aboutsummaryrefslogtreecommitdiffhomepage
path: root/doc/faq/FAQ.tex
blob: 0856377eae6b4a37a908e887a19becc9e3b7c27c (plain)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
1001
1002
1003
1004
1005
1006
1007
1008
1009
1010
1011
1012
1013
1014
1015
1016
1017
1018
1019
1020
1021
1022
1023
1024
1025
1026
1027
1028
1029
1030
1031
1032
1033
1034
1035
1036
1037
1038
1039
1040
1041
1042
1043
1044
1045
1046
1047
1048
1049
1050
1051
1052
1053
1054
1055
1056
1057
1058
1059
1060
1061
1062
1063
1064
1065
1066
1067
1068
1069
1070
1071
1072
1073
1074
1075
1076
1077
1078
1079
1080
1081
1082
1083
1084
1085
1086
1087
1088
1089
1090
1091
1092
1093
1094
1095
1096
1097
1098
1099
1100
1101
1102
1103
1104
1105
1106
1107
1108
1109
1110
1111
1112
1113
1114
1115
1116
1117
1118
1119
1120
1121
1122
1123
1124
1125
1126
1127
1128
1129
1130
1131
1132
1133
1134
1135
1136
1137
1138
1139
1140
1141
1142
1143
1144
1145
1146
1147
1148
1149
1150
1151
1152
1153
1154
1155
1156
1157
1158
1159
1160
1161
1162
1163
1164
1165
1166
1167
1168
1169
1170
1171
1172
1173
1174
1175
1176
1177
1178
1179
1180
1181
1182
1183
1184
1185
1186
1187
1188
1189
1190
1191
1192
1193
1194
1195
1196
1197
1198
1199
1200
1201
1202
1203
1204
1205
1206
1207
1208
1209
1210
1211
1212
1213
1214
1215
1216
1217
1218
1219
1220
1221
1222
1223
1224
1225
1226
1227
1228
1229
1230
1231
1232
1233
1234
1235
1236
1237
1238
1239
1240
1241
1242
1243
1244
1245
1246
1247
1248
1249
1250
1251
1252
1253
1254
1255
1256
1257
1258
1259
1260
1261
1262
1263
1264
1265
1266
1267
1268
1269
1270
1271
1272
1273
1274
1275
1276
1277
1278
1279
1280
1281
1282
1283
1284
1285
1286
1287
1288
1289
1290
1291
1292
1293
1294
1295
1296
1297
1298
1299
1300
1301
1302
1303
1304
1305
1306
1307
1308
1309
1310
1311
1312
1313
1314
1315
1316
1317
1318
1319
1320
1321
1322
1323
1324
1325
1326
1327
1328
1329
1330
1331
1332
1333
1334
1335
1336
1337
1338
1339
1340
1341
1342
1343
1344
1345
1346
1347
1348
1349
1350
1351
1352
1353
1354
1355
1356
1357
1358
1359
1360
1361
1362
1363
1364
1365
1366
1367
1368
1369
1370
1371
1372
1373
1374
1375
1376
1377
1378
1379
1380
1381
1382
1383
1384
1385
1386
1387
1388
1389
1390
1391
1392
1393
1394
1395
1396
1397
1398
1399
1400
1401
1402
1403
1404
1405
1406
1407
1408
1409
1410
1411
1412
1413
1414
1415
1416
1417
1418
1419
1420
1421
1422
1423
1424
1425
1426
1427
1428
1429
1430
1431
1432
1433
1434
1435
1436
1437
1438
1439
1440
1441
1442
1443
1444
1445
1446
1447
1448
1449
1450
1451
1452
1453
1454
1455
1456
1457
1458
1459
1460
1461
1462
1463
1464
1465
1466
1467
1468
1469
1470
1471
1472
1473
1474
1475
1476
1477
1478
1479
1480
1481
1482
1483
1484
1485
1486
1487
1488
1489
1490
1491
1492
1493
1494
1495
1496
1497
1498
1499
1500
1501
1502
1503
1504
1505
1506
1507
1508
1509
1510
1511
1512
1513
1514
1515
1516
1517
1518
1519
1520
1521
1522
1523
1524
1525
1526
1527
1528
1529
1530
1531
1532
1533
1534
1535
1536
1537
1538
1539
1540
1541
1542
1543
1544
1545
1546
1547
1548
1549
1550
1551
1552
1553
1554
1555
1556
1557
1558
1559
1560
1561
1562
1563
1564
1565
1566
1567
1568
1569
1570
1571
1572
1573
1574
1575
1576
1577
1578
1579
1580
1581
1582
1583
1584
1585
1586
1587
1588
1589
1590
1591
1592
1593
1594
1595
1596
1597
1598
1599
1600
1601
1602
1603
1604
1605
1606
1607
1608
1609
1610
1611
1612
1613
1614
1615
1616
1617
1618
1619
1620
1621
1622
1623
1624
1625
1626
1627
1628
1629
1630
1631
1632
1633
1634
1635
1636
1637
1638
1639
1640
1641
1642
1643
1644
1645
1646
1647
1648
1649
1650
1651
1652
1653
1654
1655
1656
1657
1658
1659
1660
1661
1662
1663
1664
1665
1666
1667
1668
1669
1670
1671
1672
1673
1674
1675
1676
1677
1678
1679
1680
1681
1682
1683
1684
1685
1686
1687
1688
1689
1690
1691
1692
1693
1694
1695
1696
1697
1698
1699
1700
1701
1702
1703
1704
1705
1706
1707
1708
1709
1710
1711
1712
1713
1714
1715
1716
1717
1718
1719
1720
1721
1722
1723
1724
1725
1726
1727
1728
1729
1730
1731
1732
1733
1734
1735
1736
1737
1738
1739
1740
1741
1742
1743
1744
1745
1746
1747
1748
1749
1750
1751
1752
1753
1754
1755
1756
1757
1758
1759
1760
1761
1762
1763
1764
1765
1766
1767
1768
1769
1770
1771
1772
1773
1774
1775
1776
1777
1778
1779
1780
1781
1782
1783
1784
1785
1786
1787
1788
1789
1790
1791
1792
1793
1794
1795
1796
1797
1798
1799
1800
1801
1802
1803
1804
1805
1806
1807
1808
1809
1810
1811
1812
1813
1814
1815
1816
1817
1818
1819
1820
1821
1822
1823
1824
1825
1826
1827
1828
1829
1830
1831
1832
1833
1834
1835
1836
1837
1838
1839
1840
1841
1842
1843
1844
1845
1846
1847
1848
1849
1850
1851
1852
1853
1854
1855
1856
1857
1858
1859
1860
1861
1862
1863
1864
1865
1866
1867
1868
1869
1870
1871
1872
1873
1874
1875
1876
1877
1878
1879
1880
1881
1882
1883
1884
1885
1886
1887
1888
1889
1890
1891
1892
1893
1894
1895
1896
1897
1898
1899
1900
1901
1902
1903
1904
1905
1906
1907
1908
1909
1910
1911
1912
1913
1914
1915
1916
1917
1918
1919
1920
1921
1922
1923
1924
1925
1926
1927
1928
1929
1930
1931
1932
1933
1934
1935
1936
1937
1938
1939
1940
1941
1942
1943
1944
1945
1946
1947
1948
1949
1950
1951
1952
1953
1954
1955
1956
1957
1958
1959
1960
1961
1962
1963
1964
1965
1966
1967
1968
1969
1970
1971
1972
1973
1974
1975
1976
1977
1978
1979
1980
1981
1982
1983
1984
1985
1986
1987
1988
1989
1990
1991
1992
1993
1994
1995
1996
1997
1998
1999
2000
2001
2002
2003
2004
2005
2006
2007
2008
2009
2010
2011
2012
2013
2014
2015
2016
2017
2018
2019
2020
2021
2022
2023
2024
2025
2026
2027
2028
2029
2030
2031
2032
2033
2034
2035
2036
2037
2038
2039
2040
2041
2042
2043
2044
2045
2046
2047
2048
2049
2050
2051
2052
2053
2054
2055
2056
2057
2058
2059
2060
2061
2062
2063
2064
2065
2066
2067
2068
2069
2070
2071
2072
2073
2074
2075
2076
2077
2078
2079
2080
2081
2082
2083
2084
2085
2086
2087
2088
2089
2090
2091
2092
2093
2094
2095
2096
2097
2098
2099
2100
2101
2102
2103
2104
2105
2106
2107
2108
2109
2110
2111
2112
2113
2114
2115
2116
2117
2118
2119
2120
2121
2122
2123
2124
2125
2126
2127
2128
2129
2130
2131
2132
2133
2134
2135
2136
2137
2138
2139
2140
2141
2142
2143
2144
2145
2146
2147
2148
2149
2150
2151
2152
2153
2154
2155
2156
2157
2158
2159
2160
2161
2162
2163
2164
2165
2166
2167
2168
2169
2170
2171
2172
2173
2174
2175
2176
2177
2178
2179
2180
2181
2182
2183
2184
2185
2186
2187
2188
2189
2190
2191
2192
2193
2194
2195
2196
2197
2198
2199
2200
2201
2202
2203
2204
2205
2206
2207
2208
2209
2210
2211
2212
2213
2214
2215
2216
2217
2218
2219
2220
2221
2222
2223
2224
2225
2226
2227
2228
2229
2230
2231
2232
2233
2234
2235
2236
2237
2238
2239
2240
2241
2242
2243
2244
2245
2246
2247
2248
2249
2250
2251
2252
2253
2254
2255
2256
2257
2258
2259
2260
2261
2262
2263
2264
2265
2266
2267
2268
2269
2270
2271
2272
2273
2274
2275
2276
2277
2278
2279
2280
2281
2282
2283
2284
2285
2286
2287
2288
2289
2290
2291
2292
2293
2294
2295
2296
2297
2298
2299
2300
2301
2302
2303
2304
2305
2306
2307
2308
2309
2310
2311
2312
2313
2314
2315
2316
2317
2318
2319
2320
2321
2322
2323
2324
2325
2326
2327
2328
2329
2330
2331
2332
2333
2334
2335
2336
2337
2338
2339
2340
2341
2342
2343
2344
2345
2346
2347
2348
2349
2350
2351
2352
2353
2354
2355
2356
2357
2358
2359
2360
2361
2362
2363
2364
2365
2366
2367
2368
2369
2370
2371
2372
2373
2374
2375
2376
2377
2378
2379
2380
2381
2382
2383
2384
2385
2386
2387
2388
2389
2390
2391
2392
2393
2394
2395
2396
2397
2398
2399
2400
2401
2402
2403
2404
2405
2406
2407
2408
2409
2410
2411
2412
2413
2414
2415
2416
2417
2418
2419
2420
2421
2422
2423
2424
2425
2426
2427
2428
2429
2430
2431
2432
2433
2434
2435
2436
2437
2438
2439
2440
2441
2442
2443
2444
2445
2446
2447
2448
2449
2450
2451
2452
2453
2454
2455
2456
2457
2458
2459
2460
2461
2462
2463
2464
2465
2466
2467
2468
2469
2470
2471
2472
2473
2474
2475
2476
2477
2478
2479
2480
2481
2482
2483
2484
2485
2486
2487
2488
2489
2490
2491
2492
2493
2494
2495
2496
2497
2498
2499
\RequirePackage{ifpdf}
\ifpdf   % si on est en pdflatex
\documentclass[a4paper,pdftex]{article}
\else
\documentclass[a4paper]{article}
\fi
\pagestyle{plain}

% yay les symboles
\usepackage{stmaryrd}
\usepackage{amssymb}
\usepackage{url}
%\usepackage{multicol}
\usepackage{hevea}
\usepackage{fullpage}
\usepackage[latin1]{inputenc}
\usepackage[english]{babel}

\ifpdf   % si on est en pdflatex
  \usepackage[pdftex]{graphicx}
\else
  \usepackage[dvips]{graphicx}
\fi

%\input{../macros.tex}

% Making hevea happy
%HEVEA \renewcommand{\textbar}{|}
%HEVEA \renewcommand{\textunderscore}{\_}

\def\Question#1{\stepcounter{question}\subsubsection{#1}}

% version et date
\def\faqversion{0.1}

% les macros d'amour
\def\Coq{\textsc{Coq}}
\def\Why{\textsc{Why}}
\def\Caduceus{\textsc{Caduceus}}
\def\Krakatoa{\textsc{Krakatoa}}
\def\Ltac{\textsc{Ltac}}
\def\CoqIde{\textsc{CoqIde}}

\newcommand{\coqtt}[1]{{\tt #1}}
\newcommand{\coqimp}{{\mbox{\tt ->}}}
\newcommand{\coqequiv}{{\mbox{\tt <->}}}


% macro pour les tactics
\def\split{{\tt split}}
\def\assumption{{\tt assumption}}
\def\auto{{\tt auto}}
\def\trivial{{\tt trivial}}
\def\tauto{{\tt tauto}}
\def\left{{\tt left}}
\def\right{{\tt right}}
\def\decompose{{\tt decompose}}
\def\intro{{\tt intro}}
\def\intros{{\tt intros}}
\def\field{{\tt field}}
\def\ring{{\tt ring}}
\def\apply{{\tt apply}}
\def\exact{{\tt exact}}
\def\cut{{\tt cut}}
\def\assert{{\tt assert}}
\def\solve{{\tt solve}}
\def\idtac{{\tt idtac}}
\def\fail{{\tt fail}}
\def\existstac{{\tt exists}}
\def\firstorder{{\tt firstorder}}
\def\congruence{{\tt congruence}}
\def\gb{{\tt gb}}
\def\generalize{{\tt generalize}}
\def\abstracttac{{\tt abstract}}
\def\eapply{{\tt eapply}}
\def\unfold{{\tt unfold}}
\def\rewrite{{\tt rewrite}}
\def\replace{{\tt replace}}
\def\simpl{{\tt simpl}}
\def\elim{{\tt elim}}
\def\set{{\tt set}}
\def\pose{{\tt pose}}
\def\case{{\tt case}}
\def\destruct{{\tt destruct}}
\def\reflexivity{{\tt reflexivity}}
\def\transitivity{{\tt transitivity}}
\def\symmetry{{\tt symmetry}}
\def\Focus{{\tt Focus}}
\def\discriminate{{\tt discriminate}}
\def\contradiction{{\tt contradiction}}
\def\intuition{{\tt intuition}}
\def\try{{\tt try}}
\def\repeat{{\tt repeat}}
\def\eauto{{\tt eauto}}
\def\subst{{\tt subst}}
\def\symmetryin{{\tt symmetryin}}
\def\instantiate{{\tt instantiate}}
\def\inversion{{\tt inversion}}
\def\Defined{{\tt Defined}}
\def\Qed{{\tt Qed}}
\def\pattern{{\tt pattern}}
\def\Type{{\tt Type}}
\def\Prop{{\tt Prop}}
\def\Set{{\tt Set}}


\newcommand\vfile[2]{\ahref{#1}{\tt {#2}.v}}
\urldef{\InitWf}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Init.Wf.html}
\urldef{\LogicBerardi}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Berardi.html}
\urldef{\LogicClassical}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Classical.html}
\urldef{\LogicClassicalFacts}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.ClassicalFacts.html}
\urldef{\LogicClassicalDescription}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.ClassicalDescription.html}
\urldef{\LogicProofIrrelevance}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.ProofIrrelevance.html}
\urldef{\LogicEqdep}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Eqdep.html}
\urldef{\LogicEqdepDec}{\url}
  {http://coq.inria.fr/library/Coq.Logic.Eqdep_dec.html}




\begin{document}
\bibliographystyle{plain}
\newcounter{question}
\renewcommand{\thesubsubsection}{\arabic{question}}

%%%%%%% Coq pour les nuls %%%%%%%

\title{Coq Version 8.0 for the Clueless\\
  \large(\protect\ref{lastquestion}
  \ Hints)
}
\author{Pierre Castéran \and Hugo Herbelin \and Florent Kirchner \and Benjamin Monate \and Julien Narboux}
\maketitle

%%%%%%%

\begin{abstract}
This note intends to provide an easy way to get acquainted with the
{\Coq} theorem prover. It tries to formulate appropriate answers
to some of the questions any newcomers will face, and to give
pointers to other references when possible.
\end{abstract}

%%%%%%%

%\begin{multicols}{2}
\tableofcontents
%\end{multicols}

%%%%%%%

\newpage

\section{Introduction}
This FAQ is the sum of the questions that came to mind as we developed
proofs in \Coq. Since we are singularly short-minded, we wrote the
answers we found on bits of papers to have them at hand whenever the
situation occurs again. This is pretty much the result of that: a
collection of tips one can refer to when proofs become intricate. Yes,
this means we won't take the blame for the shortcomings of this
FAQ. But if you want to contribute and send in your own question and
answers, feel free to write to us\ldots

%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%

\section{Presentation}

\Question{What is {\Coq}?}\label{whatiscoq} 
The {\Coq} tool is a formal proof management system: a proof done with {\Coq} is mechanically checked by the machine. 
In particular, {\Coq} allows:
\begin{itemize}
    \item the definition of mathematical objects and programming objects,
    \item to state mathematical theorems and software specifications,
    \item to interactively develop formal proofs of these theorems,
    \item to check these proofs by a small certification ``kernel''.
\end{itemize}
{\Coq} is based on a logical framework called ``Calculus of Inductive
Constructions'' extended by a modular development system for theories.

\Question{Did you really need to name it like that?}
Some French computer scientists have a tradition of naming their
software as animal species: Caml, Elan, Foc or Phox are examples
of this tacit convention. In French, ``coq'' means rooster, and it
sounds like the initials of the Calculus of Constructions CoC on which
it is based.

\Question{Is {\Coq} a theorem prover?}

{\Coq} comes with decision and semi-decision procedures (
propositional calculus, Presburger's arithmetic, ring and field
simplification, resolution, ...) but the main style for proving
theorems is interactively by using LCF-style tactics.


\Question{What are the other theorem provers?} 
Many other theorem provers are available for use nowadays. 
Isabelle, HOL, HOL Light, Lego, Nuprl, PVS are examples of provers that are fairly similar
to {\Coq} by the way they interact with the user. Other relatives of
{\Coq} are ACL2, Agda/Alfa, Twelf, Kiv, Mizar, NqThm, 
\begin{htmlonly}%
Omega\ldots
\end{htmlonly}
\begin{latexonly}%
{$\Omega$}mega\ldots
\end{latexonly}

\Question{What do I have to trust when I see a proof checked by Coq?}

You have to trust:

\begin{description}
\item[The theory behind Coq] The theory of {\Coq} version 8.0 is
generally admitted to be consistent wrt Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory +
inaccessible cardinals. Proofs of consistency of subsystems of the
theory of Coq can be found in the literature.
\item[The Coq kernel implementation] You have to trust that the
implementation of the {\Coq} kernel mirrors the theory behind {\Coq}. The
kernel is intentionally small to limit the risk of conceptual or
accidental implementation bugs.
\item[The Objective Caml compiler] The {\Coq} kernel is written using the
Objective Caml language but it uses only the most standard features
(no object, no label ...), so that it is highly unprobable that an
Objective Caml bug breaks the consistency of {\Coq} without breaking all
other kinds of features of {\Coq} or of other software compiled with
Objective Caml.
\item[Your hardware] In theory, if your hardware does not work
properly, it can accidentally be the case that False becomes
provable. But it is more likely the case that the whole {\Coq} system
will be unusable. You can check your proof using different computers
if you feel the need to.
\item[Your axioms] Your axioms must be consistent with the theory
behind {\Coq}.
\end{description}


\Question{Where can I find information about the theory behind {\Coq}?}
\begin{description}
\item[The Calculus of Inductive Constructions] The
\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/Reference-Manual006.html}{corresponding}
chapter and the chapter on
\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/Reference-Manual007.html}{modules} in
the {\Coq} Reference Manual.
\item[Type theory] A book~\cite{ProofsTypes} or some lecture
notes~\cite{Types:Dowek}.
\item[Inductive types]
Christine Paulin-Mohring's habilitation thesis~\cite{Pau96b}.
\item[Co-Inductive types]
Eduardo Giménez' thesis~\cite{EGThese}.
\item[Miscellaneous] A
\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/biblio.html}{bibliography} about Coq
\end{description}


\Question{How can I use {\Coq} to prove programs?}

You can either extract a program from a proof by using the extraction
mechanism or use dedicated tools, such as
\ahref{http://why.lri.fr}{\Why},
\ahref{http://krakatoa.lri.fr}{\Krakatoa},
\ahref{http://why.lri.fr/caduceus/index.en.html}{\Caduceus}, to prove
annotated programs written in other languages.

%\Question{How many {\Coq} users are there?}
%
%An estimation is about 100 regular users.

\Question{How old is {\Coq}?}

The first implementation is from 1985 (it was named {\sf CoC} which is
the acronym of the name of the logic it implemented: the Calculus of
Constructions).  The first official release of {\Coq} (version 4.10)
was distributed in 1989.

\Question{What are the \Coq-related tools?}

There are graphical user interfaces:
\begin{description}
\item[Coqide] A GTK based GUI for \Coq.
\item[Pcoq] A GUI for {\Coq} with proof by pointing and pretty printing.
\item[coqwc] A tool similar to {\tt wc} to count lines in {\Coq} files.
\item[Proof General] A emacs mode for {\Coq} and many other proof assistants.
\end{description}

There are documentation and browsing tools:

\begin{description}
\item[Helm/Mowgli] A rendering, searching and publishing tool.
\item[coq-tex] A tool to insert {\Coq} examples within .tex files. 
\item[coqdoc] A documentation tool for \Coq.
\end{description}

There are front-ends for specific languages:

\begin{description}
\item[Why] A back-end generator of verification conditions.
\item[Krakatoa] A Java code certification tool that uses both {\Coq} and {\Why} to verify the soundness of implementations with regards to the specifications.
\item[Caduceus] A C code certification tool that uses both {\Coq} and \Why.
\item[Zenon] A first-order theorem prover.
\item[Focal] The \ahref{http://focal.inria.fr}{Focal} project aims at building an environment to develop certified computer algebra libraries. 
\end{description}

\Question{What are the high-level tactics of \Coq}

\begin{itemize}
\item Decision of quantifier-free Presburger's Arithmetic
\item Simplification of expressions on rings and fields
\item Decision of closed systems of equations
\item Semi-decision of first-order logic
\item Prolog-style proof search, possibly involving equalities
\end{itemize}

\Question{What are the main libraries available for \Coq}

\begin{itemize}
\item Basic Peano's arithmetic, binary integer numbers, rational numbers,
\item Real analysis,
\item Libraries for lists, boolean, maps, floating-point numbers,
\item Libraries for relations, sets and constructive algebra,
\item Geometry
\end{itemize}


\Question{What are the mathematical applications for {\Coq}?}

{\Coq} is used for formalizing mathematical theories, for teaching,
and for proving properties of algorithms or programs libraries.

The largest mathematical formalization has been done at the University
of Nijmegen (see the
\ahref{http://vacuumcleaner.cs.kun.nl/c-corn}{Constructive Coq
Repository at Nijmegen}).

A symbolic step has also been obtained by formalizing in full a proof
of the Four Color Theorem.

\Question{What are the industrial applications for {\Coq}?}

{\Coq} is used e.g. to prove properties of the JavaCard system
(especially by Schlumberger and Trusted Logic). It has
also been used to formalize the semantics of the Lucid-Synchrone
data-flow synchronous calculus used by Esterel-Technologies.

\iffalse
todo christine compilo lustre?
\fi

%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%

\section{Documentation}

\Question{Where can I find documentation about {\Coq}?} 
All the documentation about \Coq, from the reference manual~\cite{Coq:manual} to
friendly tutorials~\cite{Coq:Tutorial} and documentation of the standard library, is available 
\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc-eng.html}{online}.
All these documents are viewable either in browsable HTML, or as
downloadable postscripts.

\Question{Where can I find this FAQ on the web?}

This FAQ is available online at \ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/faq.html}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/faq.html}}.

\Question{How can I submit suggestions / improvements / additions for this FAQ?}

This FAQ is unfinished (in the sense that there are some obvious
sections that are missing). Please send contributions to \texttt{Florent.Kirchner at lix.polytechnique.fr} and \texttt{Julien.Narboux at inria.fr}.

\Question{Is there any mailing list about {\Coq}?} 
The main {\Coq} mailing list is \url{coq-club@pauillac.inria.fr}, which
broadcasts questions and suggestions about the implementation, the
logical formalism or proof developments. See
\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/mailman/listinfo/coq-club}{\url{http://pauillac.inria.fr/mailman/listinfo/coq-club}} for
subscription. For bugs reports see question \ref{coqbug}.

\Question{Where can I find an archive of the list?}
The archives of the {\Coq} mailing list are available at
\ahref{http://pauillac.inria.fr/pipermail/coq-club}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr/pipermail/coq-club}}.


\Question{How can I be kept informed of new releases of {\Coq}?}

New versions of {\Coq} are announced on the coq-club mailing list. If you only want to receive information about new releases, you can subscribe to {\Coq} on \ahref{http://freshmeat.net/projects/coq/}{\url{http://freshmeat.net/projects/coq/}}.


\Question{Is there any book about {\Coq}?}

The first book on \Coq, Yves Bertot and Pierre Castéran's Coq'Art has been published by Springer-Verlag in 2004:
\begin{quote}
``This book provides a pragmatic introduction to the development of
proofs and certified programs using \Coq. With its large collection of
examples and exercises it is an invaluable tool for researchers,
students, and engineers interested in formal methods and the
development of zero-default software.''
\end{quote}

\Question{Where can I find some {\Coq} examples?} 

There are examples in the manual~\cite{Coq:manual} and in the
Coq'Art~\cite{Coq:coqart} exercises \ahref{\url{http://www.labri.fr/Perso/~casteran/CoqArt/index.html}}{\url{http://www.labri.fr/Perso/~casteran/CoqArt/index.html}}.
You can also find large developments using
{\Coq} in the {\Coq} user contributions:
\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/contrib-eng.html}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr/contrib-eng.html}}.

\Question{How can I report a bug?}\label{coqbug}

You can use the web interface accessible at \ahref{http://coq.inria.fr}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr}}, link ``contacts''.


%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%

\section{Installation}

\Question{What is the license of {\Coq}?}
{\Coq} is distributed under the GNU Lesser General License
(LGPL).

\Question{Where can I find the sources of {\Coq}?}
The sources of {\Coq} can be found online in the tar.gz'ed packages
(\ahref{http://coq.inria.fr}{\url{http://coq.inria.fr}}, link
``download''). Development sources can be accessed at
\ahref{http://coq.gforge.inria.fr/}{\url{http://coq.gforge.inria.fr/}}

\Question{On which platform is {\Coq} available?}
Compiled binaries are available for Linux, MacOS X, and Windows. The
sources can be easily compiled on all platforms supporting Objective
Caml.

%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%

\section{The logic of {\Coq}}

\subsection{General}

\Question{What is the logic of \Coq?}

{\Coq} is based on an axiom-free type theory called
the Calculus of Inductive Constructions (see Coquand \cite{CoHu86},
Luo~\cite{Luo90}
and Coquand--Paulin-Mohring \cite{CoPa89}). It includes higher-order
functions and predicates, inductive and co-inductive datatypes and
predicates, and a stratified hierarchy of sets.

\Question{Is \Coq's logic intuitionistic or classical?}

{\Coq}'s logic is modular. The core logic is intuitionistic
(i.e. excluded-middle $A\vee\neg A$ is not granted by default). It can
be extended to classical logic on demand by requiring an
optional module stating $A\vee\neg A$.

\Question{Can I define non-terminating programs in \Coq?}

All programs in {\Coq} are terminating. Especially, loops
must come with an evidence of their termination. 

Non-terminating programs can be simulated by passing around a
bound on how long the program is allowed to run before dying.

\Question{How is equational reasoning working in {\Coq}?}

 {\Coq} comes with an internal notion of computation called
{\em conversion} (e.g. $(x+1)+y$ is internally equivalent to
$(x+y)+1$; similarly applying argument $a$ to a function mapping $x$
to some expression $t$ converts to the expression $t$ where $x$ is
replaced by $a$). This notion of conversion (which is decidable
because {\Coq} programs are terminating) covers a certain part of
equational reasoning but is limited to sequential evaluation of
expressions of (not necessarily closed) programs. Besides conversion,
equations have to be treated by hand or using specialised tactics.

\subsection{Axioms}

\Question{What axioms can be safely added to {\Coq}?}

There are a few typical useful axioms that are independent from the
Calculus of Inductive Constructions and that can be safely added to
{\Coq}. These axioms are stated in the directory {\tt Logic} of the
standard library of {\Coq}. The most interesting ones are

\begin{itemize}
\item Excluded-middle: $\forall A:Prop, A \vee \neg A$
\item Proof-irrelevance: $\forall A:Prop \forall p_1 p_2:A, p_1=p_2$
\item Unicity of equality proofs (or equivalently Streicher's axiom $K$):
$\forall A \forall x y:A \forall p_1 p_2:x=y, p_1=p_2$
\item The axiom of unique choice: $\forall x \exists! y R(x,y) \rightarrow \exists f \forall x R(x,f(x))$
\item The functional axiom of choice: $\forall x \exists y R(x,y) \rightarrow \exists f \forall x R(x,f(x))$
\item Extensionality of predicates: $\forall P Q:A\rightarrow Prop, (\forall x, P(x) \leftrightarrow Q(x)) \rightarrow P=Q$
\item Extensionality of functions: $\forall f g:A\rightarrow B, (\forall x, f(x)=g(x)) \rightarrow f=g$
\end{itemize}

Here is a summary of the relative strength of these axioms, most
proofs can be found in directory {\tt Logic} of the standard library.
The justification of their validity relies on the interpretability in
set theory.

%HEVEA\imgsrc{axioms.png}
%BEGIN LATEX
\ifpdf   % si on est en pdflatex
\includegraphics[width=1.0\textwidth]{axioms.png}
\else
\includegraphics[width=1.0\textwidth]{axioms.eps}
\fi
%END LATEX

\Question{What standard axioms are inconsistent with {\Coq}?}

The axiom of unique choice together with classical logic
(e.g. excluded-middle) are inconsistent in the variant of the Calculus
of Inductive Constructions where {\Set} is impredicative.

As a consequence, the functional form of the axiom of choice and
excluded-middle, or any form of the axiom of choice together with
predicate extensionality are inconsistent in the {\Set}-impredicative
version of the Calculus of Inductive Constructions.

The main purpose of the \Set-predicative restriction of the Calculus
of Inductive Constructions is precisely to accommodate these axioms
which are quite standard in mathematical usage.

The $\Set$-predicative system is commonly considered consistent by
interpreting it in a standard set-theoretic boolean model, even with
classical logic, axiom of choice and predicate extensionality added.

\Question{What is Streicher's axiom $K$}
\label{Streicher}

Streicher's axiom $K$~\cite{HofStr98} is an axiom that asserts
dependent elimination of reflexive equality proofs.

\begin{coq_example*}
Axiom Streicher_K :
  forall (A:Type) (x:A) (P: x=x -> Prop),
    P (refl_equal x) -> forall p: x=x, P p.
\end{coq_example*}

In the general case, axiom $K$ is an independent statement of the
Calculus of Inductive Constructions.  However, it is true on decidable
domains (see file \vfile{\LogicEqdepDec}{Eqdep\_dec}). It is also
trivially a consequence of proof-irrelevance (see
\ref{proof-irrelevance}) hence of classical logic.

Axiom $K$ is equivalent to {\em Uniqueness of Identity Proofs} \cite{HofStr98}

\begin{coq_example*}
Axiom UIP : forall (A:Set) (x y:A) (p1 p2: x=y), p1 = p2.
\end{coq_example*}

Axiom $K$ is also equivalent to {\em Uniqueness of Reflexive Identity Proofs} \cite{HofStr98}

\begin{coq_example*}
Axiom UIP_refl : forall (A:Set) (x:A) (p: x=x), p = refl_equal x.
\end{coq_example*}

Axiom $K$ is also equivalent to 

\begin{coq_example*}
Axiom
  eq_rec_eq :
    forall (A:Set) (x:A) (P: A->Set) (p:P x) (h: x=x),
      p = eq_rect x P p x h.
\end{coq_example*}

It is also equivalent to the injectivity of dependent equality (dependent equality is itself equivalent to equality of dependent pairs).

\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive eq_dep (U:Set) (P:U -> Set) (p:U) (x:P p) :
forall q:U, P q -> Prop :=
    eq_dep_intro : eq_dep U P p x p x.
Axiom
  eq_dep_eq :
    forall (U:Set) (u:U) (P:U -> Set) (p1 p2:P u),
      eq_dep U P u p1 u p2 -> p1 = p2.
\end{coq_example*}

\Question{What is proof-irrelevance}
\label{proof-irrelevance}

A specificity of the Calculus of Inductive Constructions is to permit
statements about proofs. This leads to the question of comparing two
proofs of the same proposition. Identifying all proofs of the same
proposition is called {\em proof-irrelevance}:
$$
\forall A:\Prop, \forall p q:A, p=q
$$ 

Proof-irrelevance (in {\Prop}) can be assumed without contradiction in
{\Coq}. It expresses that only provability matters, whatever the exact
form of the proof is. This is in harmony with the common purely
logical interpretation of {\Prop}. Contrastingly, proof-irrelevance is
inconsistent in {\Set} since there are types in {\Set}, such as the
type of booleans, that are provably more than 2 elements.

Proof-irrelevance (in {\Prop}) is a consequence of classical logic
(see proofs in file \vfile{\LogicClassical}{Classical} and
\vfile{\LogicBerardi}{Berardi}). Proof-irrelevance is also a
consequence of propositional extensionality (i.e.  \coqtt{(A {\coqequiv} B)
{\coqimp} A=B}, see the proof in file
\vfile{\LogicClassicalFacts}{ClassicalFacts}).

Proof-irrelevance directly implies Streicher's axiom $K$.

\Question{What about functional extensionality?}

Extensionality of functions is admittedly consistent with the
Set-predicative Calculus of Inductive Constructions.

%\begin{coq_example*}
%  Axiom extensionality : (A,B:Set)(f,g:(A->B))(x:A)(f x)=(g x)->f=g.
%\end{coq_example*}

Let {\tt A}, {\tt B} be types. To deal with extensionality on 
\verb=A->B= without relying on a general extensionality axiom, 
a possible approach is to define one's own extensional equality on
\verb=A->B=.

\begin{coq_eval}
Variables A B : Set.
\end{coq_eval}

\begin{coq_example*}
Definition ext_eq (f g: A->B) := forall x:A, f x = g x.
\end{coq_example*}

and to reason on \verb=A->B= as a setoid (see the Chapter on
Setoids in the Reference Manual).

\Question{Is {\Prop} impredicative?}

Yes, the sort {\Prop} of propositions is {\em
impredicative}. Otherwise said, a statement of the form $\forall
A:Prop, P(A)$ can be instantiated by itself: if $\forall A:\Prop, P(A)$
is provable, then $P(\forall A:\Prop, P(A))$ is.

\Question{Is {\Set} impredicative?}

No, the sort {\Set} lying at the bottom of the hierarchy of
computational types is {\em predicative} in the basic {\Coq} system.
This means that a family of types in {\Set}, e.g. $\forall A:\Set, A
\rightarrow A$, is not a type in {\Set} and it cannot be applied on
itself.

However, the sort {\Set} was impredicative in the original versions of
{\Coq}. For backward compatibility, or for experiments by
knowledgeable users, the logic of {\Coq} can be set impredicative for
{\Set} by calling {\Coq} with the option {\tt -impredicative-set}.

{\Set} has been made predicative from version 8.0 of {\Coq}. The main
reason is to interact smoothly with a classical mathematical world
where both excluded-middle and the axiom of description are valid (see
file \vfile{\LogicClassicalDescription}{ClassicalDescription} for a
proof that excluded-middle and description implies the double negation
of excluded-middle in {\Set} and file {\tt Hurkens\_Set.v} from the
user contribution {\tt Rocq/PARADOXES} for a proof that
impredicativity of {\Set} implies the simple negation of
excluded-middle in {\Set}).

\Question{Is {\Type} impredicative?}

No, {\Type} is stratified. This is hidden for the
user, but {\Coq} internally maintains a set of constraints ensuring
stratification.

If {\Type} were impredicative then it would be possible to encode
Girard's systems $U-$ and $U$ in {\Coq} and it is known from Girard,
Coquand, Hurkens and Miquel that systems $U-$ and $U$ are inconsistent
[Girard 1972, Coquand 1991, Hurkens 1993, Miquel 2001]. This encoding
can be found in file {\tt Logic/Hurkens.v} of {\Coq} standard library.

For instance, when the user see {\tt $\forall$ X:Type, X->X : Type}, each
occurrence of {\Type} is implicitly bound to a different level, say
$\alpha$ and $\beta$ and the actual statement is {\tt
forall X:Type($\alpha$), X->X : Type($\beta$)} with the constraint
$\alpha<\beta$.

When a statement violates a constraint, the message {\tt Universe
inconsistency} appears. Example: {\tt fun (x:Type) (y:$\forall$ X:Type, X
{\coqimp} X) => y x x}.

\Question{I have two proofs of the same proposition. Can I prove they are equal?}

In the base {\Coq} system, the answer is generally no. However, if
classical logic is set, the answer is yes for propositions in {\Prop}.
The answer is also yes if proof irrelevance holds (see question
\ref{proof-irrelevance}).

There are also ``simple enough'' propositions for which you can prove
the equality without requiring any extra axioms.  This is typically
the case for propositions defined deterministically as a first-order
inductive predicate on decidable sets. See for instance in question
\ref{le-uniqueness} an axiom-free proof of the unicity of the proofs of
the proposition {\tt le m n} (less or equal on {\tt nat}).

%  It is an ongoing work of research to natively include proof
%  irrelevance in {\Coq}.

\Question{I have two proofs of an equality statement. Can I prove they are 
equal?}

 Yes, if equality is decidable on the domain considered (which
is the case for {\tt nat}, {\tt bool}, etc): see {\Coq} file
\verb=Eqdep_dec.v=). No otherwise, unless
assuming Streicher's axiom $K$ (see \cite{HofStr98}) or a more general
assumption such as proof-irrelevance (see \ref{proof-irrelevance}) or
classical logic.

All of these statements can be found in file \vfile{\LogicEqdep}{Eqdep}.

\Question{Can I prove that the second components of equal dependent
pairs are equal?}

 The answer is the same as for proofs of equality
statements. It is provable if equality on the domain of the first
component is decidable (look at \verb=inj_right_pair= from file
\vfile{\LogicEqdepDec}{Eqdep\_dec}), but not provable in the general
case. However, it is consistent (with the Calculus of Constructions)
to assume it is true. The file \vfile{\LogicEqdep}{Eqdep} actually
provides an axiom (equivalent to Streicher's axiom $K$) which entails
the result (look at \verb=inj_pair2= in \vfile{\LogicEqdep}{Eqdep}).

\subsection{Impredicativity}

\Question{Why {\tt injection} does not work on impredicative {\tt Set}?}

 E.g. in this case (this occurs only in the {\tt Set}-impredicative
 variant of \Coq):

\begin{coq_eval}
Reset Initial.
\end{coq_eval}

\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive I : Type :=
  intro : forall k:Set, k -> I.
Lemma eq_jdef : 
   forall x y:nat, intro _ x = intro _ y -> x = y.
Proof.
   intros x y H; injection H.
\end{coq_example*}

 Injectivity of constructors is restricted to predicative types. If
injectivity on large inductive types were not restricted, we would be
allowed to derive an inconsistency (e.g. following the lines of
Burali-Forti paradox). The question remains open whether injectivity
is consistent on some large inductive types not expressive enough to
encode known paradoxes (such as type I above).


\Question{What is a ``large inductive definition''?}

An inductive definition in {\Prop} or {\Set} is called large
if its constructors embed sets or propositions. As an example, here is
a large inductive type:

\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive sigST (P:Set -> Set) : Type :=
  existST : forall X:Set, P X -> sigST P.
\end{coq_example*}

In the {\tt Set} impredicative variant of {\Coq}, large inductive
definitions in {\tt Set} have restricted elimination schemes to
prevent inconsistencies. Especially, projecting the set or the
proposition content of a large inductive definition is forbidden. If
it were allowed, it would be possible to encode e.g. Burali-Forti
paradox \cite{Gir70,Coq85}.


%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\section{Talkin' with the Rooster}


%%%%%%%
\subsection{My goal is ...,  how can I prove it?}


\Question{My goal is a conjunction, how can I prove it?}

Use some theorem or assumption or use the {\split} tactic.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B:Prop, A->B-> A/\B.
intros.
split.
assumption.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{My goal contains a conjunction as an hypothesis, how can I use it?}

If you want to decompose your hypothesis into other hypothesis you can use the {\decompose} tactic:

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B:Prop, A/\B-> B.
intros.
decompose [and] H.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is a disjunction, how can I prove it?}

You can prove the left part or the right part of the disjunction using
{\left} or {\right} tactics. If you want to do a classical
reasoning step, use the {\tt classic} axiom to prove the right part with the assumption
that the left part of the disjunction is false.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B:Prop, A-> A\/B.
intros.
left.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

An example using classical reasoning:

\begin{coq_example}
Require Import Classical.

Ltac classical_right := 
match goal with 
| _:_ |-?X1 \/ _ => (elim (classic X1);intro;[left;trivial|right])
end.

Ltac classical_left := 
match goal with 
| _:_ |- _ \/?X1 => (elim (classic X1);intro;[right;trivial|left])
end.


Goal forall A B:Prop, (~A -> B) -> A\/B.
intros.
classical_right.
auto.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{My goal is an universally quantified statement, how can I prove it?}

Use some theorem or assumption or introduce the quantified variable in
the context using the {\intro} tactic. If there are several
variables you can use the {\intros} tactic. A good habit is to
provide names for these variables: {\Coq} will do it anyway, but such
automatic naming decreases legibility and robustness.


\Question{My goal is an existential, how can I prove it?}

Use some theorem or assumption or exhibit the witness using the {\existstac} tactic.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal exists x:nat, forall y, x+y=y.
exists 0.
intros.
auto.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is solvable by  some lemma, how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\apply} tactic.

\begin{coq_eval}
Reset Initial.
\end{coq_eval}

\begin{coq_example}
Lemma mylemma : forall x, x+0 = x.
auto.
Qed.

Goal 3+0 = 3.
apply mylemma.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}



\Question{My goal contains False as an hypothesis, how can I prove it?}

You can use the {\contradiction} or {\intuition} tactics.


\Question{My goal is an equality of two convertible terms, how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\reflexivity} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall x, 0+x = x.
intros.
reflexivity.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{My goal is a {\tt let x := a in ...}, how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\intro} tactic.


\Question{My goal is a {\tt let (a, ..., b) := c in}, how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\destruct} c as (a,...,b) tactic.


\Question{My goal contains some existential hypotheses, how can I use it?}

You can use the tactic {\elim} with you hypotheses as an argument.

\Question{My goal contains some existential hypotheses, how can I use it and decompose my knowledge about this new thing into different hypotheses?}

\begin{verbatim}
Ltac DecompEx H P := elim H;intro P;intro TO;decompose [and] TO;clear TO;clear H.
\end{verbatim}


\Question{My goal is an equality, how can I swap the left and right hand terms?}

Just use the {\symmetry} tactic.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall x y : nat, x=y -> y=x.
intros.
symmetry.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{My hypothesis is an equality, how can I swap the left and right hand terms?}

Just use the {\symmetryin} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall x y : nat, x=y -> y=x.
intros.
symmetry in H.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is an equality, how can I prove it by transitivity?}

Just use the {\transitivity} tactic.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall x y z : nat, x=y -> y=z -> x=z.
intros.
transitivity y.
assumption.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal would be solvable using {\tt apply;assumption} if it would not create meta-variables, how can I prove it?}

You can use {\tt eapply yourtheorem;eauto} but it won't work in all cases ! (for example if more than one hypothesis match one of the subgoals generated by \eapply) so you should rather use  {\tt try solve [eapply yourtheorem;eauto]}, otherwise some metavariables may be incorrectly instantiated.

\begin{coq_example}
Lemma trans : forall x y z : nat, x=y -> y=z -> x=z.
intros.
transitivity y;assumption.
Qed.

Goal forall x y z : nat, x=y -> y=z -> x=z.
intros.
eapply trans;eauto.
Qed.

Goal forall x y z t : nat, x=y -> x=t -> y=z -> x=z.
intros.
eapply trans;eauto.
Undo.
eapply trans.
apply H.
auto.
Qed.

Goal forall x y z t : nat, x=y -> x=t -> y=z -> x=z.
intros.
eapply trans;eauto.
Undo.
try solve [eapply trans;eauto].
eapply trans.
apply H.
auto.
Qed.

\end{coq_example}

\Question{My goal is solvable by  some lemma within a set of lemmas and I don't want to remember which one, how can I prove it?}

You can use a what is called a hints' base.

\begin{coq_example}
Require Import ZArith.
Require Ring.
Open Local Scope Z_scope.
Lemma toto1 : 1+1 = 2.
ring.
Qed.
Lemma toto2 : 2+2 = 4.
ring.
Qed.
Lemma toto3 : 2+1 = 3.
ring.
Qed.

Hint Resolve toto1 toto2 toto3 : mybase.

Goal 2+(1+1)=4. 
auto with mybase.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is one of the hypotheses, how can I prove it?}

Use the {\assumption} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal 1=1 -> 1=1.
intro.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal appears twice in the hypotheses and I want to choose which one is used, how can I do it?}

Use the {\exact} tactic.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal 1=1 -> 1=1 -> 1=1.
intros.
exact H0.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{What can be the difference between applying one hypothesis or another in the context of the last question?}

From a proof point of view it is equivalent but if you want to extract
a program from your proof, the two hypotheses can lead to different
programs.


\Question{My goal is a propositional tautology, how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\tauto} tactic.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B:Prop, A-> (A\/B) /\ A.
intros.
tauto.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{My goal is a first order formula, how can I prove it?}

Just use the semi-decision tactic: \firstorder.

\iffalse
todo: demander un exemple à Pierre
\fi

\Question{My goal is solvable by a sequence of rewrites, how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\congruence} tactic.
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall a b c d e, a=d -> b=e -> c+b=d -> c+e=a.
intros.
congruence.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is a disequality solvable by a sequence of rewrites, how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\congruence} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall a b c d, a<>d -> b=a -> d=c+b -> b<>c+b.
intros.
congruence.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is an equality on some ring (e.g. natural numbers), how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\ring} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Require Import ZArith.
Require Ring.
Open Local Scope Z_scope.
Goal forall a b : Z, (a+b)*(a+b) = a*a + 2*a*b + b*b. 
intros.
ring.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{My goal is an equality on some field (e.g. real numbers), how can I prove it?}

Just use the {\field} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Require Import Reals.
Require Ring.
Open Local Scope R_scope.
Goal forall a b : R, b*a<>0 -> (a/b) * (b/a) = 1. 
intros.
field.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is an inequality on integers in Presburger's arithmetic (an expression build from +,-,constants and variables), how can I prove it?}


\begin{coq_example}
Require Import ZArith.
Require Omega.
Open Local Scope Z_scope.
Goal forall a : Z, a>0 -> a+a > a. 
intros.
omega.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{My goal is an equation solvable using equational hypothesis on some ring (e.g. natural numbers), how can I prove it?}

You need the {\gb} tactic (see Loïc Pottier's homepage).

\subsection{Tactics usage}

\Question{I want to state a fact that I will use later as an hypothesis, how can I do it?}

If you want to use forward reasoning (first proving the fact and then
using it) you just need to use the {\assert} tactic. If you want to use
backward reasoning (proving your goal using an assumption and then
proving the assumption) use the {\cut} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B C D : Prop, (A -> B) -> (B->C) -> A -> C. 
intros.
assert (A->C).
intro;apply H0;apply H;assumption.
apply H2.
assumption.
Qed.

Goal forall A B C D : Prop, (A -> B) -> (B->C) -> A -> C. 
intros.
cut (A->C).
intro.
apply H2;assumption.
intro;apply H0;apply H;assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}




\Question{I want to state a fact that I will use later as an hypothesis and prove it later, how can I do it?}

You can use {\cut} followed by {\intro} or you can use the following {\Ltac} command:
\begin{verbatim}
Ltac assert_later t := cut t;[intro|idtac]. 
\end{verbatim}

\Question{What is the difference between {\Qed} and {\Defined}?}

These two commands perform type checking, but when {\Defined} is used the new definition is set as transparent, otherwise it is defined as opaque (see \ref{opaque}).


\Question{How can I know what a tactic does?}

You can use the {\tt info} command.



\Question{Why {\auto} does not work? How can I fix it?}

You can increase the depth of the proof search or add some lemmas in the base of hints.
Perhaps you may need to use \eauto.

\Question{What is {\eauto}?}

This is the same tactic as \auto, but it relies on {\eapply} instead of \apply.

\iffalse
todo les espaces
\fi

\Question{How can I speed up {\auto}?}

You can use \texttt{info }\auto to replace {\auto} by the tactics it generates.
You can split your hint bases into smaller ones.


\Question{What is the equivalent of {\tauto} for classical logic?}

Currently there are no equivalent tactic for classical logic. You can use Gödel's ``not not'' translation.


\Question{I want to replace some term with another in the goal, how can I do it?}

If one of your hypothesis (say {\tt H}) states that the terms are equal you can use the {\rewrite} tactic. Otherwise you can use the {\replace} {\tt with} tactic. 

\Question{I want to replace some term with another in an hypothesis, how can I do it?}

You can use the {\rewrite} {\tt in} tactic.

\Question{I want to replace some symbol with its definition, how can I do it?}

You can use the {\unfold} tactic.

\Question{How can I reduce some term?}

You can use the {\simpl} tactic.

\Question{How can I declare a shortcut for some term?}

You can use the {\set} or {\pose} tactics.

\Question{How can I perform case analysis?}

You can use the {\case} or {\destruct} tactics.

\Question{How can I prevent the case tactic from losing information ?}

You may want to use the (now standard) {\tt case\_eq} tactic. See the Coq'Art page 159.

\Question{Why should I name my intros?}

When you use the {\intro} tactic you don't have to give a name to your
hypothesis. If you do so the name will be generated by {\Coq} but your
scripts may be less robust. If you add some hypothesis to your theorem
(or change their order), you will have to change your proof to adapt
to the new names.

\Question{How can I automatize the naming?}

You can use the {\tt Show Intro.} or  {\tt Show Intros.} commands to generate the names and use your editor to generate a fully named {\intro} tactic. 
This can be automatized within {\tt xemacs}.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B C : Prop, A -> B -> C -> A/\B/\C.
Show Intros.
(*
A B C H H0
H1
*)
intros A B C H H0 H1.
repeat split;assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{I want to automatize the use of some tactic, how can I do it?}

You need to use the {\tt proof with T} command and add {\ldots} at the
end of your sentences.

For instance:
\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B C : Prop, A -> B/\C -> A/\B/\C.
Proof with assumption.
intros.
split...
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{I want to execute the {\texttt proof with} tactic only if it solves the goal, how can I do it?}

You need to use the {\try} and {\solve} tactics. For instance:
\begin{coq_example}
Require Import ZArith.
Require Ring.
Open Local Scope Z_scope.
Goal forall a b c : Z, a+b=b+a.
Proof with try solve [ring].
intros...
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{How can I do the opposite of the {\intro} tactic?}

You can use the {\generalize} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Goal forall A B : Prop, A->B-> A/\B.
intros.
generalize H.
intro.
auto.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{One of the hypothesis is an equality between a variable and some term, I want to get rid of this variable, how can I do it?}

You can use the {\subst} tactic. This will rewrite the equality everywhere and clear the assumption.

\Question{What can I do if I get ``{\tt generated subgoal term has metavariables in it }''?}

You should use the {\eapply} tactic, this will generate some goals containing metavariables. 

\Question{How can I instantiate some metavariable?}

Just use the {\instantiate} tactic.


\Question{What is the use of the {\pattern} tactic?}

The {\pattern} tactic transforms the current goal, performing
beta-expansion on all the applications featuring this tactic's
argument. For instance, if the current goal includes a subterm {\tt
phi(t)}, then {\tt pattern t} transforms the subterm into {\tt (fun
x:A => phi(x)) t}. This can be useful when {\apply} fails on matching,
to abstract the appropriate terms.

\Question{What is the difference between assert, cut and generalize?}

PS: Notice for people that are interested in proof rendering that \assert
and {\pose} (and \cut) are not rendered the same as {\generalize} (see the
HELM experimental rendering tool at \ahref{http://helm.cs.unibo.it/library.html}{\url{http://helm.cs.unibo.it}}, link
HELM, link COQ Online). Indeed {\generalize} builds a beta-expanded term
while \assert, {\pose} and {\cut} uses a let-in.

\begin{verbatim}
  (* Goal is T *)
  generalize (H1 H2).
  (* Goal is A->T *)
  ... a proof of A->T ...
\end{verbatim}

is rendered into something like
\begin{verbatim}
  (h) ... the proof of A->T ...
      we proved A->T
  (h0) by (H1 H2) we proved A
  by (h h0) we proved T
\end{verbatim}
while 
\begin{verbatim}
  (* Goal is T *)
  assert q := (H1 H2).
  (* Goal is A *)
  ... a proof of A ...
  (* Goal is A |- T *)
  ... a proof of T ...
\end{verbatim}
is rendered into something like
\begin{verbatim}
  (q) ... the proof of A ...
      we proved A
  ... the proof of T ...
  we proved T
\end{verbatim}
Otherwise said, {\generalize} is not rendered in a forward-reasoning way,
while {\assert} is.

\Question{What can I do if \Coq can not infer some implicit argument ?}

You can state explicitely what this implicit argument is. See \ref{implicit}.

\Question{How can I explicit some implicit argument ?}\label{implicit}

Just use \texttt{A:=term} where \texttt{A} is the argument.

For instance if you want to use the existence of ``nil'' on nat*nat lists:
\begin{verbatim}
exists (nil (A:=(nat*nat))).
\end{verbatim}

\iffalse
\Question{Is there anyway to do pattern matching with dependent types?}

todo
\fi

\subsection{Proof management}


\Question{How can I change the order of the subgoals?}

You can use the {\Focus} command to concentrate on some goal. When the goal is proved you will see the remaining goals.

\Question{How can I change the order of the hypothesis?}

You can use the {\tt Move ... after} command.

\Question{How can I change the name of an hypothesis?}

You can use the {\tt Rename ... into} command.

\Question{How can I delete some hypothesis?}

You can use the {\tt Clear} command.

\Question{How can use a proof which is not finished?}

You can use the {\tt Admitted} command to state your current proof as an axiom.

\Question{How can I state a conjecture?}

You can use the {\tt Admitted} command to state your current proof as an axiom.

\Question{What is the difference between a lemma, a fact and a theorem?}

From {\Coq} point of view there are no difference. But some tools can
have a different behavior when you use a lemma rather than a
theorem. For instance {\tt coqdoc} will not generate documentation for
the lemmas within your development.

\Question{How can I organize my proofs?}

You can organize your proofs using the section mechanism of \Coq. Have
a look at the manual for further information.


%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\section{Inductive and Co-inductive types}

\subsection{General}

\Question{How can I prove that two constructors are different?}

You can use the {\discriminate} tactic.

\begin{coq_example}
Inductive toto : Set := | C1 : toto | C2 : toto.
Goal C1 <> C2.
discriminate.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{During an inductive proof, how to get rid of impossible cases of an inductive definition?}

Use the {\inversion} tactic.


\Question{How can I prove that 2 terms in an inductive set are equal? Or different?}

Have a look at \coqtt{decide equality} and \coqtt{discriminate} in the \ahref{http://coq.inria.fr/doc/main.html}{Reference Manual}.

\Question{Why is the proof of \coqtt{0+n=n} on natural numbers
trivial but the proof of \coqtt{n+0=n} is not?}

 Since \coqtt{+} (\coqtt{plus}) on natural numbers is defined by analysis on its first argument

\begin{coq_example}
Print plus.
\end{coq_example}

{\noindent} The expression \coqtt{0+n} evaluates to \coqtt{n}. As {\Coq} reasons
modulo evaluation of expressions, \coqtt{0+n} and \coqtt{n} are
considered equal and the theorem \coqtt{0+n=n} is an instance of the
reflexivity of equality. On the other side, \coqtt{n+0} does not
evaluate to \coqtt{n} and a proof by induction on \coqtt{n} is
necessary to trigger the evaluation of \coqtt{+}.

\Question{Why is dependent elimination in Prop not
available by default?}

 
This is just because most of the time it is not needed. To derive a
dependent elimination principle in {\tt Prop}, use the command {\tt Scheme} and
apply the elimination scheme using the \verb=using= option of
\verb=elim=, \verb=destruct= or \verb=induction=.


\Question{Argh! I cannot write expressions like ``~{\tt if n <= p then p else n}~'', as in any programming language}
\label{minmax}

The short answer : You should use {\texttt le\_lt\_dec n p} instead.\\

That's right, you can't.
If you type for instance the following ``definition'':
\begin{coq_eval}
Reset Initial.
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example}
Definition max (n p : nat) := if n <= p then p else n.
\end{coq_example}

As \Coq~ says, the term ``~\texttt{n <= p}~'' is a proposition, i.e. a
statement that belongs to the mathematical world. There are many ways to
prove such a proposition, either by some computation, or using some already
proven theoremas. For instance, proving $3-2 \leq 2^{45503}$ is very easy,
using some theorems on arithmetical operations. If you compute both numbers
before comparing them, you risk to use a lot of time and space.


On the contrary, a function for computing the greatest of two natural numbers
is an algorithm  which, called on two natural numbers
$n$ and $p$, determines wether $n\leq p$ or $p < n$.
Such a function is a \emph{decision  procedure} for the inequality of
 \texttt{nat}.  The possibility of writing such a procedure comes 
directly from de decidability of the order $\leq$ on natural numbers.


When you write a piece of code like 
``~\texttt{if n <= p then \dots{} else \dots}~''
in a
programming language like \emph{ML} or \emph{Java}, a call to such a 
decision procedure is generated. The decision procedure is in general
a primitive function, written in a low-level language, in the correctness
of which you have to trust.

The standard Library of the system \emph{Coq} contains a  
(constructive) proof of decidability of the order $\leq$ on
\texttt{nat} : the function \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} of 
the module \texttt{Compare\_dec} of library \texttt{Arith}.

The following code shows how to define correctly \texttt{min} and
\texttt{max}, and prove some properties of these functions.

\begin{coq_example}
Require Import Compare_dec.

Definition max (n p : nat) := if le_lt_dec n p then p else n.

Definition min (n p : nat) := if le_lt_dec n p then n else p.

Eval compute in (min 4 7).

Theorem min_plus_max : forall n p, min n p + max n p  = n + p.
Proof.
 intros n p; 
 unfold min, max; 
 case (le_lt_dec n p);
 simpl; auto with arith.
Qed.

Theorem max_equiv : forall n p, max n p = p <-> n <= p.
Proof.
 unfold max; intros n p; case (le_lt_dec n p);simpl; auto.
 intuition auto with arith.
 split. 
 intro e; rewrite e; auto with arith.
 intro H; absurd (p < p); eauto with arith.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}

\Question{I wrote my own decision procedure for $\leq$, which
is much  faster than yours, but proving such theorems as
 \texttt{max\_equiv} seems to be quite difficult}

Your code is probably the following one:

\begin{coq_example}
Fixpoint my_le_lt_dec (n p :nat) {struct n}: bool  :=
 match n, p with 0, _ => true
               | S n', S p' => my_le_lt_dec n' p'
               | _   , _    => false
 end.

Definition my_max (n p:nat) := if my_le_lt_dec n p then p else n.

Definition my_min (n p:nat) := if my_le_lt_dec n p then n else p.
\end{coq_example}


For instance, the computation of \texttt{my\_max 567 321} is almost
immediate, whereas one can't wait for  the result of 
\texttt{max 56 32}, using \emph{Coq's} \texttt{le\_lt\_dec}.

This is normal. Your definition is a simple recursive function which
returns a boolean value. Coq's \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} is a \emph{certified
function}, i.e. a complex object, able not only to tell wether $n\leq p$
or $p<n$, but also of building a complete proof of the correct inequality.
What make \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} inefficient for computing \texttt{min}
and \texttt{max} is the building of a huge proof term.

Nevertheless,  \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} is very useful. Its type 
is a strong specification, using the
\texttt{sumbool} type (look at the reference manual or chapter 9 of
\cite{coqart}). Eliminations of the form
``~\texttt{case (le\_lt\_dec n p)}~'' provide proofs of
either $n \leq p$ or $p < n$, allowing to prove easily theorems as in
question~\ref{minmax}. Unfortunately, this not the case of your
\texttt{my\_le\_lt\_dec}, which returns a quite non-informative boolean
value.


\begin{coq_example}
Check le_lt_dec.
\end{coq_example}

You should keep in mind that \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} is useful to build
certified programs which need to compare natural numbers, and is not
designed to compare quickly two numbers.

Nevertheless, the \emph{extraction} of \texttt{le\_lt\_dec} towards 
\emph{Ocaml} or \emph{Haskell}, is a reasonable program for comparing two
natural numbers in Peano form in linear time.

It is also possible to keep your boolean function as a decision procedure,
but you have to establish yourself the relationship between \texttt{my\_le\_lt\_dec} and the propositions $n\leq p$ and $p<n$:

\begin{coq_example*}
Theorem my_le_lt_dec_true : 
    forall n p, my_le_lt_dec n p = true <-> n <= p.

Theorem  my_le_lt_dec_false : 
   forall n p, my_le_lt_dec n p = false <-> p < n.
\end{coq_example*}


\subsection{Recursion}

\Question{Why can't I define a non terminating program?}

 Because otherwise the decidability of the type-checking
algorithm (which involves evaluation of programs) is not ensured.  On
another side, if non terminating proofs were allowed, we could get a
proof of {\tt False}:

\begin{coq_example*}
(* This is fortunately not allowed! *)
Fixpoint InfiniteProof (n:nat) : False := InfiniteProof n.
Theorem Paradox : False.
Proof (InfiniteProof O).
\end{coq_example*}


\Question{Why only structurally well-founded loops are allowed?}

 The structural order on inductive types is a simple and
powerful notion of termination. The consistency of the Calculus of
Inductive Constructions relies on it and another consistency proof
would have to be made for stronger termination arguments (such
as the termination of the evaluation of CIC programs themselves!).

In spite of this, all non-pathological termination orders can be mapped
to a structural order. Tools to do this are provided in the file 
\vfile{\InitWf}{Wf} of the standard library of {\Coq}.

\Question{How to define loops based on non structurally smaller
recursive calls?}

 The procedure is as follows (we consider the definition of {\tt
mergesort} as an example).

\begin{itemize}

\item Define the termination order, say {\tt R} on the type {\tt A} of
the arguments of the loop.

\begin{coq_eval}
Open Scope R_scope.
Require Import List.
\end{coq_eval}

\begin{coq_example*}
Definition R (a b:list nat) := length a < length b.
\end{coq_example*}

\item Prove that this order is well-founded (in fact that all elements in {\tt A} are accessible along {\tt R}).

\begin{coq_example*}
Lemma Rwf : well_founded R.
\end{coq_example*}

\item Define the step function (which needs proofs that recursive
calls are on smaller arguments).

\begin{coq_example*}
Definition split (l : list nat) 
   : {l1: list nat | R l1 l} * {l2 : list nat | R l2 l}
   := (* ... *) .
Definition concat (l1 l2 : list nat) : list nat := (* ... *) .
Definition merge_step (l : list nat) (f: forall l':list nat, R l' l -> list nat) :=
  let (lH1,lH2) := (split l) in
  let (l1,H1) := lH1 in
  let (l2,H2) := lH2 in
  concat (f l1 H1) (f l2 H2).
\end{coq_example*}

\item Define the recursive function by fixpoint on the step function.

\begin{coq_example*}
Definition merge := Fix Rwf (fun _ => list nat) merge_step.
\end{coq_example*}

\end{itemize}

\Question{What is behind the accessibility and well-foundedness proofs?}

 Well-foundedness of some relation {\tt R} on some type {\tt A}
is defined as the accessibility of all elements of {\tt A} along {\tt R}.

\begin{coq_example}
Print well_founded.
Print Acc.
\end{coq_example}

The structure of the accessibility predicate is a well-founded tree
branching at each node {\tt x} in {\tt A} along all the nodes {\tt x'}
less than {\tt x} along {\tt R}. Any sequence of elements of {\tt A}
decreasing along the order {\tt R} are branches in the accessibility
tree. Hence any decreasing along {\tt R} is mapped into a structural
decreasing in the accessibility tree of {\tt R}. This is emphasised in
the definition of {\tt fix} which recurs not on its argument {\tt x:A}
but on the accessibility of this argument along {\tt R}.

See file \vfile{\InitWf}{Wf}.

\Question{How to perform simultaneous double induction?}

 In general a (simultaneous) double induction is simply solved by an
induction on the first hypothesis followed by an inversion over the
second hypothesis. Here is an example

\begin{coq_eval}
Reset Initial.
\end{coq_eval}

\begin{coq_example}
Inductive even : nat -> Prop :=
  | even_O : even 0
  | even_S : forall n:nat, even n -> even (S (S n)).

Inductive odd : nat -> Prop :=
  | odd_SO : odd 1
  | odd_S : forall n:nat, odd n -> odd (S (S n)).

Lemma not_even_and_odd : forall n:nat, even n -> odd n -> False.
induction 1.
  inversion 1.
  inversion 1. apply IHeven; trivial.
\end{coq_example}
\begin{coq_eval}
Qed.
\end{coq_eval}

In case the type of the second induction hypothesis is not
dependent, {\tt inversion} can just be replaced by {\tt destruct}.

\Question{How to define a function by simultaneous double recursion?}

 The same trick applies, you can even use the pattern-matching
compilation algorithm to do the work for you. Here is an example:

\begin{coq_example}
Fixpoint minus (n m:nat) {struct n} : nat :=
  match n, m with
  | O, _ => 0
  | S k, O => S k
  | S k, S l => minus k l
  end.
Print  minus.
\end{coq_example}

In case of dependencies in the type of the induction objects
$t_1$ and $t_2$, an extra argument stating $t_1=t_2$ must be given to
the fixpoint definition

\Question{How to perform nested and double induction?}

 To reason by nested (i.e. lexicographic) induction, just reason by
induction on the successive components.

\smallskip

Double induction (or induction on pairs) is a restriction of the
lexicographic induction. Here is an example of double induction.

\begin{coq_example}
Lemma nat_double_ind : 
forall P : nat -> nat -> Prop, P 0 0 -> 
  (forall m n, P m n -> P m (S n)) -> 
  (forall m n, P m n -> P (S m) n) -> 
     forall m n, P m n.
intros P H00 HmS HSn; induction m.
(* case 0 *)
induction n; [assumption | apply HmS; apply IHn].
(* case Sm *)
intro n; apply HSn; apply IHm.
\end{coq_example}
\begin{coq_eval}
Qed.
\end{coq_eval}

\Question{How to define a function by nested recursion?}

 The same trick applies. Here is the example of Ackermann
function.

\begin{coq_example}
Fixpoint ack (n:nat) : nat -> nat :=
  match n with
  | O => S
  | S n' =>
     (fix ack' (m:nat) : nat :=
        match m with
        | O => ack n' 1
        | S m' => ack n' (ack' m')
        end)
  end.
\end{coq_example}


\subsection{Co-inductive types}

\Question{I have a cofixpoint $t:=F(t)$ and I want to prove $t=F(t)$. How to do it?}

Just case-expand $F({\tt t})$ then complete by a trivial case analysis.
Here is what it gives on e.g. the type of streams on naturals

\begin{coq_eval}
Set Implicit Arguments.
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example}
CoInductive Stream (A:Set) : Set :=
  Cons : A -> Stream A -> Stream A.
CoFixpoint nats (n:nat) : Stream nat := Cons n (nats (S n)).
Lemma Stream_unfold : 
   forall n:nat, nats n = Cons n (nats (S n)).
Proof.
  intro;
  change (nats n = match nats n with
                  | Cons x s => Cons x s
                  end).
  case (nats n); reflexivity.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}



\section{Syntax and notations}

\Question{I do not want to type ``forall'' because it is too long, what can I do?}

You can define your own notation for forall:
\begin{verbatim}
Notation "fa x : t, P" := (forall x:t, P) (at level 200, x ident).
\end{verbatim}
or if your are using {\CoqIde} you can define a pretty symbol for for all and an input method (see \ref{forallcoqide}).



\Question{How can I define a notation for square?}

You can use for instance:
\begin{verbatim}
Notation "x ^2" := (Rmult x x) (at level 20).
\end{verbatim}
Note that you can not use:
\begin{texttt}
Notation "x $^²$" := (Rmult x x) (at level 20).
\end{texttt}
because ``$^2$'' is an iso-latin character. If you really want this kind of notation you should use UTF-8.


\Question{Why ``no associativity'' and  ``left associativity'' at the same level does not work?}

Because we relie on camlp4 for syntactical analysis and camlp4 does not really implement no associativity. By default, non associative operators are defined as right associative.



\Question{How can I know the associativity associated with a level?}

You can do ``Print Grammar constr'', and decode the output from camlp4, good luck !

\section{Modules}




%%%%%%%
\section{\Ltac}

\Question{What is {\Ltac}?}

{\Ltac} is the tactic language for \Coq. It provides the user with a
high-level ``toolbox'' for tactic creation.

\Question{Why do I always get the same error message?}


\Question{Is there any printing command in {\Ltac}?}

You can use the {\idtac} tactic with a string argument. This string
will be printed out. The same applies to the {\fail} tactic

\Question{What is the syntax for let in {\Ltac}?}

If $x_i$ are identifiers and $e_i$ and $expr$ are tactic expressions, then let reads:
\begin{center}
{\tt let $x_1$:=$e_1$ with $x_2$:=$e_2$\ldots with $x_n$:=$e_n$ in
$expr$}.
\end{center}
Beware that if $expr$ is complex (i.e. features at least a sequence) parenthesis
should be added around it. For example: 
\begin{coq_example}
Ltac twoIntro := let x:=intro in (x;x).
\end{coq_example}

\Question{What is the syntax for pattern matching in {\Ltac}?}

Pattern matching on a term $expr$ (non-linear first order unification)
with patterns $p_i$ and tactic expressions $e_i$ reads:
\begin{center}
\hspace{10ex}
{\tt match $expr$ with
\hspace*{2ex}$p_1$ => $e_1$
\hspace*{1ex}\textbar$p_2$ => $e_2$
\hspace*{1ex}\ldots
\hspace*{1ex}\textbar$p_n$ => $e_n$
\hspace*{1ex}\textbar\ \textunderscore\ => $e_{n+1}$
end.
}
\end{center}
Underscore matches all terms.

\Question{What is the semantics for ``match goal''?}

The semantics of {\tt match goal} depends on whether it returns
tactics or not.  The {\tt match goal} expression matches the current
goal against a series of patterns: {$hyp_1 {\ldots} hyp_n$ \textbar-
$ccl$}. It uses a first-order unification algorithm and in case of
success, if the right-hand-side is an expression, it tries to type it
while if the right-hand-side is a tactic, it tries to apply it.  If the
typing or the tactic application fails, the {\tt match goal} tries all
the possible combinations of $hyp_i$ before dropping the branch and
moving to the next one. Underscore matches all terms.

\Question{Why can't I use a ``match goal'' returning a tactic in a non
tail-recursive position?}

This is precisely because the semantics of {\tt match goal} is to
apply the tactic on the right as soon as a pattern unifies what is
meaningful only in tail-recursive uses.

The semantics in non tail-recursive call could have been the one used
for terms (i.e. fail if the tactic expression is not typable, but
don't try to apply it). For uniformity of semantics though, this has
been rejected.

\Question{How can I generate a new name?}

You can use the following syntax:
{\tt let id:=fresh in \ldots}\\
For example:
\begin{coq_example}
Ltac introIdGen := let id:=fresh in intro id.
\end{coq_example}


\iffalse
\Question{How can I access the type of a term?}

You can use typeof.
todo
\fi

\Question{How can I define static and dynamic code?}

\section{Tactics written in Ocaml}

\Question{Can you show me an example of a tactic written in OCaml?}

You have some examples of tactics written in Ocaml in the ``contrib'' directory of {\Coq} sources. 




\section{Case studies}


\Question{How can I define vectors or lists of size n?}

\Question{How to prove that 2 sets are different?}

 You need to find a property true on one set and false on the
other one. As an example we show how to prove that {\tt bool} and {\tt
nat} are discriminable. As discrimination property we take the
property to have no more than 2 elements.

\begin{coq_example*}
Theorem nat_bool_discr : bool <> nat.
Proof.
  pose (discr :=
    fun X:Set =>
      ~ (forall a b:X, ~ (forall x:X, x <> a -> x <> b -> False))).
  intro Heq; assert (H: discr bool).
  intro H; apply (H true false); destruct x; auto.
  rewrite Heq in H; apply H; clear H.
  destruct a; destruct b as [|n]; intro H0; eauto.
  destruct n; [ apply (H0 2); discriminate | eauto ].
Qed.
\end{coq_example*}

\Question{Is there an axiom-free proof of Streicher's axiom $K$ for
the equality on {\tt nat}?}
\label{K-nat}

Yes, because equality is decidable on {\tt nat}. Here is the proof.

\begin{coq_example*}
Require Import Eqdep_dec.
Require Import Peano_dec.
Theorem K_nat :
  forall (x:nat) (P:x = x -> Prop), P (refl_equal x) -> forall p:x = x, P p.
Proof.
intros; apply K_dec_set with (p := p).
apply eq_nat_dec.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example*}

Similarly, we have

\begin{coq_example*}
Theorem eq_rect_eq_nat :
  forall (p:nat) (Q:nat->Type) (x:Q p) (h:p=p), x = eq_rect p Q x p h.
Proof.
intros; apply K_nat with (p := h); reflexivity.
Qed.
\end{coq_example*}

\Question{How to prove that two proofs of {\tt n<=m} on {\tt nat} are equal?}
\label{le-uniqueness}

This is provable without requiring any axiom because axiom $K$
directly holds on {\tt nat}. Here is a proof using question \ref{K-nat}.

\begin{coq_example*}
Require Import Arith.
Scheme le_ind' := Induction for le Sort Prop.
Theorem le_uniqueness_proof : forall (n m : nat) (p q : n <= m), p = q.
Proof.
induction p using le_ind'; intro q.
 replace (le_n n) with
  (eq_rect _ (fun n0 => n <= n0) (le_n n) _ (refl_equal n)).
 2:reflexivity.
  generalize (refl_equal n).
    pattern n at 2 4 6 10, q; case q; [intro | intros m l e].
     rewrite <- eq_rect_eq_nat; trivial.
     contradiction (le_Sn_n m); rewrite <- e; assumption.
 replace (le_S n m p) with
  (eq_rect _ (fun n0 => n <= n0) (le_S n m p) _ (refl_equal (S m))).
 2:reflexivity.
  generalize (refl_equal (S m)).
    pattern (S m) at 1 3 4 6, q; case q; [intro Heq | intros m0 l HeqS].
     contradiction (le_Sn_n m); rewrite Heq; assumption.
     injection HeqS; intro Heq; generalize l HeqS.
      rewrite <- Heq; intros; rewrite <- eq_rect_eq_nat.
      rewrite (IHp l0); reflexivity.
Qed.
\end{coq_example*}

\Question{How to exploit equalities on sets}

To extract information from an equality on sets, you need to
find a predicate of sets satisfied by the elements of the sets. As an
example, let's consider the following theorem.

\begin{coq_example*}
Theorem interval_discr :
  forall m n:nat,
    {x : nat | x <= m} = {x : nat | x <= n} -> m = n.
\end{coq_example*}

We have a proof requiring the axiom of proof-irrelevance. We
conjecture that proof-irrelevance can be circumvented by introducing a
primitive definition of discrimination of the proofs of
\verb!{x : nat | x <= m}!.

\begin{latexonly}%
The proof can be found in file {\tt interval$\_$discr.v} in this directory.
%Here is the proof
%\begin{small}
%\begin{flushleft}
%\begin{texttt}
%\def_{\ifmmode\sb\else\subscr\fi}
%\include{interval_discr.v}
%%% WARNING semantics of \_ has changed !
%\end{texttt}
%$a\_b\_c$
%\end{flushleft}
%\end{small}
\end{latexonly}%
\begin{htmlonly}%
\ahref{./interval_discr.v}{Here} is the proof.
\end{htmlonly}

\Question{I have a problem of dependent elimination on
proofs, how to solve it?}

\begin{coq_eval}
Reset Initial.
\end{coq_eval}

\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive Def1 : Set := c1 : Def1.
Inductive DefProp : Def1 -> Prop :=
  c2 : forall d:Def1, DefProp d.
Inductive Comb : Set :=
  c3 : forall d:Def1, DefProp d -> Comb.
Lemma eq_comb :
  forall (d1 d1':Def1) (d2:DefProp d1) (d2':DefProp d1'),
    d1 = d1' -> c3 d1 d2 = c3 d1' d2'.
\end{coq_example*}

 You need to derive the dependent elimination
scheme for DefProp by hand using {\coqtt Scheme}.

\begin{coq_eval}
Abort.
\end{coq_eval}

\begin{coq_example*}
Scheme DefProp_elim := Induction for DefProp Sort Prop.
Lemma eq_comb :
  forall d1 d1':Def1,
    d1 = d1' ->
    forall (d2:DefProp d1) (d2':DefProp d1'), c3 d1 d2 = c3 d1' d2'.
intros.
destruct H.
destruct d2 using DefProp_elim.
destruct d2' using DefProp_elim.
reflexivity.
Qed.
\end{coq_example*}


\Question{And what if I want to prove the following?}

\begin{coq_example*}
Inductive natProp : nat -> Prop :=
  | p0 : natProp 0
  | pS : forall n:nat, natProp n -> natProp (S n).
Inductive package : Set :=
  pack : forall n:nat, natProp n -> package.
Lemma eq_pack :
 forall n n':nat,
   n = n' ->
   forall (np:natProp n) (np':natProp n'), pack n np = pack n' np'.
\end{coq_example*}



\begin{coq_eval}
Abort.
\end{coq_eval}
\begin{coq_example*}
Scheme natProp_elim := Induction for natProp Sort Prop.
Definition pack_S : package -> package.
destruct 1.
apply (pack (S n)).
apply pS; assumption.
Defined.
Lemma eq_pack :
  forall n n':nat,
    n = n' ->
    forall (np:natProp n) (np':natProp n'), pack n np = pack n' np'.
intros n n' Heq np np'.
generalize dependent n'.
induction np using natProp_elim.
induction np' using natProp_elim; intros; auto.
 discriminate Heq.
induction np' using natProp_elim; intros; auto.
 discriminate Heq.
change (pack_S (pack n np) = pack_S (pack n0 np')).
apply (f_equal (A:=package)).
apply IHnp.
auto.
Qed.
\end{coq_example*}







\section{Publishing tools}

\Question{How can I generate some latex from my development?}

You can use {\tt coqdoc}.

\Question{How can I generate some HTML from my development?}

You can use {\tt coqdoc}.

\Question{How can I generate some dependency graph from my development?}

\Question{How can I cite some {\Coq} in my latex document?}

You can use {\tt coq\_tex}.

\Question{How can I cite the {\Coq} reference manual?}

You can use this bibtex entry:
\begin{verbatim}
@Manual{Coq:manual,
  title =        {The Coq proof assistant reference manual},
  author =       {\mbox{The Coq development team}},
  organization = {LogiCal Project},
  note =         {Version 8.0},
  year =         {2004},
  url =          "http://coq.inria.fr"
}
\end{verbatim}

\Question{Where can I publish my developments in {\Coq}?}

You can submit your developments as a user contribution to the {\Coq}
development team. This ensures its liveness along the evolution and
possible changes of {\Coq}.

You can also submit your developments to the HELM/MoWGLI repository at
the University of Bologna (see
\ahref{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}{\url{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}}). For
developments submitted in this database, it is possible to visualize
the developments in natural language and execute various retrieving
requests.

\Question{How can I read my proof in natural language?}

You can submit your proof to the HELM/MoWGLI repository and use the
rendering tool provided by the server (see
\ahref{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}{\url{http://mowgli.cs.unibo.it}}).

\section{\CoqIde}

\Question{What is {\CoqIde}?}

{\CoqIde} is a gtk based GUI for \Coq.

\Question{How to enable Emacs keybindings?}
 Insert \texttt{gtk-key-theme-name = "Emacs"}
    in your \texttt{.coqide-gtk2rc} file. It may be in the current dir
    or in \verb#$HOME# dir. This is done by default.

%$ juste pour que la coloration emacs marche

\Question{How to enable antialiased fonts?}

 Set the \verb#GDK_USE_XFT# variable to \verb#1#. This is by default with \verb#Gtk >= 2.2#.
    If some of your fonts are not available, set \verb#GDK_USE_XFT# to \verb#0#.

\Question{How to use those Forall and Exists pretty symbols?}\label{forallcoqide}
 Thanks to the notation features in \Coq, you just need to insert these
lines in your {\Coq} buffer:\\
\begin{texttt}
Notation "$\forall$ x : t, P" := (forall x:t, P) (at level 200, x ident).
\end{texttt}\\
\begin{texttt}
Notation "$\exists$ x : t, P" := (exists x:t, P) (at level 200, x ident).
\end{texttt}

Copy/Paste of these lines from this file will not work outside of \CoqIde.
You need to load a file containing these lines or to enter the $\forall$
using an input method (see \ref{inputmeth}). To try it just use \verb#Require Import utf8# from inside
\CoqIde. 
To enable these notations automatically start coqide with
\begin{verbatim}
	coqide -l utf8
\end{verbatim}
In the ide subdir of {\Coq} library, you will find a sample utf8.v with some 
pretty simple notations.

\Question{How to define an input method for non ASCII symbols?}\label{inputmeth}

\begin{itemize}
\item First solution: type \verb#<CONTROL><SHIFT>2200# to enter a forall in the script widow. 
	2200 is the hexadecimal code for forall in unicode charts and is encoded as 	
	in UTF-8.
	2203 is for exists. See \ahref{http://www.unicode.org}{\url{http://www.unicode.org}} for more codes.
\item Second solution: rebind \verb#<AltGr>a# to forall and \verb#<AltGr>e# to exists. 
	Under X11, you need to use something like
\begin{verbatim}
		xmodmap -e "keycode  24 = a A F13 F13" 
		xmodmap -e "keycode  26 = e E F14 F14"
\end{verbatim}
	and then to add   
\begin{verbatim}
		bind "F13" {"insert-at-cursor" ("")}
		bind "F14" {"insert-at-cursor" ("")}
\end{verbatim}
	to your "binding "text"" section in \verb#.coqiderc-gtk2rc.#
	The strange ("") argument is the UTF-8 encoding for
	0x2200. 
	You can compute these encodings using the lablgtk2 toplevel with 
\begin{verbatim}		
Glib.Utf8.from_unichar 0x2200;;
\end{verbatim}
	Further symbols can be bound on higher Fxx keys or on even on other keys you
	do not need .
\end{itemize}

\Question{How to build a custom {\CoqIde} with user ml code?}
 Use 
	coqmktop -ide -byte m1.cmo...mi.cmo
    or 
	coqmktop -ide -opt m1.cmx...mi.cmx

\Question{How to customize the shortcuts for menus?}
 Two solutions are offered:
\begin{itemize}
\item Edit \$HOME/.coqide.keys by hand or
\item Add "gtk-can-change-accels = 1" in your .coqide-gtk2rc file. Then
    from \CoqIde, you may select a menu entry and press the desired 
    shortcut. 
\end{itemize}

\Question{What encoding should I use? What is this $\backslash$x\{iiii\} in my file?}
 The encoding option is related to the way files are saved. 
 Keep it as UTF-8 until it becomes important for you to exchange files 
 with non UTF-8 aware applications.
 If you choose something else than UTF-8, then missing characters will 
 be encoded by $\backslash$x\{....\} or $\backslash$x\{........\}
 where each dot is an hex. digit. 
 The number between braces is the hexadecimal UNICODE index for the
  missing character.
    



\section{Extraction}

\Question{What is program extraction?}

Program extraction consist in generating a program from a constructive proof.

\Question{Which language can I extract to?}

You can extract your programs to Objective Caml and Haskell.

\Question{How can I extract an incomplete proof?}

You can provide programs for your axioms.



%%%%%%%
\section{Glossary}

\Question{Can you explain me what an evaluable constant is?}

An evaluable constant is a constant which is unfoldable.

\Question{What is a goal?}

The goal is the statement to be proved.

\Question{What is a meta variable?}

A meta variable in {\Coq} represents a ``hole'', i.e. a part of a proof
that is still unknown. 

\Question{What is Gallina?}  

Gallina is the specification language of \Coq. Complete documentation
of this language can be found in the Reference Manual.

\Question{What is The Vernacular?}  

It is the language of commands of Gallina i.e. definitions, lemmas, {\ldots}  


\Question{What is a dependent type?}

A dependant type is a type which depends on some term. For instance
``vector of size n'' is a dependant type representing all the vectors
of size $n$. Its type depends on $n$

\Question{What is a proof by reflection?}

This is a proof generated by some computation which is done using the
internal reduction of {\Coq} (not using the tactic language of {\Coq}
(\Ltac) nor the implementation language for \Coq).  An example of
tactic using the reflection mechanism is the {\ring} tactic. The
reflection method consist in reflecting a subset of {\Coq} language (for
example the arithmetical expressions) into an object of the \Coq
language itself (in this case an inductive type denoting arithmetical
expressions).  For more information see~\cite{howe,harrison,boutin}
and the last chapter of the Coq'Art.

\Question{What is intuitionistic logic?}

This is any logic which does not assume that ``A or not A''.


\Question{What is proof-irrelevance?}

See question \ref{proof-irrelevance}


\Question{What is the difference between opaque and transparent?}{\label{opaque}}	

Opaque definitions can not be unfolded but transparent ones can.


\section{Troubleshooting}

\Question{What can I do when {\tt Qed.} is slow?}

Sometime you can use the {\abstracttac} tactic, which makes as if you had
stated some local lemma, this speeds up the typing process.

\Question{Why \texttt{Reset Initial.} does not work when using \texttt{coqc}?}

The initial state corresponds to the state of coqtop when the interactive
session began. It does not make sense in files to compile.


\Question{What can I do if I get ``No more subgoals but non-instantiated existential variables''?}

This means that {\eauto} or {\eapply} didn't instantiate an
existential variable which eventually got erased by some computation.
You have to backtrack to the faulty occurrence of {\eauto} or
{\eapply} and give the missing argument an explicit value.

Note that you can see what the current existential are using the {\tt
  Show Existentials} command.

\begin{coq_example}
Lemma example_show_existentials :  forall a b c:nat, a=b -> b=c -> a=c.
Proof.
intros.
eapply trans_equal.
Show Existentials.
eassumption.
assumption.
Qed.
\end{coq_example}


\Question{What can I do if I get ``Cannot solve a second-order unification problem''?}

You can help {\Coq} using the {\pattern} tactic.

\Question{Why does {\Coq} tell me that \texttt{\{x:A|(P x)\}} is not convertible with \texttt{(sig A P)}?}

 This is because \texttt{\{x:A|P x\}} is a notation for
\texttt{sig (fun x:A => P x)}. Since {\Coq} does not reason up to
$\eta$-conversion, this is different from \texttt{sig P}.


\Question{I copy-paste a term and {\Coq} says it is not convertible
  to the original term. Sometimes it even says the copied term is not
well-typed.}

 This is probably due to invisible implicit information (implicit
arguments, coercions and Cases annotations) in the printed term, which
is not re-synthesised from the copied-pasted term in the same way as
it is in the original term.

  Consider for instance {\tt (@eq Type True True)}. This term is
printed as {\tt True=True} and re-parsed as {\tt (@eq Prop True
True)}. The two terms are not convertible (hence they fool tactics
like {\tt pattern}).

  There is currently no satisfactory answer to the problem. However,
the command {\tt Set Printing All} is useful for diagnosing the
problem.
 
  Due to coercions, one may even face type-checking errors. In some
rare cases, the criterion to hide coercions is a bit too loose, which
may result in a typing error message if the parser is not able to find
again the missing coercion.



\section{Conclusion and Farewell.}
\label{ccl}

\Question{What if my question isn't answered here?} 
\label{lastquestion}

Don't panic \verb+:-)+. You can try the {\Coq} manual~\cite{Coq:manual} for a technical
description of the prover. The Coq'Art~\cite{Coq:coqart} is the first
book written on {\Coq} and provides a comprehensive review of the
theorem prover as well as a number of example and exercises. Finally,
the tutorial~\cite{Coq:Tutorial} provides a smooth introduction to
theorem proving in \Coq.


%%%%%%%
\newpage
\nocite{LaTeX:intro}
\nocite{LaTeX:symb}
\bibliography{fk}

%%%%%%%
\typeout{*********************************************}
\typeout{********* That makes \thequestion{\space} questions **********}
\typeout{*********************************************}

\end{document}