Family}. We get an equiconsistency result by
mapping each $\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}$ occurring into a
given derivation into as many different inductive types and constructors
as the number of different (partial) replacements of sorts, needed for
this derivation, in the parameters that are arities (this is possible
because $\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}$ well-formed implies
that $\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_{I'}}{\Gamma_{C'}}$ is well-formed and
has the same allowed eliminations, where
$\Gamma_{I'}$ is defined as above and $\Gamma_{C'} = [c_1:\forall
\Gamma_{P'},C_1;\ldots;c_n:\forall \Gamma_{P'},C_n]$). That is,
the changes in the types of each partial instance
$q_1\,\ldots\,q_r$ can be characterized by the ordered sets of arity
sorts among the types of parameters, and to each signature is
associated a new inductive definition with fresh names. Conversion is
preserved as any (partial) instance $I_j\,q_1\,\ldots\,q_r$ or
$C_i\,q_1\,\ldots\,q_r$ is mapped to the names chosen in the specific
instance of $\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}$.
\newcommand{\Single}{\mbox{\textsf{Set}}}
In practice, the rule {\bf Ind-Family} is used by {\Coq} only when all the
inductive types of the inductive definition are declared with an arity whose
sort is in the $\Type$
hierarchy. Then, the polymorphism is over the parameters whose
type is an arity of sort in the {\Type} hierarchy.
The sort $s_j$ are
chosen canonically so that each $s_j$ is minimal with respect to the
hierarchy ${\Prop}\subset{\Set_p}\subset\Type$ where $\Set_p$ is
predicative {\Set}.
%and ${\Prop_u}$ is the sort of small singleton
%inductive types (i.e. of inductive types with one single constructor
%and that contains either proofs or inhabitants of singleton types
%only).
More precisely, an empty or small singleton inductive definition
(i.e. an inductive definition of which all inductive types are
singleton -- see paragraph~\ref{singleton}) is set in
{\Prop}, a small non-singleton inductive type is set in {\Set} (even
in case {\Set} is impredicative -- see Section~\ref{impredicativity}),
and otherwise in the {\Type} hierarchy.
% TODO: clarify the case of a partial application ??
Note that the side-condition about allowed elimination sorts in the
rule~{\bf Ind-Family} is just to avoid to recompute the allowed
elimination sorts at each instance of a pattern-matching (see
section~\ref{elimdep}).
As an example, let us consider the following definition:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive option (A:Type) : Type :=
| None : option A
| Some : A -> option A.
\end{coq_example*}
As the definition is set in the {\Type} hierarchy, it is used
polymorphically over its parameters whose types are arities of a sort
in the {\Type} hierarchy. Here, the parameter $A$ has this property,
hence, if \texttt{option} is applied to a type in {\Set}, the result is
in {\Set}. Note that if \texttt{option} is applied to a type in {\Prop},
then, the result is not set in \texttt{Prop} but in \texttt{Set}
still. This is because \texttt{option} is not a singleton type (see
section~\ref{singleton}) and it would loose the elimination to {\Set} and
{\Type} if set in {\Prop}.
\begin{coq_example}
Check (fun A:Set => option A).
Check (fun A:Prop => option A).
\end{coq_example}
Here is another example.
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive prod (A B:Type) : Type := pair : A -> B -> prod A B.
\end{coq_example*}
As \texttt{prod} is a singleton type, it will be in {\Prop} if applied
twice to propositions, in {\Set} if applied twice to at least one type
in {\Set} and none in {\Type}, and in {\Type} otherwise. In all cases,
the three kind of eliminations schemes are allowed.
\begin{coq_example}
Check (fun A:Set => prod A).
Check (fun A:Prop => prod A A).
Check (fun (A:Prop) (B:Set) => prod A B).
Check (fun (A:Type) (B:Prop) => prod A B).
\end{coq_example}
\subsection{Destructors}
The specification of inductive definitions with arities and
constructors is quite natural. But we still have to say how to use an
object in an inductive type.
This problem is rather delicate. There are actually several different
ways to do that. Some of them are logically equivalent but not always
equivalent from the computational point of view or from the user point
of view.
From the computational point of view, we want to be able to define a
function whose domain is an inductively defined type by using a
combination of case analysis over the possible constructors of the
object and recursion.
Because we need to keep a consistent theory and also we prefer to keep
a strongly normalizing reduction, we cannot accept any sort of
recursion (even terminating). So the basic idea is to restrict
ourselves to primitive recursive functions and functionals.
For instance, assuming a parameter $A:\Set$ exists in the local context, we
want to build a function \length\ of type $\ListA\ra \nat$ which
computes the length of the list, so such that $(\length~(\Nil~A)) = \nO$
and $(\length~(\cons~A~a~l)) = (\nS~(\length~l))$. We want these
equalities to be recognized implicitly and taken into account in the
conversion rule.
From the logical point of view, we have built a type family by giving
a set of constructors. We want to capture the fact that we do not
have any other way to build an object in this type. So when trying to
prove a property about an object $m$ in an inductive definition it is
enough to enumerate all the cases where $m$ starts with a different
constructor.
In case the inductive definition is effectively a recursive one, we
want to capture the extra property that we have built the smallest
fixed point of this recursive equation. This says that we are only
manipulating finite objects. This analysis provides induction
principles.
For instance, in order to prove $\forall l:\ListA,(\haslengthA~l~(\length~l))$
it is enough to prove:
\noindent $(\haslengthA~(\Nil~A)~(\length~(\Nil~A)))$ and
\smallskip
$\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, (\haslengthA~l~(\length~l)) \ra
(\haslengthA~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\length~(\cons~A~a~l)))$.
\smallskip
\noindent which given the conversion equalities satisfied by \length\ is the
same as proving:
$(\haslengthA~(\Nil~A)~\nO)$ and $\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA,
(\haslengthA~l~(\length~l)) \ra
(\haslengthA~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~(\length~l)))$.
One conceptually simple way to do that, following the basic scheme
proposed by Martin-L\"of in his Intuitionistic Type Theory, is to
introduce for each inductive definition an elimination operator. At
the logical level it is a proof of the usual induction principle and
at the computational level it implements a generic operator for doing
primitive recursion over the structure.
But this operator is rather tedious to implement and use. We choose in
this version of {\Coq} to factorize the operator for primitive recursion
into two more primitive operations as was first suggested by Th. Coquand
in~\cite{Coq92}. One is the definition by pattern-matching. The second one is a definition by guarded fixpoints.
\subsubsection[The {\tt match\ldots with \ldots end} construction.]{The {\tt match\ldots with \ldots end} construction.\label{Caseexpr}
\index{match@{\tt match\ldots with\ldots end}}}
The basic idea of this operator is that we have an object
$m$ in an inductive type $I$ and we want to prove a property
which possibly depends on $m$. For this, it is enough to prove the
property for $m = (c_i~u_1\ldots u_{p_i})$ for each constructor of $I$.
The basic idea of this operator is that we have an object
$m$ in an inductive type $I$ and we want to prove a property
which possibly depends on $m$. For this, it is enough to prove the
property for $m = (c_i~u_1\ldots u_{p_i})$ for each constructor of $I$.
The \Coq{} term for this proof will be written:
\[\kw{match}~m~\kw{with}~ (c_1~x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1}) \Ra f_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
(c_n~x_{n1}~...~x_{np_n}) \Ra f_n~ \kw{end}\]
In this expression, if
$m$ eventually happens to evaluate to $(c_i~u_1\ldots u_{p_i})$ then
the expression will behave as specified in its $i$-th branch and
it will reduce to $f_i$ where the $x_{i1}$\ldots $x_{ip_i}$ are replaced
by the $u_1\ldots u_p$ according to the $\iota$-reduction.
Actually, for type-checking a \kw{match\ldots with\ldots end}
expression we also need to know the predicate $P$ to be proved by case
analysis. In the general case where $I$ is an inductively defined
$n$-ary relation, $P$ is a predicate over $n+1$ arguments: the $n$ first ones
correspond to the arguments of $I$ (parameters excluded), and the last
one corresponds to object $m$. \Coq{} can sometimes infer this
predicate but sometimes not. The concrete syntax for describing this
predicate uses the \kw{as\ldots in\ldots return} construction. For
instance, let us assume that $I$ is an unary predicate with one
parameter. The predicate is made explicit using the syntax:
\[\kw{match}~m~\kw{as}~ x~ \kw{in}~ I~\verb!_!~a~ \kw{return}~ P
~\kw{with}~ (c_1~x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1}) \Ra f_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
(c_n~x_{n1}~...~x_{np_n}) \Ra f_n \kw{end}\]
The \kw{as} part can be omitted if either the result type does not
depend on $m$ (non-dependent elimination) or $m$ is a variable (in
this case, $m$ can occur in $P$ where it is considered a bound variable).
The \kw{in} part can be
omitted if the result type does not depend on the arguments of
$I$. Note that the arguments of $I$ corresponding to parameters
\emph{must} be \verb!_!, because the result type is not generalized to
all possible values of the parameters. The other arguments of $I$
(sometimes called indices in the litterature) have to be variables
($a$ above) and these variables can occur in $P$ and bound in it.
The expression after \kw{in}
must be seen as an \emph{inductive type pattern}. Notice that
expansion of implicit arguments and notations apply to this pattern.
For the purpose of presenting the inference rules, we use a more
compact notation:
\[ \Case{(\lb a x \mto P)}{m}{ \lb x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1} \mto f_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
\lb x_{n1}...x_{np_n} \mto f_n}\]
%% CP 06/06 Obsolete avec la nouvelle syntaxe et incompatible avec la
%% presentation theorique qui suit
% \paragraph{Non-dependent elimination.}
%
% When defining a function of codomain $C$ by case analysis over an
% object in an inductive type $I$, we build an object of type $I
% \ra C$. The minimality principle on an inductively defined logical
% predicate $I$ of type $A \ra \Prop$ is often used to prove a property
% $\forall x:A,(I~x)\ra (C~x)$. These are particular cases of the dependent
% principle that we stated before with a predicate which does not depend
% explicitly on the object in the inductive definition.
% For instance, a function testing whether a list is empty
% can be
% defined as:
% \[\kw{fun} l:\ListA \Ra \kw{match}~l~\kw{with}~ \Nil \Ra \true~
% |~(\cons~a~m) \Ra \false \kw{end}\]
% represented by
% \[\lb l:\ListA \mto\Case{\bool}{l}{\true~ |~ \lb a~m,~\false}\]
%\noindent {\bf Remark. }
% In the system \Coq\ the expression above, can be
% written without mentioning
% the dummy abstraction:
% \Case{\bool}{l}{\Nil~ \mbox{\tt =>}~\true~ |~ (\cons~a~m)~
% \mbox{\tt =>}~ \false}
\paragraph[Allowed elimination sorts.]{Allowed elimination sorts.\index{Elimination sorts}}
An important question for building the typing rule for \kw{match} is
what can be the type of $\lb a x \mto P$ with respect to the type of the inductive
definitions.
We define now a relation \compat{I:A}{B} between an inductive
definition $I$ of type $A$ and an arity $B$. This relation states that
an object in the inductive definition $I$ can be eliminated for
proving a property $\lb a x \mto P$ of type $B$.
The case of inductive definitions in sorts \Set\ or \Type{} is simple.
There is no restriction on the sort of the predicate to be
eliminated.
\paragraph{Notations.}
The \compat{I:A}{B} is defined as the smallest relation satisfying the
following rules:
We write \compat{I}{B} for \compat{I:A}{B} where $A$ is the type of
$I$.
\begin{description}
\item[Prod] \inference{\frac{\compat{(I~x):A'}{B'}}
{\compat{I:\forall x:A, A'}{\forall x:A, B'}}}
\item[{\Set} \& \Type] \inference{\frac{
s_1 \in \{\Set,\Type(j)\},
s_2 \in \Sort}{\compat{I:s_1}{I\ra s_2}}}
\end{description}
The case of Inductive definitions of sort \Prop{} is a bit more
complicated, because of our interpretation of this sort. The only
harmless allowed elimination, is the one when predicate $P$ is also of
sort \Prop.
\begin{description}
\item[\Prop] \inference{\compat{I:\Prop}{I\ra\Prop}}
\end{description}
\Prop{} is the type of logical propositions, the proofs of properties
$P$ in \Prop{} could not be used for computation and are consequently
ignored by the extraction mechanism.
Assume $A$ and $B$ are two propositions, and the logical disjunction
$A\vee B$ is defined inductively by:
\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive or (A B:Prop) : Prop :=
or_introl : A -> or A B | or_intror : B -> or A B.
\end{coq_example*}
The following definition which computes a boolean value by case over
the proof of \texttt{or A B} is not accepted:
% (***************************************************************)
% (*** This example should fail with ``Incorrect elimination'' ***)
\begin{coq_example}
Fail Definition choice (A B: Prop) (x:or A B) :=
match x with or_introl _ _ a => true | or_intror _ _ b => false end.
\end{coq_example}
From the computational point of view, the structure of the proof of
\texttt{(or A B)} in this term is needed for computing the boolean
value.
In general, if $I$ has type \Prop\ then $P$ cannot have type $I\ra
\Set$, because it will mean to build an informative proof of type
$(P~m)$ doing a case analysis over a non-computational object that
will disappear in the extracted program. But the other way is safe
with respect to our interpretation we can have $I$ a computational
object and $P$ a non-computational one, it just corresponds to proving
a logical property of a computational object.
% Also if $I$ is in one of the sorts \{\Prop, \Set\}, one cannot in
% general allow an elimination over a bigger sort such as \Type. But
% this operation is safe whenever $I$ is a {\em small inductive} type,
% which means that all the types of constructors of
% $I$ are small with the following definition:\\
% $(I~t_1\ldots t_s)$ is a {\em small type of constructor} and
% $\forall~x:T,C$ is a small type of constructor if $C$ is and if $T$
% has type \Prop\ or \Set. \index{Small inductive type}
% We call this particular elimination which gives the possibility to
% compute a type by induction on the structure of a term, a {\em strong
% elimination}\index{Strong elimination}.
In the same spirit, elimination on $P$ of type $I\ra
\Type$ cannot be allowed because it trivially implies the elimination
on $P$ of type $I\ra \Set$ by cumulativity. It also implies that there
is two proofs of the same property which are provably different,
contradicting the proof-irrelevance property which is sometimes a
useful axiom:
\begin{coq_example}
Axiom proof_irrelevance : forall (P : Prop) (x y : P), x=y.
\end{coq_example}
\begin{coq_eval}
Reset proof_irrelevance.
\end{coq_eval}
The elimination of an inductive definition of type \Prop\ on a
predicate $P$ of type $I\ra \Type$ leads to a paradox when applied to
impredicative inductive definition like the second-order existential
quantifier \texttt{exProp} defined above, because it give access to
the two projections on this type.
%\paragraph{Warning: strong elimination}
%\index{Elimination!Strong elimination}
%In previous versions of Coq, for a small inductive definition, only the
%non-informative strong elimination on \Type\ was allowed, because
%strong elimination on \Typeset\ was not compatible with the current
%extraction procedure. In this version, strong elimination on \Typeset\
%is accepted but a dummy element is extracted from it and may generate
%problems if extracted terms are explicitly used such as in the
%{\tt Program} tactic or when extracting ML programs.
\paragraph[Empty and singleton elimination]{Empty and singleton elimination\label{singleton}
\index{Elimination!Singleton elimination}
\index{Elimination!Empty elimination}}
There are special inductive definitions in \Prop\ for which more
eliminations are allowed.
\begin{description}
\item[\Prop-extended]
\inference{
\frac{I \mbox{~is an empty or singleton
definition}~~~s \in \Sort}{\compat{I:\Prop}{I\ra s}}
}
\end{description}
% A {\em singleton definition} has always an informative content,
% even if it is a proposition.
A {\em singleton
definition} has only one constructor and all the arguments of this
constructor have type \Prop. In that case, there is a canonical
way to interpret the informative extraction on an object in that type,
such that the elimination on any sort $s$ is legal. Typical examples are
the conjunction of non-informative propositions and the equality.
If there is an hypothesis $h:a=b$ in the local context, it can be used for
rewriting not only in logical propositions but also in any type.
% In that case, the term \verb!eq_rec! which was defined as an axiom, is
% now a term of the calculus.
\begin{coq_example}
Print eq_rec.
Extraction eq_rec.
\end{coq_example}
An empty definition has no constructors, in that case also,
elimination on any sort is allowed.
\paragraph{Type of branches.}
Let $c$ be a term of type $C$, we assume $C$ is a type of constructor
for an inductive definition $I$. Let $P$ be a term that represents the
property to be proved.
We assume $r$ is the number of parameters.
We define a new type \CI{c:C}{P} which represents the type of the
branch corresponding to the $c:C$ constructor.
\[
\begin{array}{ll}
\CI{c:(I_i~p_1\ldots p_r\ t_1 \ldots t_p)}{P} &\equiv (P~t_1\ldots ~t_p~c) \\[2mm]
\CI{c:\forall~x:T,C}{P} &\equiv \forall~x:T,\CI{(c~x):C}{P}
\end{array}
\]
We write \CI{c}{P} for \CI{c:C}{P} with $C$ the type of $c$.
\paragraph{Examples.}
For $\ListA$ the type of $P$ will be $\ListA\ra s$ for $s \in \Sort$. \\
$ \CI{(\cons~A)}{P} \equiv
\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA,(P~(\cons~A~a~l))$.
For $\haslengthA$, the type of $P$ will be
$\forall l:\ListA,\forall n:\nat, (\haslengthA~l~n)\ra \Prop$ and the expression
\CI{(\conshl~A)}{P} is defined as:\\
$\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat, \forall
h:(\haslengthA~l~n), (P~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~n)~(\conshl~A~a~l~n~l))$.\\
If $P$ does not depend on its third argument, we find the more natural
expression:\\
$\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat,
(\haslengthA~l~n)\ra(P~(\cons~A~a~l)~(\nS~n))$.
\paragraph{Typing rule.}
Our very general destructor for inductive definition enjoys the
following typing rule
% , where we write
% \[
% \Case{P}{c}{[x_{11}:T_{11}]\ldots[x_{1p_1}:T_{1p_1}]g_1\ldots
% [x_{n1}:T_{n1}]\ldots[x_{np_n}:T_{np_n}]g_n}
% \]
% for
% \[
% \Case{P}{c}{(c_1~x_{11}~...~x_{1p_1}) \Ra g_1 ~|~\ldots~|~
% (c_n~x_{n1}...x_{np_n}) \Ra g_n }
% \]
\begin{description}
\item[match] \label{elimdep} \index{Typing rules!match}
\inference{
\frac{\WTEG{c}{(I~q_1\ldots q_r~t_1\ldots t_s)}~~
\WTEG{P}{B}~~\compat{(I~q_1\ldots q_r)}{B}
~~
(\WTEG{f_i}{\CI{(c_{p_i}~q_1\ldots q_r)}{P}})_{i=1\ldots l}}
{\WTEG{\Case{P}{c}{f_1|\ldots |f_l}}{(P\ t_1\ldots t_s\ c)}}}%\\[3mm]
provided $I$ is an inductive type in a declaration
\Ind{}{r}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C} with
$\Gamma_C = [c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n]$ and $c_{p_1}\ldots c_{p_l}$ are the
only constructors of $I$.
\end{description}
\paragraph{Example.}
For \List\ and \haslength\ the typing rules for the {\tt match} expression
are (writing just $t:M$ instead of \WTEG{t}{M}, the global environment and
local context being the same in all the judgments).
\[\frac{l:\ListA~~P:\ListA\ra s~~~f_1:(P~(\Nil~A))~~
f_2:\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, (P~(\cons~A~a~l))}
{\Case{P}{l}{f_1~|~f_2}:(P~l)}\]
\[\frac{
\begin{array}[b]{@{}c@{}}
H:(\haslengthA~L~N) \\ P:\forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat, (\haslengthA~l~n)\ra
\Prop\\
f_1:(P~(\Nil~A)~\nO~\nilhl) \\
f_2:\forall a:A, \forall l:\ListA, \forall n:\nat, \forall
h:(\haslengthA~l~n), (P~(\cons~A~a~n)~(\nS~n)~(\conshl~A~a~l~n~h))
\end{array}}
{\Case{P}{H}{f_1~|~f_2}:(P~L~N~H)}\]
\paragraph[Definition of $\iota$-reduction.]{Definition of $\iota$-reduction.\label{iotared}
\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}}
We still have to define the $\iota$-reduction in the general case.
A $\iota$-redex is a term of the following form:
\[\Case{P}{(c_{p_i}~q_1\ldots q_r~a_1\ldots a_m)}{f_1|\ldots |
f_l}\]
with $c_{p_i}$ the $i$-th constructor of the inductive type $I$ with $r$
parameters.
The $\iota$-contraction of this term is $(f_i~a_1\ldots a_m)$ leading
to the general reduction rule:
\[ \Case{P}{(c_{p_i}~q_1\ldots q_r~a_1\ldots a_m)}{f_1|\ldots |
f_n} \triangleright_{\iota} (f_i~a_1\ldots a_m) \]
\subsection[Fixpoint definitions]{Fixpoint definitions\label{Fix-term} \index{Fix@{\tt Fix}}}
The second operator for elimination is fixpoint definition.
This fixpoint may involve several mutually recursive definitions.
The basic concrete syntax for a recursive set of mutually recursive
declarations is (with $\Gamma_i$ contexts):
\[\kw{fix}~f_1 (\Gamma_1) :A_1:=t_1~\kw{with} \ldots \kw{with}~ f_n
(\Gamma_n) :A_n:=t_n\]
The terms are obtained by projections from this set of declarations
and are written
\[\kw{fix}~f_1 (\Gamma_1) :A_1:=t_1~\kw{with} \ldots \kw{with}~ f_n
(\Gamma_n) :A_n:=t_n~\kw{for}~f_i\]
In the inference rules, we represent such a
term by
\[\Fix{f_i}{f_1:A_1':=t_1' \ldots f_n:A_n':=t_n'}\]
with $t_i'$ (resp. $A_i'$) representing the term $t_i$ abstracted
(resp. generalized) with
respect to the bindings in the context $\Gamma_i$, namely
$t_i'=\lb \Gamma_i \mto t_i$ and $A_i'=\forall \Gamma_i, A_i$.
\subsubsection{Typing rule}
The typing rule is the expected one for a fixpoint.
\begin{description}
\item[Fix] \index{Typing rules!Fix}
\inference{\frac{(\WTEG{A_i}{s_i})_{i=1\ldots n}~~~~
(\WTE{\Gamma,f_1:A_1,\ldots,f_n:A_n}{t_i}{A_i})_{i=1\ldots n}}
{\WTEG{\Fix{f_i}{f_1:A_1:=t_1 \ldots f_n:A_n:=t_n}}{A_i}}}
\end{description}
Any fixpoint definition cannot be accepted because non-normalizing terms
will lead to proofs of absurdity.
The basic scheme of recursion that should be allowed is the one needed for
defining primitive
recursive functionals. In that case the fixpoint enjoys a special
syntactic restriction, namely one of the arguments belongs to an
inductive type, the function starts with a case analysis and recursive
calls are done on variables coming from patterns and representing subterms.
For instance in the case of natural numbers, a proof of the induction
principle of type
\[\forall P:\nat\ra\Prop, (P~\nO)\ra(\forall n:\nat, (P~n)\ra(P~(\nS~n)))\ra
\forall n:\nat, (P~n)\]
can be represented by the term:
\[\begin{array}{l}
\lb P:\nat\ra\Prop\mto\lb f:(P~\nO)\mto \lb g:(\forall n:\nat,
(P~n)\ra(P~(\nS~n))) \mto\\
\Fix{h}{h:\forall n:\nat, (P~n):=\lb n:\nat\mto \Case{P}{n}{f~|~\lb
p:\nat\mto (g~p~(h~p))}}
\end{array}
\]
Before accepting a fixpoint definition as being correctly typed, we
check that the definition is ``guarded''. A precise analysis of this
notion can be found in~\cite{Gim94}.
The first stage is to precise on which argument the fixpoint will be
decreasing. The type of this argument should be an inductive
definition.
For doing this the syntax of fixpoints is extended and becomes
\[\Fix{f_i}{f_1/k_1:A_1:=t_1 \ldots f_n/k_n:A_n:=t_n}\]
where $k_i$ are positive integers.
Each $A_i$ should be a type (reducible to a term) starting with at least
$k_i$ products $\forall y_1:B_1,\ldots \forall y_{k_i}:B_{k_i}, A'_i$
and $B_{k_i}$
being an instance of an inductive definition.
Now in the definition $t_i$, if $f_j$ occurs then it should be applied
to at least $k_j$ arguments and the $k_j$-th argument should be
syntactically recognized as structurally smaller than $y_{k_i}$
The definition of being structurally smaller is a bit technical.
One needs first to define the notion of
{\em recursive arguments of a constructor}\index{Recursive arguments}.
For an inductive definition \Ind{}{r}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C},
the type of a constructor $c$ has the form
$\forall p_1:P_1,\ldots \forall p_r:P_r,
\forall x_1:T_1, \ldots \forall x_r:T_r, (I_j~p_1\ldots
p_r~t_1\ldots t_s)$ the recursive arguments will correspond to $T_i$ in
which one of the $I_l$ occurs.
The main rules for being structurally smaller are the following:\\
Given a variable $y$ of type an inductive
definition in a declaration
\Ind{}{r}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C}
where $\Gamma_I$ is $[I_1:A_1;\ldots;I_k:A_k]$, and $\Gamma_C$ is
$[c_1:C_1;\ldots;c_n:C_n]$.
The terms structurally smaller than $y$ are:
\begin{itemize}
\item $(t~u), \lb x:u \mto t$ when $t$ is structurally smaller than $y$ .
\item \Case{P}{c}{f_1\ldots f_n} when each $f_i$ is structurally
smaller than $y$. \\
If $c$ is $y$ or is structurally smaller than $y$, its type is an inductive
definition $I_p$ part of the inductive
declaration corresponding to $y$.
Each $f_i$ corresponds to a type of constructor $C_q \equiv
\forall p_1:P_1,\ldots,\forall p_r:P_r, \forall y_1:B_1, \ldots \forall y_k:B_k, (I~a_1\ldots a_k)$
and can consequently be
written $\lb y_1:B'_1\mto \ldots \lb y_k:B'_k\mto g_i$.
($B'_i$ is obtained from $B_i$ by substituting parameters variables)
the variables $y_j$ occurring
in $g_i$ corresponding to recursive arguments $B_i$ (the ones in
which one of the $I_l$ occurs) are structurally smaller than $y$.
\end{itemize}
The following definitions are correct, we enter them using the
{\tt Fixpoint} command as described in Section~\ref{Fixpoint} and show
the internal representation.
\begin{coq_example}
Fixpoint plus (n m:nat) {struct n} : nat :=
match n with
| O => m
| S p => S (plus p m)
end.
Print plus.
Fixpoint lgth (A:Set) (l:list A) {struct l} : nat :=
match l with
| nil _ => O
| cons _ a l' => S (lgth A l')
end.
Print lgth.
Fixpoint sizet (t:tree) : nat := let (f) := t in S (sizef f)
with sizef (f:forest) : nat :=
match f with
| emptyf => O
| consf t f => plus (sizet t) (sizef f)
end.
Print sizet.
\end{coq_example}
\subsubsection[Reduction rule]{Reduction rule\index{iota-reduction@$\iota$-reduction}}
Let $F$ be the set of declarations: $f_1/k_1:A_1:=t_1 \ldots
f_n/k_n:A_n:=t_n$.
The reduction for fixpoints is:
\[ (\Fix{f_i}{F}~a_1\ldots
a_{k_i}) \triangleright_{\iota} \substs{t_i}{f_k}{\Fix{f_k}{F}}{k=1\ldots n}
~a_1\ldots a_{k_i}\]
when $a_{k_i}$ starts with a constructor.
This last restriction is needed in order to keep strong normalization
and corresponds to the reduction for primitive recursive operators.
We can illustrate this behavior on examples.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall n m:nat, plus (S n) m = S (plus n m).
reflexivity.
Abort.
Goal forall f:forest, sizet (node f) = S (sizef f).
reflexivity.
Abort.
\end{coq_example}
But assuming the definition of a son function from \tree\ to \forest:
\begin{coq_example}
Definition sont (t:tree) : forest
:= let (f) := t in f.
\end{coq_example}
The following is not a conversion but can be proved after a case analysis.
% (******************************************************************)
% (** Error: Impossible to unify .... **)
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall t:tree, sizet t = S (sizef (sont t)).
Fail reflexivity.
destruct t.
reflexivity.
\end{coq_example}
\begin{coq_eval}
Abort.
\end{coq_eval}
% La disparition de Program devrait rendre la construction Match obsolete
% \subsubsection{The {\tt Match \ldots with \ldots end} expression}
% \label{Matchexpr}
% %\paragraph{A unary {\tt Match\ldots with \ldots end}.}
% \index{Match...with...end@{\tt Match \ldots with \ldots end}}
% The {\tt Match} operator which was a primitive notion in older
% presentations of the Calculus of Inductive Constructions is now just a
% macro definition which generates the good combination of {\tt Case}
% and {\tt Fix} operators in order to generate an operator for primitive
% recursive definitions. It always considers an inductive definition as
% a single inductive definition.
% The following examples illustrates this feature.
% \begin{coq_example}
% Definition nat_pr : (C:Set)C->(nat->C->C)->nat->C
% :=[C,x,g,n]Match n with x g end.
% Print nat_pr.
% \end{coq_example}
% \begin{coq_example}
% Definition forest_pr
% : (C:Set)C->(tree->forest->C->C)->forest->C
% := [C,x,g,n]Match n with x g end.
% \end{coq_example}
% Cet exemple faisait error (HH le 12/12/96), j'ai change pour une
% version plus simple
%\begin{coq_example}
%Definition forest_pr
% : (P:forest->Set)(P emptyf)->((t:tree)(f:forest)(P f)->(P (consf t f)))
% ->(f:forest)(P f)
% := [C,x,g,n]Match n with x g end.
%\end{coq_example}
\subsubsection{Mutual induction}
The principles of mutual induction can be automatically generated
using the {\tt Scheme} command described in Section~\ref{Scheme}.
\section{Admissible rules for global environments}
From the original rules of the type system, one can show the
admissibility of rules which change the local context of definition of
objects in the global environment. We show here the admissible rules
that are used used in the discharge mechanism at the end of a section.
% This is obsolete: Abstraction over defined constants actually uses a
% let-in since there are let-ins in Coq
%% \paragraph{Mechanism of substitution.}
%% One rule which can be proved valid, is to replace a term $c$ by its
%% value in the global environment. As we defined the substitution of a term for
%% a variable in a term, one can define the substitution of a term for a
%% constant. One easily extends this substitution to local contexts and global
%% environments.
%% \paragraph{Substitution Property:}
%% \inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:=t:T; E'}{\Gamma}}
%% {\WF{E; \subst{E'}{c}{t}}{\subst{\Gamma}{c}{t}}}}
\paragraph{Abstraction.}
One can modify a global declaration by generalizing it over a
previously assumed constant $c$. For doing that, we need to modify the
reference to the global declaration in the subsequent global
environment and local context by explicitly applying this constant to
the constant $c'$.
Below, if $\Gamma$ is a context of the form
$[y_1:A_1;\ldots;y_n:A_n]$, we write $\forall
x:U,\subst{\Gamma}{c}{x}$ to mean
$[y_1:\forall~x:U,\subst{A_1}{c}{x};\ldots;y_n:\forall~x:U,\subst{A_n}{c}{x}]$
and
$\subst{E}{|\Gamma|}{|\Gamma|c}$.
to mean the parallel substitution
$\subst{\subst{E}{y_1}{(y_1~c)}\ldots}{y_n}{(y_n~c)}$.
\paragraph{First abstracting property:}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:U;E';c':=t:T;E''}{\Gamma}}
{\WF{E;c:U;E';c':=\lb x:U\mto \subst{t}{c}{x}:\forall~x:U,\subst{T}{c}{x};
\subst{E''}{c'}{(c'~c)}}{\subst{\Gamma}{c}{(c~c')}}}}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:U;E';c':T;E''}{\Gamma}}
{\WF{E;c:U;E';c':\forall~x:U,\subst{T}{c}{x};
\subst{E''}{c'}{(c'~c)}}{\subst{\Gamma}{c}{(c~c')}}}}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:U;E';\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C};E''}{\Gamma}}
{\WFTWOLINES{E;c:U;E';\Ind{}{p+1}{\forall x:U,\subst{\Gamma_I}{c}{x}}{\forall x:U,\subst{\Gamma_C}{c}{x}};\subst{E''}{|\Gamma_I,\Gamma_C|}{|\Gamma_I,\Gamma_C|~c}}{\subst{\Gamma}{|\Gamma_I,\Gamma_C|}{|\Gamma_I,\Gamma_C|~c}}}}
One can similarly modify a global declaration by generalizing it over
a previously defined constant~$c'$. Below, if $\Gamma$ is a context
of the form $[y_1:A_1;\ldots;y_n:A_n]$, we write $
\subst{\Gamma}{c}{u}$ to mean
$[y_1:\subst{A_1}{c}{u};\ldots;y_n:\subst{A_n}{c}{u}]$.
\paragraph{Second abstracting property:}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:=u:U;E';c':=t:T;E''}{\Gamma}}
{\WF{E;c:=u:U;E';c':=(\letin{x}{u:U}{\subst{t}{c}{x}}):\subst{T}{c}{u};E''}{\Gamma}}}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:=u:U;E';c':T;E''}{\Gamma}}
{\WF{E;c:=u:U;E';c':\subst{T}{c}{u};E''}{\Gamma}}}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:=u:U;E';\Ind{}{p}{\Gamma_I}{\Gamma_C};E''}{\Gamma}}
{\WF{E;c:=u:U;E';\Ind{}{p}{\subst{\Gamma_I}{c}{u}}{\subst{\Gamma_C}{c}{u}};E''}{\Gamma}}}
\paragraph{Pruning the local context.}
If one abstracts or substitutes constants with the above rules then it
may happen that some declared or defined constant does not occur any
more in the subsequent global environment and in the local context. One can
consequently derive the following property.
\paragraph{First pruning property:}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:U;E'}{\Gamma} \qquad c \mbox{ does not occur in $E'$ and $\Gamma$}}
{\WF{E;E'}{\Gamma}}}
\paragraph{Second pruning property:}
\inference{\frac{\WF{E;c:=u:U;E'}{\Gamma} \qquad c \mbox{ does not occur in $E'$ and $\Gamma$}}
{\WF{E;E'}{\Gamma}}}
\section{Co-inductive types}
The implementation contains also co-inductive definitions, which are
types inhabited by infinite objects.
More information on co-inductive definitions can be found
in~\cite{Gimenez95b,Gim98,GimCas05}.
%They are described in Chapter~\ref{Co-inductives}.
\section[The Calculus of Inductive Construction with
impredicative \Set]{The Calculus of Inductive Construction with
impredicative \Set\label{impredicativity}}
\Coq{} can be used as a type-checker for the
Calculus of Inductive Constructions with an impredicative sort \Set{}
by using the compiler option \texttt{-impredicative-set}.
For example, using the ordinary \texttt{coqtop} command, the following
is rejected.
% (** This example should fail *******************************
% Error: The term forall X:Set, X -> X has type Type
% while it is expected to have type Set ***)
\begin{coq_example}
Fail Definition id: Set := forall X:Set,X->X.
\end{coq_example}
while it will type-check, if one uses instead the \texttt{coqtop
-impredicative-set} command.
The major change in the theory concerns the rule for product formation
in the sort \Set, which is extended to a domain in any sort:
\begin{description}
\item [Prod] \index{Typing rules!Prod (impredicative Set)}
\inference{\frac{\WTEG{T}{s}~~~~s \in \Sort~~~~~~
\WTE{\Gamma::(x:T)}{U}{\Set}}
{ \WTEG{\forall~x:T,U}{\Set}}}
\end{description}
This extension has consequences on the inductive definitions which are
allowed.
In the impredicative system, one can build so-called {\em large inductive
definitions} like the example of second-order existential
quantifier (\texttt{exSet}).
There should be restrictions on the eliminations which can be
performed on such definitions. The eliminations rules in the
impredicative system for sort \Set{} become:
\begin{description}
\item[\Set] \inference{\frac{s \in
\{\Prop, \Set\}}{\compat{I:\Set}{I\ra s}}
~~~~\frac{I \mbox{~is a small inductive definition}~~~~s \in
\{\Type(i)\}}
{\compat{I:\Set}{I\ra s}}}
\end{description}
%%% Local Variables:
%%% mode: latex
%%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual"
%%% End:
|