% TODO: unify the use of \form and \type to mean a type % or use \form specifically for a type of type Prop \chapter{Tactics \index{Tactics} \label{Tactics}} A deduction rule is a link between some (unique) formula, that we call the {\em conclusion} and (several) formulas that we call the {\em premises}. A deduction rule can be read in two ways. The first one says: {\it ``if I know this and this then I can deduce this''}. For instance, if I have a proof of $A$ and a proof of $B$ then I have a proof of $A \land B$. This is forward reasoning from premises to conclusion. The other way says: {\it ``to prove this I have to prove this and this''}. For instance, to prove $A \land B$, I have to prove $A$ and I have to prove $B$. This is backward reasoning from conclusion to premises. We say that the conclusion is the {\em goal}\index{goal} to prove and premises are the {\em subgoals}\index{subgoal}. The tactics implement {\em backward reasoning}. When applied to a goal, a tactic replaces this goal with the subgoals it generates. We say that a tactic reduces a goal to its subgoal(s). Each (sub)goal is denoted with a number. The current goal is numbered 1. By default, a tactic is applied to the current goal, but one can address a particular goal in the list by writing {\sl n:\tac} which means {\it ``apply tactic {\tac} to goal number {\sl n}''}. We can show the list of subgoals by typing {\tt Show} (see Section~\ref{Show}). Since not every rule applies to a given statement, every tactic cannot be used to reduce any goal. In other words, before applying a tactic to a given goal, the system checks that some {\em preconditions} are satisfied. If it is not the case, the tactic raises an error message. Tactics are built from atomic tactics and tactic expressions (which extends the folklore notion of tactical) to combine those atomic tactics. This chapter is devoted to atomic tactics. The tactic language will be described in Chapter~\ref{TacticLanguage}. \section{Invocation of tactics \label{tactic-syntax} \index{tactic@{\tac}}} A tactic is applied as an ordinary command. It may be preceded by a goal selector: {\tt all} if the tactic is to be applied to every focused goal simultaneously, or a natural number $n$ if it is to be applied to the $n$-th goal. If no selector is specified, the default selector (see Section \ref{default-selector}) is used. \newcommand{\selector}{\nterm{selector}} \begin{tabular}{lcl} {\selector} & := & {\tt all} | {\num}\\ {\commandtac} & ::= & {\selector} {\tt :} {\tac} {\tt .}\\ & $|$ & {\tac} {\tt .} \end{tabular} \subsection[\tt Set Default Goal Selector ``\selector''.] {\tt Set Default Goal Selector ``\selector''. \optindex{Default Goal Selector} \label{default-selector}} After using this command, the default selector -- used when no selector is specified when applying a tactic -- is set to the chosen value. The initial value is $1$, hence the tactics are, by default, applied to the first goal. Using {\tt Set Default Goal Selector ``all''} will make is so that tactics are, by default, applied to every goal simultaneously. Then, to apply a tactic {\tt tac} to the first goal only, you can write {\tt 1:tac}. \subsection[\tt Test Default Goal Selector.] {\tt Test Default Goal Selector.} This command displays the current default selector. \subsection{Bindings list \index{Binding list} \label{Binding-list}} Tactics that take a term as argument may also support a bindings list, so as to instantiate some parameters of the term by name or position. The general form of a term equipped with a bindings list is {\tt {\term} with {\bindinglist}} where {\bindinglist} may be of two different forms: \begin{itemize} \item In a bindings list of the form {\tt (\vref$_1$ := \term$_1$) \dots\ (\vref$_n$ := \term$_n$)}, {\vref} is either an {\ident} or a {\num}. The references are determined according to the type of {\term}. If \vref$_i$ is an identifier, this identifier has to be bound in the type of {\term} and the binding provides the tactic with an instance for the parameter of this name. If \vref$_i$ is some number $n$, this number denotes the $n$-th non dependent premise of the {\term}, as determined by the type of {\term}. \ErrMsg \errindex{No such binder} \item A bindings list can also be a simple list of terms {\tt \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$}. In that case the references to which these terms correspond are determined by the tactic. In case of {\tt induction}, {\tt destruct}, {\tt elim} and {\tt case} (see Section~\ref{elim}) the terms have to provide instances for all the dependent products in the type of \term\ while in the case of {\tt apply}, or of {\tt constructor} and its variants, only instances for the dependent products that are not bound in the conclusion of the type are required. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not the right number of missing arguments} \end{itemize} \subsection{Occurrences sets and occurrences clauses} \label{Occurrences_clauses} \index{Occurrences clauses} An occurrences clause is a modifier to some tactics that obeys the following syntax: \begin{tabular}{lcl} {\occclause} & ::= & {\tt in} {\occgoalset} \\ {\occgoalset} & ::= & \zeroone{{\ident$_1$} \zeroone{\atoccurrences} {\tt ,} \\ & & {\dots} {\tt ,}\\ & & {\ident$_m$} \zeroone{\atoccurrences}}\\ & & \zeroone{{\tt |-} \zeroone{{\tt *} \zeroone{\atoccurrences}}}\\ & | & {\tt *} {\tt |-} \zeroone{{\tt *} \zeroone{\atoccurrences}}\\ & | & {\tt *}\\ {\atoccurrences} & ::= & {\tt at} {\occlist}\\ {\occlist} & ::= & \zeroone{{\tt -}} {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$} \end{tabular} The role of an occurrence clause is to select a set of occurrences of a {\term} in a goal. In the first case, the {{\ident$_i$} \zeroone{{\tt at} {\num$_1^i$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_i}^i$}}} parts indicate that occurrences have to be selected in the hypotheses named {\ident$_i$}. If no numbers are given for hypothesis {\ident$_i$}, then all the occurrences of {\term} in the hypothesis are selected. If numbers are given, they refer to occurrences of {\term} when the term is printed using option {\tt Set Printing All} (see Section~\ref{SetPrintingAll}), counting from left to right. In particular, occurrences of {\term} in implicit arguments (see Section~\ref{Implicit Arguments}) or coercions (see Section~\ref{Coercions}) are counted. If a minus sign is given between {\tt at} and the list of occurrences, it negates the condition so that the clause denotes all the occurrences except the ones explicitly mentioned after the minus sign. As an exception to the left-to-right order, the occurrences in the {\tt return} subexpression of a {\tt match} are considered {\em before} the occurrences in the matched term. In the second case, the {\tt *} on the left of {\tt |-} means that all occurrences of {\term} are selected in every hypothesis. In the first and second case, if {\tt *} is mentioned on the right of {\tt |-}, the occurrences of the conclusion of the goal have to be selected. If some numbers are given, then only the occurrences denoted by these numbers are selected. In no numbers are given, all occurrences of {\term} in the goal are selected. Finally, the last notation is an abbreviation for {\tt * |- *}. Note also that {\tt |-} is optional in the first case when no {\tt *} is given. Here are some tactics that understand occurrences clauses: {\tt set}, {\tt remember}, {\tt induction}, {\tt destruct}. \SeeAlso~Sections~\ref{tactic:set}, \ref{Tac-induction}, \ref{SetPrintingAll}. \section{Applying theorems} \subsection{\tt exact \term} \tacindex{exact} \label{exact} This tactic applies to any goal. It gives directly the exact proof term of the goal. Let {\T} be our goal, let {\tt p} be a term of type {\tt U} then {\tt exact p} succeeds iff {\tt T} and {\tt U} are convertible (see Section~\ref{conv-rules}). \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not an exact proof} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{eexact \term}\tacindex{eexact} This tactic behaves like \texttt{exact} but is able to handle terms and goals with meta-variables. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt assumption} \tacindex{assumption} This tactic looks in the local context for an hypothesis which type is equal to the goal. If it is the case, the subgoal is proved. Otherwise, it fails. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such assumption} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \tacindex{eassumption} \item \texttt{eassumption} This tactic behaves like \texttt{assumption} but is able to handle goals with meta-variables. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt refine \term} \tacindex{refine} \label{refine} \label{refine-example} \index{?@{\texttt{?}}} This tactic applies to any goal. It behaves like {\tt exact} with a big difference: the user can leave some holes (denoted by \texttt{\_} or {\tt (\_:\type)}) in the term. {\tt refine} will generate as many subgoals as there are holes in the term. The type of holes must be either synthesized by the system or declared by an explicit cast like \verb|(_:nat->Prop)|. Any subgoal that occurs in other subgoals is automatically shelved, as if calling {\tt shelve\_unifiable} (see Section~\ref{shelve}). This low-level tactic can be useful to advanced users. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Inductive Option : Set := | Fail : Option | Ok : bool -> Option. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example} Definition get : forall x:Option, x <> Fail -> bool. refine (fun x:Option => match x return x <> Fail -> bool with | Fail => _ | Ok b => fun _ => b end). intros; absurd (Fail = Fail); trivial. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} Defined. \end{coq_example*} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{invalid argument}: the tactic \texttt{refine} does not know what to do with the term you gave. \item \texttt{Refine passed ill-formed term}: the term you gave is not a valid proof (not easy to debug in general). This message may also occur in higher-level tactics that call \texttt{refine} internally. \item \errindex{Cannot infer a term for this placeholder}: there is a hole in the term you gave which type cannot be inferred. Put a cast around it. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt simple refine \term}\tacindex{simple refine} This tactic behaves like {\tt refine}, but it does not shelve any subgoal. It does not perform any beta-reduction either. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt apply \term} \tacindex{apply} \label{apply} \label{eapply} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\term} is a term well-formed in the local context. The tactic {\tt apply} tries to match the current goal against the conclusion of the type of {\term}. If it succeeds, then the tactic returns as many subgoals as the number of non-dependent premises of the type of {\term}. If the conclusion of the type of {\term} does not match the goal {\em and} the conclusion is an inductive type isomorphic to a tuple type, then each component of the tuple is recursively matched to the goal in the left-to-right order. The tactic {\tt apply} relies on first-order unification with dependent types unless the conclusion of the type of {\term} is of the form {\tt ($P$ $t_1$ \dots\ $t_n$)} with $P$ to be instantiated. In the latter case, the behavior depends on the form of the goal. If the goal is of the form {\tt (fun $x$ => $Q$)~$u_1$~\ldots~$u_n$} and the $t_i$ and $u_i$ unifies, then $P$ is taken to be {\tt (fun $x$ => $Q$)}. Otherwise, {\tt apply} tries to define $P$ by abstracting over $t_1$~\ldots ~$t_n$ in the goal. See {\tt pattern} in Section~\ref{pattern} to transform the goal so that it gets the form {\tt (fun $x$ => $Q$)~$u_1$~\ldots~$u_n$}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Impossible to unify \dots\ with \dots} The {\tt apply} tactic failed to match the conclusion of {\term} and the current goal. You can help the {\tt apply} tactic by transforming your goal with the {\tt change} or {\tt pattern} tactics (see sections~\ref{pattern},~\ref{change}). \item \errindex{Unable to find an instance for the variables {\ident} \dots\ {\ident}} This occurs when some instantiations of the premises of {\term} are not deducible from the unification. This is the case, for instance, when you want to apply a transitivity property. In this case, you have to use one of the variants below: \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt apply {\term} with {\term$_1$} \dots\ {\term$_n$}} \tacindex{apply \dots\ with} Provides {\tt apply} with explicit instantiations for all dependent premises of the type of {\term} that do not occur in the conclusion and consequently cannot be found by unification. Notice that {\term$_1$} \mbox{\dots} {\term$_n$} must be given according to the order of these dependent premises of the type of {\term}. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not the right number of missing arguments} \item{\tt apply {\term} with ({\vref$_1$} := {\term$_1$}) \dots\ ({\vref$_n$} := {\term$_n$})} This also provides {\tt apply} with values for instantiating premises. Here, variables are referred by names and non-dependent products by increasing numbers (see syntax in Section~\ref{Binding-list}). \item {\tt apply \term$_1$ , \mbox{\dots} , \term$_n$} This is a shortcut for {\tt apply} {\term$_1$} {\tt ; [ ..~|} \ldots~{\tt ; [ ..~| {\tt apply} {\term$_n$} ]} \ldots~{\tt ]}, i.e. for the successive applications of {\term$_{i+1}$} on the last subgoal generated by {\tt apply} {\term$_i$}, starting from the application of {\term$_1$}. \item {\tt eapply \term}\tacindex{eapply} The tactic {\tt eapply} behaves like {\tt apply} but it does not fail when no instantiations are deducible for some variables in the premises. Rather, it turns these variables into existential variables which are variables still to instantiate (see Section~\ref{evars}). The instantiation is intended to be found later in the proof. \item {\tt simple apply {\term}} \tacindex{simple apply} This behaves like {\tt apply} but it reasons modulo conversion only on subterms that contain no variables to instantiate. For instance, the following example does not succeed because it would require the conversion of {\tt id ?foo} and {\tt O}. \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Definition id (x : nat) := x. Hypothesis H : forall y, id y = y. Goal O = O. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} Fail simple apply H. \end{coq_example} Because it reasons modulo a limited amount of conversion, {\tt simple apply} fails quicker than {\tt apply} and it is then well-suited for uses in used-defined tactics that backtrack often. Moreover, it does not traverse tuples as {\tt apply} does. \item \zeroone{{\tt simple}} {\tt apply} {\term$_1$} \zeroone{{\tt with} {\bindinglist$_1$}} {\tt ,} \ldots {\tt ,} {\term$_n$} \zeroone{{\tt with} {\bindinglist$_n$}}\\ \zeroone{{\tt simple}} {\tt eapply} {\term$_1$} \zeroone{{\tt with} {\bindinglist$_1$}} {\tt ,} \ldots {\tt ,} {\term$_n$} \zeroone{{\tt with} {\bindinglist$_n$}} This summarizes the different syntaxes for {\tt apply} and {\tt eapply}. \item {\tt lapply {\term}} \tacindex{lapply} This tactic applies to any goal, say {\tt G}. The argument {\term} has to be well-formed in the current context, its type being reducible to a non-dependent product {\tt A -> B} with {\tt B} possibly containing products. Then it generates two subgoals {\tt B->G} and {\tt A}. Applying {\tt lapply H} (where {\tt H} has type {\tt A->B} and {\tt B} does not start with a product) does the same as giving the sequence {\tt cut B. 2:apply H.} where {\tt cut} is described below. \Warning When {\term} contains more than one non dependent product the tactic {\tt lapply} only takes into account the first product. \end{Variants} \Example Assume we have a transitive relation {\tt R} on {\tt nat}: \label{eapply-example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Variable R : nat -> nat -> Prop. Hypothesis Rtrans : forall x y z:nat, R x y -> R y z -> R x z. Variables n m p : nat. Hypothesis Rnm : R n m. Hypothesis Rmp : R m p. \end{coq_example*} Consider the goal {\tt (R n p)} provable using the transitivity of {\tt R}: \begin{coq_example*} Goal R n p. \end{coq_example*} The direct application of {\tt Rtrans} with {\tt apply} fails because no value for {\tt y} in {\tt Rtrans} is found by {\tt apply}: %\begin{coq_eval} %Set Printing Depth 50. %(********** The following is not correct and should produce **********) %(**** Error: generated subgoal (R n ?17) has metavariables in it *****) %\end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Fail apply Rtrans. \end{coq_example} A solution is to apply {\tt (Rtrans n m p)} or {\tt (Rtrans n m)}. \begin{coq_example} apply (Rtrans n m p). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} Note that {\tt n} can be inferred from the goal, so the following would work too. \begin{coq_example*} apply (Rtrans _ m). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} More elegantly, {\tt apply Rtrans with (y:=m)} allows only mentioning the unknown {\tt m}: \begin{coq_example*} apply Rtrans with (y := m). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} Another solution is to mention the proof of {\tt (R x y)} in {\tt Rtrans} \ldots \begin{coq_example} apply Rtrans with (1 := Rnm). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} \ldots or the proof of {\tt (R y z)}. \begin{coq_example} apply Rtrans with (2 := Rmp). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} On the opposite, one can use {\tt eapply} which postpones the problem of finding {\tt m}. Then one can apply the hypotheses {\tt Rnm} and {\tt Rmp}. This instantiates the existential variable and completes the proof. \begin{coq_example} eapply Rtrans. apply Rnm. apply Rmp. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset R. \end{coq_eval} \noindent {\bf Remark: } When the conclusion of the type of the term to apply is an inductive type isomorphic to a tuple type and {\em apply} looks recursively whether a component of the tuple matches the goal, it excludes components whose statement would result in applying an universal lemma of the form {\tt forall A, ... -> A}. Excluding this kind of lemma can be avoided by setting the following option: \begin{quote} \optindex{Universal Lemma Under Conjunction} {\tt Set Universal Lemma Under Conjunction} \end{quote} This option, which preserves compatibility with versions of {\Coq} prior to 8.4 is also available for {\tt apply {\term} in {\ident}} (see Section~\ref{apply-in}). \subsection{\tt apply {\term} in {\ident}} \label{apply-in} \tacindex{apply \dots\ in} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\term} is a term well-formed in the local context and the argument {\ident} is an hypothesis of the context. The tactic {\tt apply {\term} in {\ident}} tries to match the conclusion of the type of {\ident} against a non-dependent premise of the type of {\term}, trying them from right to left. If it succeeds, the statement of hypothesis {\ident} is replaced by the conclusion of the type of {\term}. The tactic also returns as many subgoals as the number of other non-dependent premises in the type of {\term} and of the non-dependent premises of the type of {\ident}. If the conclusion of the type of {\term} does not match the goal {\em and} the conclusion is an inductive type isomorphic to a tuple type, then the tuple is (recursively) decomposed and the first component of the tuple of which a non-dependent premise matches the conclusion of the type of {\ident}. Tuples are decomposed in a width-first left-to-right order (for instance if the type of {\tt H1} is a \verb=A <-> B= statement, and the type of {\tt H2} is \verb=A= then {\tt apply H1 in H2} transforms the type of {\tt H2} into {\tt B}). The tactic {\tt apply} relies on first-order pattern-matching with dependent types. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Statement without assumptions} This happens if the type of {\term} has no non dependent premise. \item \errindex{Unable to apply} This happens if the conclusion of {\ident} does not match any of the non dependent premises of the type of {\term}. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt apply \nelist{\term}{,} in {\ident}} This applies each of {\term} in sequence in {\ident}. \item {\tt apply \nelist{{\term} with {\bindinglist}}{,} in {\ident}} This does the same but uses the bindings in each {\bindinglist} to instantiate the parameters of the corresponding type of {\term} (see syntax of bindings in Section~\ref{Binding-list}). \item {\tt eapply \nelist{{\term} with {\bindinglist}}{,} in {\ident}} \tacindex{eapply \dots\ in} This works as {\tt apply \nelist{{\term} with {\bindinglist}}{,} in {\ident}} but turns unresolved bindings into existential variables, if any, instead of failing. \item {\tt apply \nelist{{\term} with {\bindinglist}}{,} in {\ident} as {\intropattern}} This works as {\tt apply \nelist{{\term} with {\bindinglist}}{,} in {\ident}} then applies the {\intropattern} to the hypothesis {\ident}. \item {\tt eapply \nelist{{\term} with {\bindinglist}}{,} in {\ident} as {\intropattern}} This works as {\tt apply \nelist{{\term} with {\bindinglist}}{,} in {\ident} as {\intropattern}} but using {\tt eapply}. \item {\tt simple apply {\term} in {\ident}} \tacindex{simple apply \dots\ in} \tacindex{simple eapply \dots\ in} This behaves like {\tt apply {\term} in {\ident}} but it reasons modulo conversion only on subterms that contain no variables to instantiate. For instance, if {\tt id := fun x:nat => x} and {\tt H : forall y, id y = y -> True} and {\tt H0 :\ O = O} then {\tt simple apply H in H0} does not succeed because it would require the conversion of {\tt id ?1234} and {\tt O} where {\tt ?1234} is a variable to instantiate. Tactic {\tt simple apply {\term} in {\ident}} does not either traverse tuples as {\tt apply {\term} in {\ident}} does. \item {\tt \zeroone{simple} apply \nelist{{\term} \zeroone{with {\bindinglist}}}{,} in {\ident} \zeroone{as {\intropattern}}}\\ {\tt \zeroone{simple} eapply \nelist{{\term} \zeroone{with {\bindinglist}}}{,} in {\ident} \zeroone{as {\intropattern}}} This summarizes the different syntactic variants of {\tt apply {\term} in {\ident}} and {\tt eapply {\term} in {\ident}}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt constructor \num} \label{constructor} \tacindex{constructor} This tactic applies to a goal such that its conclusion is an inductive type (say {\tt I}). The argument {\num} must be less or equal to the numbers of constructor(s) of {\tt I}. Let {\tt ci} be the {\tt i}-th constructor of {\tt I}, then {\tt constructor i} is equivalent to {\tt intros; apply ci}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not an inductive product} \item \errindex{Not enough constructors} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{constructor} This tries \texttt{constructor 1} then \texttt{constructor 2}, \dots\ , then \texttt{constructor} \textit{n} where \textit{n} is the number of constructors of the head of the goal. \item {\tt constructor \num~with} {\bindinglist} Let {\tt ci} be the {\tt i}-th constructor of {\tt I}, then {\tt constructor i with \bindinglist} is equivalent to {\tt intros; apply ci with \bindinglist}. \Warning the terms in the \bindinglist\ are checked in the context where {\tt constructor} is executed and not in the context where {\tt apply} is executed (the introductions are not taken into account). % To document? % \item {\tt constructor {\tactic}} \item {\tt split}\tacindex{split} This applies only if {\tt I} has a single constructor. It is then equivalent to {\tt constructor 1}. It is typically used in the case of a conjunction $A\land B$. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not an inductive goal with 1 constructor} \item {\tt exists {\bindinglist}}\tacindex{exists} This applies only if {\tt I} has a single constructor. It is then equivalent to {\tt intros; constructor 1 with \bindinglist}. It is typically used in the case of an existential quantification $\exists x, P(x)$. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not an inductive goal with 1 constructor} \item {\tt exists \nelist{\bindinglist}{,}} This iteratively applies {\tt exists {\bindinglist}}. \item {\tt left}\tacindex{left}\\ {\tt right}\tacindex{right} These tactics apply only if {\tt I} has two constructors, for instance in the case of a disjunction $A\lor B$. Then, they are respectively equivalent to {\tt constructor 1} and {\tt constructor 2}. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not an inductive goal with 2 constructors} \item {\tt left with \bindinglist}\\ {\tt right with \bindinglist}\\ {\tt split with \bindinglist} As soon as the inductive type has the right number of constructors, these expressions are equivalent to calling {\tt constructor $i$ with \bindinglist} for the appropriate $i$. \item \texttt{econstructor}\tacindex{econstructor}\\ \texttt{eexists}\tacindex{eexists}\\ \texttt{esplit}\tacindex{esplit}\\ \texttt{eleft}\tacindex{eleft}\\ \texttt{eright}\tacindex{eright} These tactics and their variants behave like \texttt{constructor}, \texttt{exists}, \texttt{split}, \texttt{left}, \texttt{right} and their variants but they introduce existential variables instead of failing when the instantiation of a variable cannot be found (cf \texttt{eapply} and Section~\ref{eapply-example}). \end{Variants} \section{Managing the local context} \subsection{\tt intro} \tacindex{intro} \label{intro} This tactic applies to a goal that is either a product or starts with a let binder. If the goal is a product, the tactic implements the ``Lam''\index{Typing rules!Lam} rule given in Section~\ref{Typed-terms}\footnote{Actually, only the second subgoal will be generated since the other one can be automatically checked.}. If the goal starts with a let binder, then the tactic implements a mix of the ``Let''\index{Typing rules!Let} and ``Conv''\index{Typing rules!Conv}. If the current goal is a dependent product $\forall x:T,~U$ (resp {\tt let $x$:=$t$ in $U$}) then {\tt intro} puts {\tt $x$:$T$} (resp {\tt $x$:=$t$}) in the local context. % Obsolete (quantified names already avoid hypotheses names): % Otherwise, it puts % {\tt x}{\it n}{\tt :T} where {\it n} is such that {\tt x}{\it n} is a %fresh name. The new subgoal is $U$. % If the {\tt x} has been renamed {\tt x}{\it n} then it is replaced % by {\tt x}{\it n} in {\tt U}. If the goal is a non-dependent product $T \to U$, then it puts in the local context either {\tt H}{\it n}{\tt :$T$} (if $T$ is of type {\tt Set} or {\tt Prop}) or {\tt X}{\it n}{\tt :$T$} (if the type of $T$ is {\tt Type}). The optional index {\it n} is such that {\tt H}{\it n} or {\tt X}{\it n} is a fresh identifier. In both cases, the new subgoal is $U$. If the goal is neither a product nor starting with a let definition, the tactic {\tt intro} applies the tactic {\tt hnf} until the tactic {\tt intro} can be applied or the goal is not head-reducible. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No product even after head-reduction} \item \errindexbis{{\ident} is already used}{is already used} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt intros}\tacindex{intros} This repeats {\tt intro} until it meets the head-constant. It never reduces head-constants and it never fails. \item {\tt intro {\ident}} This applies {\tt intro} but forces {\ident} to be the name of the introduced hypothesis. \ErrMsg \errindex{name {\ident} is already used} \Rem If a name used by {\tt intro} hides the base name of a global constant then the latter can still be referred to by a qualified name (see \ref{LongNames}). \item {\tt intros \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} This is equivalent to the composed tactic {\tt intro \ident$_1$; \dots\ ; intro \ident$_n$}. More generally, the \texttt{intros} tactic takes a pattern as argument in order to introduce names for components of an inductive definition or to clear introduced hypotheses. This is explained in~\ref{intros-pattern}. \item {\tt intros until {\ident}} \tacindex{intros until} This repeats {\tt intro} until it meets a premise of the goal having form {\tt (} {\ident}~{\tt :}~{\term} {\tt )} and discharges the variable named {\ident} of the current goal. \ErrMsg \errindex{No such hypothesis in current goal} \item {\tt intros until {\num}} \tacindex{intros until} This repeats {\tt intro} until the {\num}-th non-dependent product. For instance, on the subgoal % \verb+forall x y:nat, x=y -> y=x+ the tactic \texttt{intros until 1} is equivalent to \texttt{intros x y H}, as \verb+x=y -> y=x+ is the first non-dependent product. And on the subgoal % \verb+forall x y z:nat, x=y -> y=x+ the tactic \texttt{intros until 1} is equivalent to \texttt{intros x y z} as the product on \texttt{z} can be rewritten as a non-dependent product: % \verb+forall x y:nat, nat -> x=y -> y=x+ \ErrMsg \errindex{No such hypothesis in current goal} This happens when {\num} is 0 or is greater than the number of non-dependent products of the goal. \item {\tt intro after \ident} \tacindex{intro after}\\ {\tt intro before \ident} \tacindex{intro before}\\ {\tt intro at top} \tacindex{intro at top}\\ {\tt intro at bottom} \tacindex{intro at bottom} These tactics apply {\tt intro} and move the freshly introduced hypothesis respectively after the hypothesis \ident{}, before the hypothesis \ident{}, at the top of the local context, or at the bottom of the local context. All hypotheses on which the new hypothesis depends are moved too so as to respect the order of dependencies between hypotheses. Note that {\tt intro at bottom} is a synonym for {\tt intro} with no argument. \ErrMsg \errindex{No such hypothesis} : {\ident} \item {\tt intro \ident$_1$ after \ident$_2$}\\ {\tt intro \ident$_1$ before \ident$_2$}\\ {\tt intro \ident$_1$ at top}\\ {\tt intro \ident$_1$ at bottom} These tactics behave as previously but naming the introduced hypothesis \ident$_1$. It is equivalent to {\tt intro \ident$_1$} followed by the appropriate call to {\tt move}~(see Section~\ref{move}). \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt intros {\intropatternlist}} \label{intros-pattern} \tacindex{intros \intropattern} \index{Introduction patterns} \index{Naming introduction patterns} \index{Disjunctive/conjunctive introduction patterns} \index{Disjunctive/conjunctive introduction patterns} \index{Equality introduction patterns} This extension of the tactic {\tt intros} allows to apply tactics on the fly on the variables or hypotheses which have been introduced. An {\em introduction pattern list} {\intropatternlist} is a list of introduction patterns possibly containing the filling introduction patterns {\tt *} and {\tt **}. An {\em introduction pattern} is either: \begin{itemize} \item a {\em naming introduction pattern}, i.e. either one of: \begin{itemize} \item the pattern \texttt{?} \item the pattern \texttt{?\ident} \item an identifier \end{itemize} \item an {\em action introduction pattern} which itself classifies into: \begin{itemize} \item a {\em disjunctive/conjunctive introduction pattern}, i.e. either one of: \begin{itemize} \item a disjunction of lists of patterns: {\tt [$\intropatternlist_1$ | \dots\ | $\intropatternlist_n$]} \item a conjunction of patterns: {\tt ($p_1$ , \dots\ , $p_n$)} \item a list of patterns {\tt ($p_1$ \&\ \dots\ \&\ $p_n$)} for sequence of right-associative binary constructs \end{itemize} \item an {\em equality introduction pattern}, i.e. either one of: \begin{itemize} \item a pattern for decomposing an equality: {\tt [= $p_1$ \dots\ $p_n$]} \item the rewriting orientations: {\tt ->} or {\tt <-} \end{itemize} \item the on-the-fly application of lemmas: $p${\tt \%{\term$_1$}} \ldots {\tt \%{\term$_n$}} where $p$ itself is not a pattern for on-the-fly application of lemmas (note: syntax is in experimental stage) \end{itemize} \item the wildcard: {\tt \_} \end{itemize} Assuming a goal of type $Q \to P$ (non-dependent product), or of type $\forall x:T,~P$ (dependent product), the behavior of {\tt intros $p$} is defined inductively over the structure of the introduction pattern~$p$: \begin{itemize} \item introduction on \texttt{?} performs the introduction, and lets {\Coq} choose a fresh name for the variable; \item introduction on \texttt{?\ident} performs the introduction, and lets {\Coq} choose a fresh name for the variable based on {\ident}; \item introduction on \texttt{\ident} behaves as described in Section~\ref{intro}; \item introduction over a disjunction of list of patterns {\tt [$\intropatternlist_{1}$ | \dots\ | $\intropatternlist_n$]} expects the product to be over an inductive type whose number of constructors is $n$ (or more generally over a type of conclusion an inductive type built from $n$ constructors, e.g. {\tt C -> A\textbackslash/B} with $n=2$ since {\tt A\textbackslash/B} has 2 constructors): it destructs the introduced hypothesis as {\tt destruct} (see Section~\ref{destruct}) would and applies on each generated subgoal the corresponding tactic; \texttt{intros}~$\intropatternlist_i$. The introduction patterns in $\intropatternlist_i$ are expected to consume no more than the number of arguments of the $i^{\mbox{\scriptsize th}}$ constructor. If it consumes less, then {\Coq} completes the pattern so that all the arguments of the constructors of the inductive type are introduced (for instance, the list of patterns {\tt [$\;$|$\;$] H} applied on goal {\tt forall x:nat, x=0 -> 0=x} behaves the same as the list of patterns {\tt [$\,$|$\,$?$\,$] H}); \item introduction over a conjunction of patterns {\tt ($p_1$, \ldots, $p_n$)} expects the goal to be a product over an inductive type $I$ with a single constructor that itself has at least $n$ arguments: it performs a case analysis over the hypothesis, as {\tt destruct} would, and applies the patterns $p_1$~\ldots~$p_n$ to the arguments of the constructor of $I$ (observe that {\tt ($p_1$, {\ldots}, $p_n$)} is an alternative notation for {\tt [$p_1$ {\ldots} $p_n$]}); \item introduction via {\tt ($p_1$ \& \dots\ \& $p_n$)} is a shortcut for introduction via {\tt ($p_1$,(\ldots,(\dots,$p_n$)\ldots))}; it expects the hypothesis to be a sequence of right-associative binary inductive constructors such as {\tt conj} or {\tt ex\_intro}; for instance, an hypothesis with type {\tt A\verb|/\|(exists x, B\verb|/\|C\verb|/\|D)} can be introduced via pattern {\tt (a \& x \& b \& c \& d)}; \item if the product is over an equality type, then a pattern of the form {\tt [= $p_{1}$ \dots\ $p_n$]} applies either {\tt injection} (see Section~\ref{injection}) or {\tt discriminate} (see Section~\ref{discriminate}) instead of {\tt destruct}; if {\tt injection} is applicable, the patterns $p_1$, \ldots, $p_n$ are used on the hypotheses generated by {\tt injection}; if the number of patterns is smaller than the number of hypotheses generated, the pattern \texttt{?} is used to complete the list; %TODO! %if {\tt discriminate} is applicable, the list of patterns $p_{1}$ %\dots\ $p_n$ is supposed to be empty; \item introduction over {\tt ->} (respectively {\tt <-}) expects the hypothesis to be an equality and the right-hand-side (respectively the left-hand-side) is replaced by the left-hand-side (respectively the right-hand-side) in the conclusion of the goal; the hypothesis itself is erased; if the term to substitute is a variable, it is substituted also in the context of goal and the variable is removed too; \item introduction over a pattern $p${\tt \%{\term$_1$}} \ldots {\tt \%{\term$_n$}} first applies {\term$_1$},\ldots, {\term$_n$} on the hypothesis to be introduced (as in {\tt apply }{\term}$_1$, \ldots, {\term}$_n$ {\tt in}) prior to the application of the introduction pattern $p$; \item introduction on the wildcard depends on whether the product is dependent or not: in the non-dependent case, it erases the corresponding hypothesis (i.e. it behaves as an {\tt intro} followed by a {\tt clear}, cf Section~\ref{clear}) while in the dependent case, it succeeds and erases the variable only if the wildcard is part of a more complex list of introduction patterns that also erases the hypotheses depending on this variable; \item introduction over {\tt *} introduces all forthcoming quantified variables appearing in a row; introduction over {\tt **} introduces all forthcoming quantified variables or hypotheses until the goal is not any more a quantification or an implication. \end{itemize} \Example \begin{coq_example} Goal forall A B C:Prop, A \/ B /\ C -> (A -> C) -> C. intros * [a | (_,c)] f. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \Rem {\tt intros $p_1~\ldots~p_n$} is not equivalent to \texttt{intros $p_1$;\ldots; intros $p_n$} for the following reason: If one of the $p_i$ is a wildcard pattern, he might succeed in the first case because the further hypotheses it depends in are eventually erased too while it might fail in the second case because of dependencies in hypotheses which are not yet introduced (and a fortiori not yet erased). \Rem In {\tt intros $\intropatternlist$}, if the last introduction pattern is a disjunctive or conjunctive pattern {\tt [$\intropatternlist_1$ | \dots\ | $\intropatternlist_n$]}, the completion of $\intropatternlist_i$ so that all the arguments of the $i^{\mbox{\scriptsize th}}$ constructors of the corresponding inductive type are introduced can be controlled with the following option: \optindex{Bracketing Last Introduction Pattern} \begin{quote} {\tt Set Bracketing Last Introduction Pattern} \end{quote} Force completion, if needed, when the last introduction pattern is a disjunctive or conjunctive pattern (this is the default). \begin{quote} {\tt Unset Bracketing Last Introduction Pattern} \end{quote} Deactivate completion when the last introduction pattern is a disjunctive or conjunctive pattern. \subsection{\tt clear \ident} \tacindex{clear} \label{clear} This tactic erases the hypothesis named {\ident} in the local context of the current goal. As a consequence, {\ident} is no more displayed and no more usable in the proof development. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} \item \errindexbis{{\ident} is used in the conclusion}{is used in the conclusion} \item \errindexbis{{\ident} is used in the hypothesis {\ident'}}{is used in the hypothesis} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt clear {\ident$_1$} \dots\ {\ident$_n$}} This is equivalent to {\tt clear {\ident$_1$}. {\ldots} clear {\ident$_n$}.} \item {\tt clearbody {\ident}}\tacindex{clearbody} This tactic expects {\ident} to be a local definition then clears its body. Otherwise said, this tactic turns a definition into an assumption. \ErrMsg \errindexbis{{\ident} is not a local definition}{is not a local definition} \item \texttt{clear - {\ident$_1$} \dots\ {\ident$_n$}} This tactic clears all the hypotheses except the ones depending in the hypotheses named {\ident$_1$} {\ldots} {\ident$_n$} and in the goal. \item \texttt{clear} This tactic clears all the hypotheses except the ones the goal depends on. \item {\tt clear dependent \ident \tacindex{clear dependent}} This clears the hypothesis \ident\ and all the hypotheses that depend on it. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt revert \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} \tacindex{revert} \label{revert} This applies to any goal with variables \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$. It moves the hypotheses (possibly defined) to the goal, if this respects dependencies. This tactic is the inverse of {\tt intro}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} \item \errindexbis{{\ident} is used in the hypothesis {\ident'}}{is used in the hypothesis} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt revert dependent \ident \tacindex{revert dependent}} This moves to the goal the hypothesis {\ident} and all the hypotheses that depend on it. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt move {\ident$_1$} after {\ident$_2$}} \tacindex{move} \label{move} This moves the hypothesis named {\ident$_1$} in the local context after the hypothesis named {\ident$_2$}. The proof term is not changed. If {\ident$_1$} comes before {\ident$_2$} in the order of dependencies, then all the hypotheses between {\ident$_1$} and {\ident$_2$} that (possibly indirectly) depend on {\ident$_1$} are moved too. If {\ident$_1$} comes after {\ident$_2$} in the order of dependencies, then all the hypotheses between {\ident$_1$} and {\ident$_2$} that (possibly indirectly) occur in {\ident$_1$} are moved too. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt move {\ident$_1$} before {\ident$_2$}} This moves {\ident$_1$} towards and just before the hypothesis named {\ident$_2$}. \item {\tt move {\ident} at top} This moves {\ident} at the top of the local context (at the beginning of the context). \item {\tt move {\ident} at bottom} This moves {\ident} at the bottom of the local context (at the end of the context). \end{Variants} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} \item \errindex{Cannot move {\ident$_1$} after {\ident$_2$}: it occurs in {\ident$_2$}} \item \errindex{Cannot move {\ident$_1$} after {\ident$_2$}: it depends on {\ident$_2$}} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt rename {\ident$_1$} into {\ident$_2$}} \tacindex{rename} This renames hypothesis {\ident$_1$} into {\ident$_2$} in the current context. The name of the hypothesis in the proof-term, however, is left unchanged. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt rename {\ident$_1$} into {\ident$_2$}, \ldots, {\ident$_{2k-1}$} into {\ident$_{2k}$}} This renames the variables {\ident$_1$} \ldots {\ident$_2k-1$} into respectively {\ident$_2$} \ldots {\ident$_2k$} in parallel. In particular, the target identifiers may contain identifiers that exist in the source context, as long as the latter are also renamed by the same tactic. \end{Variants} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} \item \errindexbis{{\ident$_2$} is already used}{is already used} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt set ( {\ident} := {\term} )} \label{tactic:set} \tacindex{set} This replaces {\term} by {\ident} in the conclusion of the current goal and adds the new definition {\tt {\ident} := \term} to the local context. If {\term} has holes (i.e. subexpressions of the form ``\_''), the tactic first checks that all subterms matching the pattern are compatible before doing the replacement using the leftmost subterm matching the pattern. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{The variable {\ident} is already defined} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt set ( {\ident} := {\term} ) in {\occgoalset}} This notation allows specifying which occurrences of {\term} have to be substituted in the context. The {\tt in {\occgoalset}} clause is an occurrence clause whose syntax and behavior are described in Section~\ref{Occurrences_clauses}. \item {\tt set ( {\ident} \nelistnosep{\binder} := {\term} )} This is equivalent to {\tt set ( {\ident} := fun \nelistnosep{\binder} => {\term} )}. \item {\tt set \term} This behaves as {\tt set (} {\ident} := {\term} {\tt )} but {\ident} is generated by {\Coq}. This variant also supports an occurrence clause. \item {\tt set ( {\ident$_0$} \nelistnosep{\binder} := {\term} ) in {\occgoalset}}\\ {\tt set {\term} in {\occgoalset}} These are the general forms that combine the previous possibilities. \item {\tt remember {\term} as {\ident}}\tacindex{remember} This behaves as {\tt set ( {\ident} := {\term} ) in *} and using a logical (Leibniz's) equality instead of a local definition. \item {\tt remember {\term} as {\ident} eqn:{\ident}} This behaves as {\tt remember {\term} as {\ident}}, except that the name of the generated equality is also given. \item {\tt remember {\term} as {\ident} in {\occgoalset}} This is a more general form of {\tt remember} that remembers the occurrences of {\term} specified by an occurrences set. \item {\tt pose ( {\ident} := {\term} )}\tacindex{pose} This adds the local definition {\ident} := {\term} to the current context without performing any replacement in the goal or in the hypotheses. It is equivalent to {\tt set ( {\ident} {\tt :=} {\term} {\tt ) in |-}}. \item {\tt pose ( {\ident} \nelistnosep{\binder} := {\term} )} This is equivalent to {\tt pose (} {\ident} {\tt :=} {\tt fun} \nelistnosep{\binder} {\tt =>} {\term} {\tt )}. \item{\tt pose {\term}} This behaves as {\tt pose ( {\ident} := {\term} )} but {\ident} is generated by {\Coq}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt decompose [ {\qualid$_1$} \dots\ {\qualid$_n$} ] \term} \label{decompose} \tacindex{decompose} This tactic recursively decomposes a complex proposition in order to obtain atomic ones. \Example \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Goal forall A B C:Prop, A /\ B /\ C \/ B /\ C \/ C /\ A -> C. intros A B C H; decompose [and or] H; assumption. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} Qed. \end{coq_example*} {\tt decompose} does not work on right-hand sides of implications or products. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt decompose sum \term}\tacindex{decompose sum} This decomposes sum types (like \texttt{or}). \item {\tt decompose record \term}\tacindex{decompose record} This decomposes record types (inductive types with one constructor, like \texttt{and} and \texttt{exists} and those defined with the \texttt{Record} macro, see Section~\ref{Record}). \end{Variants} \section{Controlling the proof flow} \subsection{\tt assert ( {\ident} :\ {\form} )} \tacindex{assert} This tactic applies to any goal. {\tt assert (H : U)} adds a new hypothesis of name \texttt{H} asserting \texttt{U} to the current goal and opens a new subgoal \texttt{U}\footnote{This corresponds to the cut rule of sequent calculus.}. The subgoal {\texttt U} comes first in the list of subgoals remaining to prove. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not a proposition or a type} Arises when the argument {\form} is neither of type {\tt Prop}, {\tt Set} nor {\tt Type}. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt assert {\form}} This behaves as {\tt assert ( {\ident} :\ {\form} )} but {\ident} is generated by {\Coq}. \item \texttt{assert {\form} by {\tac}}\tacindex{assert by} This tactic behaves like \texttt{assert} but applies {\tac} to solve the subgoals generated by \texttt{assert}. \ErrMsg \errindex{Proof is not complete} \item \texttt{assert {\form} as {\intropattern}\tacindex{assert as}} If {\intropattern} is a naming introduction pattern (see Section~\ref{intros-pattern}), the hypothesis is named after this introduction pattern (in particular, if {\intropattern} is {\ident}, the tactic behaves like \texttt{assert ({\ident} :\ {\form})}). If {\intropattern} is an action introduction pattern, the tactic behaves like \texttt{assert {\form}} followed by the action done by this introduction pattern. \item \texttt{assert {\form} as {\intropattern} by {\tac}} This combines the two previous variants of {\tt assert}. \item{\tt assert ( {\ident} := {\term} )} This behaves as {\tt assert ({\ident} :\ {\type});[exact {\term}|idtac]} where {\type} is the type of {\term}. This is deprecated in favor of {\tt pose proof}. \ErrMsg \errindex{Variable {\ident} is already declared} \item \texttt{pose proof {\term} as {\intropattern}\tacindex{pose proof}} This tactic behaves like \texttt{assert T as {\intropattern} by exact {\term}} where \texttt{T} is the type of {\term}. In particular, \texttt{pose proof {\term} as {\ident}} behaves as \texttt{assert ({\ident} := {\term})} and \texttt{pose proof {\term} as {\intropattern}\tacindex{pose proof}} is the same as applying the {\intropattern} to {\term}. \item \texttt{enough ({\ident} :\ {\form})}\tacindex{enough} This adds a new hypothesis of name {\ident} asserting {\form} to the goal the tactic \texttt{enough} is applied to. A new subgoal stating \texttt{\form} is inserted after the initial goal rather than before it as \texttt{assert} would do. \item \texttt{enough {\form}}\tacindex{enough} This behaves like \texttt{enough ({\ident} :\ {\form})} with the name {\ident} of the hypothesis generated by {\Coq}. \item \texttt{enough {\form} as {\intropattern}\tacindex{enough as}} This behaves like \texttt{enough} {\form} using {\intropattern} to name or destruct the new hypothesis. \item \texttt{enough ({\ident} :\ {\form}) by {\tac}}\tacindex{enough by}\\ \texttt{enough {\form} by {\tac}}\tacindex{enough by}\\ \texttt{enough {\form} as {\intropattern} by {\tac}} This behaves as above but with {\tac} expected to solve the initial goal after the extra assumption {\form} is added and possibly destructed. If the \texttt{as} {\intropattern} clause generates more than one subgoal, {\tac} is applied to all of them. \item {\tt cut {\form}}\tacindex{cut} This tactic applies to any goal. It implements the non-dependent case of the ``App''\index{Typing rules!App} rule given in Section~\ref{Typed-terms}. (This is Modus Ponens inference rule.) {\tt cut U} transforms the current goal \texttt{T} into the two following subgoals: {\tt U -> T} and \texttt{U}. The subgoal {\tt U -> T} comes first in the list of remaining subgoal to prove. \item {\tt specialize ({\ident} \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$)\tacindex{specialize}} \\ {\tt specialize {\ident} with \bindinglist} The tactic {\tt specialize} works on local hypothesis \ident. The premises of this hypothesis (either universal quantifications or non-dependent implications) are instantiated by concrete terms coming either from arguments \term$_1$ $\ldots$ \term$_n$ or from a bindings list (see Section~\ref{Binding-list} for more about bindings lists). In the second form, all instantiation elements must be given, whereas in the first form the application to \term$_1$ {\ldots} \term$_n$ can be partial. The first form is equivalent to {\tt assert (\ident' := {\ident} {\term$_1$} \dots\ \term$_n$); clear \ident; rename \ident' into \ident}. The name {\ident} can also refer to a global lemma or hypothesis. In this case, for compatibility reasons, the behavior of {\tt specialize} is close to that of {\tt generalize}: the instantiated statement becomes an additional premise of the goal. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindexbis{{\ident} is used in hypothesis \ident'}{is used in hypothesis} \item \errindexbis{{\ident} is used in conclusion}{is used in conclusion} \end{ErrMsgs} %% Moreover, the old syntax allows the use of a number after {\tt specialize} %% for controlling the number of premises to instantiate. Giving this %% number should not be mandatory anymore (automatic detection of how %% many premises can be eaten without leaving meta-variables). Hence %% no documentation for this integer optional argument of specialize \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt generalize \term} \tacindex{generalize} \label{generalize} This tactic applies to any goal. It generalizes the conclusion with respect to some term. \Example \begin{coq_eval} Goal forall x y:nat, (0 <= x + y + y). intros. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. generalize (x + y + y). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} If the goal is $G$ and $t$ is a subterm of type $T$ in the goal, then {\tt generalize} \textit{t} replaces the goal by {\tt forall (x:$T$), $G'$} where $G'$ is obtained from $G$ by replacing all occurrences of $t$ by {\tt x}. The name of the variable (here {\tt n}) is chosen based on $T$. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt generalize {\term$_1$ , \dots\ , \term$_n$}} This is equivalent to {\tt generalize \term$_n$; \dots\ ; generalize \term$_1$}. Note that the sequence of \term$_i$'s are processed from $n$ to $1$. \item {\tt generalize {\term} at {\num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$}} This is equivalent to {\tt generalize \term} but it generalizes only over the specified occurrences of {\term} (counting from left to right on the expression printed using option {\tt Set Printing All}). \item {\tt generalize {\term} as {\ident}} This is equivalent to {\tt generalize \term} but it uses {\ident} to name the generalized hypothesis. \item {\tt generalize {\term$_1$} at {\num$_{11}$ \dots\ \num$_{1i_1}$} as {\ident$_1$} , {\ldots} , {\term$_n$} at {\num$_{n1}$ \mbox{\dots} \num$_{ni_n}$} as {\ident$_2$}} This is the most general form of {\tt generalize} that combines the previous behaviors. \item {\tt generalize dependent \term} \tacindex{generalize dependent} This generalizes {\term} but also {\em all} hypotheses that depend on {\term}. It clears the generalized hypotheses. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt evar ( {\ident} :\ {\term} )} \tacindex{evar} \label{evar} The {\tt evar} tactic creates a new local definition named \ident\ with type \term\ in the context. The body of this binding is a fresh existential variable. \subsection{\tt instantiate ( {\num} := {\term} )} \tacindex{instantiate} \label{instantiate} The {\tt instantiate} tactic refines (see Section~\ref{refine}) an existential variable with the term \term. The \num\ argument is the position of the existential variable from right to left in the conclusion. This cannot be the number of the existential variable since this number is different in every session. When you are referring to hypotheses which you did not name explicitly, be aware that Coq may make a different decision on how to name the variable in the current goal and in the context of the existential variable. This can lead to surprising behaviors. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt instantiate ( {\num} := {\term} ) in \ident} \item {\tt instantiate ( {\num} := {\term} ) in ( Value of {\ident} )} \item {\tt instantiate ( {\num} := {\term} ) in ( Type of {\ident} )} These allow to refer respectively to existential variables occurring in a hypothesis or in the body or the type of a local definition. \item {\tt instantiate} Without argument, the {\tt instantiate} tactic tries to solve as many existential variables as possible, using information gathered from other tactics in the same tactical. This is automatically done after each complete tactic (i.e. after a dot in proof mode), but not, for example, between each tactic when they are sequenced by semicolons. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt admit} \tacindex{admit} \tacindex{give\_up} \label{admit} The {\tt admit} tactic allows temporarily skipping a subgoal so as to progress further in the rest of the proof. A proof containing admitted goals cannot be closed with {\tt Qed} but only with {\tt Admitted}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt give\_up} Synonym of {\tt admit}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt absurd \term} \tacindex{absurd} \label{absurd} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\term} is any proposition {\tt P} of type {\tt Prop}. This tactic applies {\tt False} elimination, that is it deduces the current goal from {\tt False}, and generates as subgoals {\tt $\sim$P} and {\tt P}. It is very useful in proofs by cases, where some cases are impossible. In most cases, \texttt{P} or $\sim$\texttt{P} is one of the hypotheses of the local context. \subsection{\tt contradiction} \label{contradiction} \tacindex{contradiction} This tactic applies to any goal. The {\tt contradiction} tactic attempts to find in the current context (after all {\tt intros}) one hypothesis that is equivalent to {\tt False}. It permits to prune irrelevant cases. This tactic is a macro for the tactics sequence {\tt intros; elimtype False; assumption}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such assumption} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt contradiction \ident} The proof of {\tt False} is searched in the hypothesis named \ident. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt contradict \ident} \label{contradict} \tacindex{contradict} This tactic allows manipulating negated hypothesis and goals. The name \ident\ should correspond to a hypothesis. With {\tt contradict H}, the current goal and context is transformed in the following way: \begin{itemize} \item {\tt H:$\neg$A $\vd$ B} \ becomes \ {\tt $\vd$ A} \item {\tt H:$\neg$A $\vd$ $\neg$B} \ becomes \ {\tt H: B $\vd$ A } \item {\tt H: A $\vd$ B} \ becomes \ {\tt $\vd$ $\neg$A} \item {\tt H: A $\vd$ $\neg$B} \ becomes \ {\tt H: B $\vd$ $\neg$A} \end{itemize} \subsection{\tt exfalso} \label{exfalso} \tacindex{exfalso} This tactic implements the ``ex falso quodlibet'' logical principle: an elimination of {\tt False} is performed on the current goal, and the user is then required to prove that {\tt False} is indeed provable in the current context. This tactic is a macro for {\tt elimtype False}. \section{Case analysis and induction} The tactics presented in this section implement induction or case analysis on inductive or co-inductive objects (see Section~\ref{Cic-inductive-definitions}). \subsection{\tt destruct \term} \tacindex{destruct} \label{destruct} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\term} must be of inductive or co-inductive type and the tactic generates subgoals, one for each possible form of {\term}, i.e. one for each constructor of the inductive or co-inductive type. Unlike {\tt induction}, no induction hypothesis is generated by {\tt destruct}. There are special cases: \begin{itemize} \item If {\term} is an identifier {\ident} denoting a quantified variable of the conclusion of the goal, then {\tt destruct {\ident}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; destruct {\ident}}. If {\ident} is not anymore dependent in the goal after application of {\tt destruct}, it is erased (to avoid erasure, use parentheses, as in {\tt destruct ({\ident})}). \item If {\term} is a {\num}, then {\tt destruct {\num}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}} followed by {\tt destruct} applied to the last introduced hypothesis. Remark: For destruction of a numeral, use syntax {\tt destruct ({\num})} (not very interesting anyway). \item In case {\term} is an hypothesis {\ident} of the context, and {\ident} is not anymore dependent in the goal after application of {\tt destruct}, it is erased (to avoid erasure, use parentheses, as in {\tt destruct ({\ident})}). \item The argument {\term} can also be a pattern of which holes are denoted by ``\_''. In this case, the tactic checks that all subterms matching the pattern in the conclusion and the hypotheses are compatible and performs case analysis using this subterm. \end{itemize} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt destruct \term$_1$, \ldots, \term$_n$} This is a shortcut for {\tt destruct \term$_1$; \ldots; destruct \term$_n$}. \item{\tt destruct {\term} as {\disjconjintropattern}} This behaves as {\tt destruct {\term}} but uses the names in {\intropattern} to name the variables introduced in the context. The {\intropattern} must have the form {\tt [} $p_{11}$ \ldots $p_{1n_1}$ {\tt |} {\ldots} {\tt |} $p_{m1}$ \ldots $p_{mn_m}$ {\tt ]} with $m$ being the number of constructors of the type of {\term}. Each variable introduced by {\tt destruct} in the context of the $i^{th}$ goal gets its name from the list $p_{i1}$ \ldots $p_{in_i}$ in order. If there are not enough names, {\tt destruct} invents names for the remaining variables to introduce. More generally, the $p_{ij}$ can be any introduction pattern (see Section~\ref{intros-pattern}). This provides a concise notation for chaining destruction of an hypothesis. % It is recommended to use this variant of {\tt destruct} for % robust proof scripts. \item{\tt destruct {\term} eqn:{\namingintropattern}} This behaves as {\tt destruct {\term}} but adds an equation between {\term} and the value that {\term} takes in each of the possible cases. The name of the equation is specified by {\namingintropattern} (see Section~\ref{intros-pattern}), in particular {\tt ?} can be used to let Coq generate a fresh name. \item{\tt destruct {\term} with \bindinglist} This behaves like \texttt{destruct {\term}} providing explicit instances for the dependent premises of the type of {\term} (see syntax of bindings in Section~\ref{Binding-list}). \item{\tt edestruct {\term}\tacindex{edestruct}} This tactic behaves like \texttt{destruct {\term}} except that it does not fail if the instance of a dependent premises of the type of {\term} is not inferable. Instead, the unresolved instances are left as existential variables to be inferred later, in the same way as {\tt eapply} does (see Section~\ref{eapply-example}). \item{\tt destruct {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$}}\\ {\tt destruct {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist}} These are synonyms of {\tt induction {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$}} and {\tt induction {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist}}. \item \texttt{destruct {\term} in {\occgoalset}} This syntax is used for selecting which occurrences of {\term} the case analysis has to be done on. The {\tt in {\occgoalset}} clause is an occurrence clause whose syntax and behavior is described in Section~\ref{Occurrences_clauses}. \item{\tt destruct {\term$_1$} with {\bindinglist$_1$} as {\disjconjintropattern} eqn:{\namingintropattern} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist$_2$} in {\occgoalset}}\\ {\tt edestruct {\term$_1$} with {\bindinglist$_1$} as {\disjconjintropattern} eqn:{\namingintropattern} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist$_2$} in {\occgoalset}} These are the general forms of {\tt destruct} and {\tt edestruct}. They combine the effects of the {\tt with}, {\tt as}, {\tt eqn:}, {\tt using}, and {\tt in} clauses. \item{\tt case \term}\label{case}\tacindex{case} The tactic {\tt case} is a more basic tactic to perform case analysis without recursion. It behaves as {\tt elim \term} but using a case-analysis elimination principle and not a recursive one. \item {\tt case {\term} with {\bindinglist}} Analogous to {\tt elim {\term} with {\bindinglist}} above. \item{\tt ecase {\term}\tacindex{ecase}}\\ {\tt ecase {\term} with {\bindinglist}} In case the type of {\term} has dependent premises, or dependent premises whose values are not inferable from the {\tt with {\bindinglist}} clause, {\tt ecase} turns them into existential variables to be resolved later on. \item {\tt simple destruct \ident}\tacindex{simple destruct} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; case {\tt {\ident}}} when {\ident} is a quantified variable of the goal. \item {\tt simple destruct {\num}} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}; case {\tt {\ident}}} where {\ident} is the name given by {\tt intros until {\num}} to the {\num}-th non-dependent premise of the goal. \item{\tt case\_eq \term}\label{case_eq}\tacindex{case\_eq} The tactic {\tt case\_eq} is a variant of the {\tt case} tactic that allow to perform case analysis on a term without completely forgetting its original form. This is done by generating equalities between the original form of the term and the outcomes of the case analysis. % The effect of this tactic is similar to the effect of {\tt % destruct {\term} in |- *} with the exception that no new hypotheses % are introduced in the context. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt induction \term} \tacindex{induction} \label{Tac-induction} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\term} must be of inductive type and the tactic {\tt induction} generates subgoals, one for each possible form of {\term}, i.e. one for each constructor of the inductive type. If the argument is dependent in either the conclusion or some hypotheses of the goal, the argument is replaced by the appropriate constructor form in each of the resulting subgoals and induction hypotheses are added to the local context using names whose prefix is {\tt IH}. There are particular cases: \begin{itemize} \item If {\term} is an identifier {\ident} denoting a quantified variable of the conclusion of the goal, then {\tt induction {\ident}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; induction {\ident}}. If {\ident} is not anymore dependent in the goal after application of {\tt induction}, it is erased (to avoid erasure, use parentheses, as in {\tt induction ({\ident})}). \item If {\term} is a {\num}, then {\tt induction {\num}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}} followed by {\tt induction} applied to the last introduced hypothesis. Remark: For simple induction on a numeral, use syntax {\tt induction ({\num})} (not very interesting anyway). \item In case {\term} is an hypothesis {\ident} of the context, and {\ident} is not anymore dependent in the goal after application of {\tt induction}, it is erased (to avoid erasure, use parentheses, as in {\tt induction ({\ident})}). \item The argument {\term} can also be a pattern of which holes are denoted by ``\_''. In this case, the tactic checks that all subterms matching the pattern in the conclusion and the hypotheses are compatible and performs induction using this subterm. \end{itemize} \Example \begin{coq_example} Lemma induction_test : forall n:nat, n = n -> n <= n. intros n H. induction n. \end{coq_example} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not an inductive product} \item \errindex{Unable to find an instance for the variables {\ident} \ldots {\ident}} Use in this case the variant {\tt elim \dots\ with \dots} below. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt induction {\term} as {\disjconjintropattern}} This behaves as {\tt induction {\term}} but uses the names in {\disjconjintropattern} to name the variables introduced in the context. The {\disjconjintropattern} must typically be of the form {\tt [} $p_{11}$ {\ldots} $p_{1n_1}$ {\tt |} {\ldots} {\tt |} $p_{m1}$ {\ldots} $p_{mn_m}$ {\tt ]} with $m$ being the number of constructors of the type of {\term}. Each variable introduced by {\tt induction} in the context of the $i^{th}$ goal gets its name from the list $p_{i1}$ {\ldots} $p_{in_i}$ in order. If there are not enough names, {\tt induction} invents names for the remaining variables to introduce. More generally, the $p_{ij}$ can be any disjunctive/conjunctive introduction pattern (see Section~\ref{intros-pattern}). For instance, for an inductive type with one constructor, the pattern notation {\tt (}$p_{1}$ {\tt ,} {\ldots} {\tt ,} $p_{n}${\tt )} can be used instead of {\tt [} $p_{1}$ {\ldots} $p_{n}$ {\tt ]}. %% \item{\tt induction {\term} eqn:{\namingintropattern}} %% This behaves as {\tt induction {\term}} but adds an equation between %% {\term} and the value that {\term} takes in each of the induction %% case. The name of the equation is built according to %% {\namingintropattern} which can be an identifier, a ``?'', etc, as %% indicated in Section~\ref{intros-pattern}. %% \item{\tt induction {\term} as {\disjconjintropattern} eqn:{\namingintropattern}} %% This combines the two previous forms. \item{\tt induction {\term} with \bindinglist} This behaves like \texttt{induction {\term}} providing explicit instances for the premises of the type of {\term} (see the syntax of bindings in Section~\ref{Binding-list}). \item{\tt einduction {\term}\tacindex{einduction}} This tactic behaves like \texttt{induction {\term}} excepts that it does not fail if some dependent premise of the type of {\term} is not inferable. Instead, the unresolved premises are posed as existential variables to be inferred later, in the same way as {\tt eapply} does (see Section~\ref{eapply-example}). \item {\tt induction {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$}} This behaves as {\tt induction {\term$_1$}} but using {\term$_2$} as induction scheme. It does not expect the conclusion of the type of {\term$_1$} to be inductive. \item {\tt induction {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist}} This behaves as {\tt induction {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$}} but also providing instances for the premises of the type of {\term$_2$}. \item \texttt{induction {\term}$_1$, {\ldots}, {\term}$_n$ using {\qualid}} This syntax is used for the case {\qualid} denotes an induction principle with complex predicates as the induction principles generated by {\tt Function} or {\tt Functional Scheme} may be. \item \texttt{induction {\term} in {\occgoalset}} This syntax is used for selecting which occurrences of {\term} the induction has to be carried on. The {\tt in \occgoalset} clause is an occurrence clause whose syntax and behavior is described in Section~\ref{Occurrences_clauses}. If variables or hypotheses not mentioning {\term} in their type are listed in {\occgoalset}, those are generalized as well in the statement to prove. \Example \begin{coq_example} Lemma comm x y : x + y = y + x. induction y in x |- *. Show 2. \end{coq_example} \item {\tt induction {\term$_1$} with {\bindinglist$_1$} as {\disjconjintropattern} %% eqn:{\namingintropattern} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist$_2$} in {\occgoalset}}\\ {\tt einduction {\term$_1$} with {\bindinglist$_1$} as {\disjconjintropattern} %% eqn:{\namingintropattern} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist$_2$} in {\occgoalset}} These are the most general forms of {\tt induction} and {\tt einduction}. It combines the effects of the {\tt with}, {\tt as}, %%{\tt eqn:}, {\tt using}, and {\tt in} clauses. \item {\tt elim \term}\label{elim} This is a more basic induction tactic. Again, the type of the argument {\term} must be an inductive type. Then, according to the type of the goal, the tactic {\tt elim} chooses the appropriate destructor and applies it as the tactic {\tt apply} would do. For instance, if the proof context contains {\tt n:nat} and the current goal is {\tt T} of type {\tt Prop}, then {\tt elim n} is equivalent to {\tt apply nat\_ind with (n:=n)}. The tactic {\tt elim} does not modify the context of the goal, neither introduces the induction loading into the context of hypotheses. More generally, {\tt elim \term} also works when the type of {\term} is a statement with premises and whose conclusion is inductive. In that case the tactic performs induction on the conclusion of the type of {\term} and leaves the non-dependent premises of the type as subgoals. In the case of dependent products, the tactic tries to find an instance for which the elimination lemma applies and fails otherwise. \item {\tt elim {\term} with {\bindinglist}} Allows to give explicit instances to the premises of the type of {\term} (see Section~\ref{Binding-list}). \item{\tt eelim {\term}\tacindex{eelim}} In case the type of {\term} has dependent premises, this turns them into existential variables to be resolved later on. \item{\tt elim {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$}}\\ {\tt elim {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist}\tacindex{elim \dots\ using}} Allows the user to give explicitly an elimination predicate {\term$_2$} that is not the standard one for the underlying inductive type of {\term$_1$}. The {\bindinglist} clause allows instantiating premises of the type of {\term$_2$}. \item{\tt elim {\term$_1$} with {\bindinglist$_1$} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist$_2$}}\\ {\tt eelim {\term$_1$} with {\bindinglist$_1$} using {\term$_2$} with {\bindinglist$_2$}} These are the most general forms of {\tt elim} and {\tt eelim}. It combines the effects of the {\tt using} clause and of the two uses of the {\tt with} clause. \item {\tt elimtype \form}\tacindex{elimtype} The argument {\form} must be inductively defined. {\tt elimtype I} is equivalent to {\tt cut I. intro H{\rm\sl n}; elim H{\rm\sl n}; clear H{\rm\sl n}}. Therefore the hypothesis {\tt H{\rm\sl n}} will not appear in the context(s) of the subgoal(s). Conversely, if {\tt t} is a term of (inductive) type {\tt I} that does not occur in the goal, then {\tt elim t} is equivalent to {\tt elimtype I; 2: exact t.} \item {\tt simple induction \ident}\tacindex{simple induction} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; elim {\tt {\ident}}} when {\ident} is a quantified variable of the goal. \item {\tt simple induction {\num}} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}; elim {\tt {\ident}}} where {\ident} is the name given by {\tt intros until {\num}} to the {\num}-th non-dependent premise of the goal. %% \item {\tt simple induction {\term}}\tacindex{simple induction} %% If {\term} is an {\ident} corresponding to a quantified variable of %% the goal then the tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; elim %% {\tt {\ident}}}. If {\term} is a {\num} then the tactic behaves as %% {\tt intros until {\ident}; elim {\tt {\ident}}}. Otherwise, it is %% a synonym for {\tt elim {\term}}. %% \Rem For simple induction on a numeral, use syntax {\tt simple %% induction ({\num})}. \end{Variants} %\subsection[\tt FixPoint \dots]{\tt FixPoint \dots\tacindex{Fixpoint}} %Not yet documented. \subsection{\tt double induction \ident$_1$ \ident$_2$} \tacindex{double induction} This tactic is deprecated and should be replaced by {\tt induction \ident$_1$; induction \ident$_2$} (or {\tt induction \ident$_1$; destruct \ident$_2$} depending on the exact needs). %% This tactic applies to any goal. If the variables {\ident$_1$} and %% {\ident$_2$} of the goal have an inductive type, then this tactic %% performs double induction on these variables. For instance, if the %% current goal is \verb+forall n m:nat, P n m+ then, {\tt double induction n %% m} yields the four cases with their respective inductive hypotheses. %% In particular, for proving \verb+(P (S n) (S m))+, the generated induction %% hypotheses are \verb+(P (S n) m)+ and \verb+(m:nat)(P n m)+ (of the latter, %% \verb+(P n m)+ and \verb+(P n (S m))+ are derivable). %% \Rem When the induction hypothesis \verb+(P (S n) m)+ is not %% needed, {\tt induction \ident$_1$; destruct \ident$_2$} produces %% more concise subgoals. \begin{Variant} \item {\tt double induction \num$_1$ \num$_2$} This tactic is deprecated and should be replaced by {\tt induction \num$_1$; induction \num$_3$} where \num$_3$ is the result of \num$_2$-\num$_1$. %% This applies double induction on the \num$_1^{th}$ and \num$_2^{th}$ {\it %% non dependent} premises of the goal. More generally, any combination of an %% {\ident} and a {\num} is valid. \end{Variant} \subsection{\tt dependent induction \ident} \tacindex{dependent induction} \label{DepInduction} The \emph{experimental} tactic \texttt{dependent induction} performs induction-inversion on an instantiated inductive predicate. One needs to first require the {\tt Coq.Program.Equality} module to use this tactic. The tactic is based on the BasicElim tactic by Conor McBride \cite{DBLP:conf/types/McBride00} and the work of Cristina Cornes around inversion \cite{DBLP:conf/types/CornesT95}. From an instantiated inductive predicate and a goal, it generates an equivalent goal where the hypothesis has been generalized over its indexes which are then constrained by equalities to be the right instances. This permits to state lemmas without resorting to manually adding these equalities and still get enough information in the proofs. \Example \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Lemma le_minus : forall n:nat, n < 1 -> n = 0. intros n H ; induction H. \end{coq_example} Here we did not get any information on the indexes to help fulfill this proof. The problem is that, when we use the \texttt{induction} tactic, we lose information on the hypothesis instance, notably that the second argument is \texttt{1} here. Dependent induction solves this problem by adding the corresponding equality to the context. \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Require Import Coq.Program.Equality. Lemma le_minus : forall n:nat, n < 1 -> n = 0. intros n H ; dependent induction H. \end{coq_example} The subgoal is cleaned up as the tactic tries to automatically simplify the subgoals with respect to the generated equalities. In this enriched context, it becomes possible to solve this subgoal. \begin{coq_example} reflexivity. \end{coq_example} Now we are in a contradictory context and the proof can be solved. \begin{coq_example} inversion H. \end{coq_example} This technique works with any inductive predicate. In fact, the \texttt{dependent induction} tactic is just a wrapper around the \texttt{induction} tactic. One can make its own variant by just writing a new tactic based on the definition found in \texttt{Coq.Program.Equality}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt dependent induction {\ident} generalizing {\ident$_1$} \dots {\ident$_n$}}\tacindex{dependent induction \dots\ generalizing} This performs dependent induction on the hypothesis {\ident} but first generalizes the goal by the given variables so that they are universally quantified in the goal. This is generally what one wants to do with the variables that are inside some constructors in the induction hypothesis. The other ones need not be further generalized. \item {\tt dependent destruction {\ident}}\tacindex{dependent destruction} This performs the generalization of the instance {\ident} but uses {\tt destruct} instead of {\tt induction} on the generalized hypothesis. This gives results equivalent to {\tt inversion} or {\tt dependent inversion} if the hypothesis is dependent. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso \ref{dependent-induction-example} for a larger example of dependent induction and an explanation of the underlying technique. \subsection{\tt functional induction (\qualid\ \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$)} \tacindex{functional induction} \label{FunInduction} The tactic \texttt{functional induction} performs case analysis and induction following the definition of a function. It makes use of a principle generated by \texttt{Function} (see Section~\ref{Function}) or \texttt{Functional Scheme} (see Section~\ref{FunScheme}). \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Import Nat. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Functional Scheme minus_ind := Induction for minus Sort Prop. Check minus_ind. Lemma le_minus (n m:nat) : n - m <= n. functional induction (minus n m) using minus_ind; simpl; auto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} Qed. \end{coq_example*} \Rem \texttt{(\qualid\ \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$)} must be a correct full application of \qualid. In particular, the rules for implicit arguments are the same as usual. For example use \texttt{@\qualid} if you want to write implicit arguments explicitly. \Rem Parentheses over \qualid \dots \term$_n$ are mandatory. \Rem \texttt{functional induction (f x1 x2 x3)} is actually a wrapper for \texttt{induction x1, x2, x3, (f x1 x2 x3) using \qualid} followed by a cleaning phase, where {\qualid} is the induction principle registered for $f$ (by the \texttt{Function} (see Section~\ref{Function}) or \texttt{Functional Scheme} (see Section~\ref{FunScheme}) command) corresponding to the sort of the goal. Therefore \texttt{functional induction} may fail if the induction scheme {\qualid} is not defined. See also Section~\ref{Function} for the function terms accepted by \texttt{Function}. \Rem There is a difference between obtaining an induction scheme for a function by using \texttt{Function} (see Section~\ref{Function}) and by using \texttt{Functional Scheme} after a normal definition using \texttt{Fixpoint} or \texttt{Definition}. See \ref{Function} for details. \SeeAlso{\ref{Function},\ref{FunScheme},\ref{FunScheme-examples}, \ref{sec:functional-inversion}} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Cannot find induction information on \qualid} \item \errindex{Not the right number of induction arguments} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt functional induction (\qualid\ \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$) as {\disjconjintropattern} using \term$_{m+1}$ with \bindinglist} Similarly to \texttt{Induction} and \texttt{elim} (see Section~\ref{Tac-induction}), this allows giving explicitly the name of the introduced variables, the induction principle, and the values of dependent premises of the elimination scheme, including \emph{predicates} for mutual induction when {\qualid} is part of a mutually recursive definition. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt discriminate \term} \label{discriminate} \tacindex{discriminate} This tactic proves any goal from an assumption stating that two structurally different terms of an inductive set are equal. For example, from {\tt (S (S O))=(S O)} we can derive by absurdity any proposition. The argument {\term} is assumed to be a proof of a statement of conclusion {\tt{\term$_1$} = {\term$_2$}} with {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} being elements of an inductive set. To build the proof, the tactic traverses the normal forms\footnote{Reminder: opaque constants will not be expanded by $\delta$ reductions.} of {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} looking for a couple of subterms {\tt u} and {\tt w} ({\tt u} subterm of the normal form of {\term$_1$} and {\tt w} subterm of the normal form of {\term$_2$}), placed at the same positions and whose head symbols are two different constructors. If such a couple of subterms exists, then the proof of the current goal is completed, otherwise the tactic fails. \Rem The syntax {\tt discriminate {\ident}} can be used to refer to a hypothesis quantified in the goal. In this case, the quantified hypothesis whose name is {\ident} is first introduced in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No primitive equality found} \item \errindex{Not a discriminable equality} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{discriminate \num} This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} followed by \texttt{discriminate \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item \texttt{discriminate {\term} with \bindinglist} This does the same thing as \texttt{discriminate {\term}} but using the given bindings to instantiate parameters or hypotheses of {\term}. \item \texttt{ediscriminate \num}\tacindex{ediscriminate}\\ \texttt{ediscriminate {\term} \zeroone{with \bindinglist}} This works the same as {\tt discriminate} but if the type of {\term}, or the type of the hypothesis referred to by {\num}, has uninstantiated parameters, these parameters are left as existential variables. \item \texttt{discriminate} This behaves like {\tt discriminate {\ident}} if {\ident} is the name of an hypothesis to which {\tt discriminate} is applicable; if the current goal is of the form {\term$_1$} {\tt <>} {\term$_2$}, this behaves as {\tt intro {\ident}; discriminate {\ident}}. \ErrMsg \errindex{No discriminable equalities} \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt injection \term} \label{injection} \tacindex{injection} The {\tt injection} tactic is based on the fact that constructors of inductive sets are injections. That means that if $c$ is a constructor of an inductive set, and if $(c~\vec{t_1})$ and $(c~\vec{t_2})$ are two terms that are equal then $~\vec{t_1}$ and $~\vec{t_2}$ are equal too. If {\term} is a proof of a statement of conclusion {\tt {\term$_1$} = {\term$_2$}}, then {\tt injection} applies injectivity as deep as possible to derive the equality of all the subterms of {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} placed in the same positions. For example, from {\tt (S (S n))=(S (S (S m)))} we may derive {\tt n=(S m)}. To use this tactic {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} should be elements of an inductive set and they should be neither explicitly equal, nor structurally different. We mean by this that, if {\tt n$_1$} and {\tt n$_2$} are their respective normal forms, then: \begin{itemize} \item {\tt n$_1$} and {\tt n$_2$} should not be syntactically equal, \item there must not exist any pair of subterms {\tt u} and {\tt w}, {\tt u} subterm of {\tt n$_1$} and {\tt w} subterm of {\tt n$_2$} , placed in the same positions and having different constructors as head symbols. \end{itemize} If these conditions are satisfied, then, the tactic derives the equality of all the subterms of {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} placed in the same positions and puts them as antecedents of the current goal. \Example Consider the following goal: \begin{coq_example*} Inductive list : Set := | nil : list | cons : nat -> list -> list. Variable P : list -> Prop. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} Lemma ex : forall (l:list) (n:nat), P nil -> cons n l = cons 0 nil -> P l. intros l n H H0. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. injection H0. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} Beware that \texttt{injection} yields an equality in a sigma type whenever the injected object has a dependent type $P$ with its two instances in different types $(P~t_1~...~t_n)$ and $(P~u_1~...~u_n)$. If $t_1$ and $u_1$ are the same and have for type an inductive type for which a decidable equality has been declared using the command {\tt Scheme Equality} (see \ref{Scheme}), the use of a sigma type is avoided. \Rem If some quantified hypothesis of the goal is named {\ident}, then {\tt injection {\ident}} first introduces the hypothesis in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not a projectable equality but a discriminable one} \item \errindex{Nothing to do, it is an equality between convertible terms} \item \errindex{Not a primitive equality} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{injection \num} This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} followed by \texttt{injection \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item \texttt{injection {\term} with \bindinglist} This does the same as \texttt{injection {\term}} but using the given bindings to instantiate parameters or hypotheses of {\term}. \item \texttt{einjection \num}\tacindex{einjection}\\ \texttt{einjection {\term} \zeroone{with \bindinglist}} This works the same as {\tt injection} but if the type of {\term}, or the type of the hypothesis referred to by {\num}, has uninstantiated parameters, these parameters are left as existential variables. \item{\tt injection} If the current goal is of the form {\term$_1$} {\tt <>} {\term$_2$}, this behaves as {\tt intro {\ident}; injection {\ident}}. \ErrMsg \errindex{goal does not satisfy the expected preconditions} \item \texttt{injection {\term} \zeroone{with \bindinglist} as \nelistnosep{\intropattern}}\\ \texttt{injection {\num} as {\intropattern} \dots\ \intropattern}\\ \texttt{injection as {\intropattern} \dots\ \intropattern}\\ \texttt{einjection {\term} \zeroone{with \bindinglist} as \nelistnosep{\intropattern}}\\ \texttt{einjection {\num} as {\intropattern} \dots\ \intropattern}\\ \texttt{einjection as {\intropattern} \dots\ \intropattern} \tacindex{injection \dots\ as} These variants apply \texttt{intros} \nelistnosep{\intropattern} after the call to \texttt{injection} or \texttt{einjection} so that all equalities generated are moved in the context of hypotheses. The number of {\intropattern} must not exceed the number of equalities newly generated. If it is smaller, fresh names are automatically generated to adjust the list of {\intropattern} to the number of new equalities. The original equality is erased if it corresponds to an hypothesis. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt inversion \ident} \tacindex{inversion} Let the type of {\ident} in the local context be $(I~\vec{t})$, where $I$ is a (co)inductive predicate. Then, \texttt{inversion} applied to \ident~ derives for each possible constructor $c_i$ of $(I~\vec{t})$, {\bf all} the necessary conditions that should hold for the instance $(I~\vec{t})$ to be proved by $c_i$. \Rem If {\ident} does not denote a hypothesis in the local context but refers to a hypothesis quantified in the goal, then the latter is first introduced in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \Rem As inversion proofs may be large in size, we recommend the user to stock the lemmas whenever the same instance needs to be inverted several times. See Section~\ref{Derive-Inversion}. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{inversion \num} This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} then \texttt{inversion \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item \tacindex{inversion\_clear} \texttt{inversion\_clear \ident} This behaves as \texttt{inversion} and then erases \ident~ from the context. \item \tacindex{inversion \dots\ as} \texttt{inversion {\ident} as \intropattern} This generally behaves as \texttt{inversion} but using names in {\intropattern} for naming hypotheses. The {\intropattern} must have the form {\tt [} $p_{11} \ldots p_{1n_1}$ {\tt |} {\ldots} {\tt |} $p_{m1} \ldots p_{mn_m}$ {\tt ]} with $m$ being the number of constructors of the type of {\ident}. Be careful that the list must be of length $m$ even if {\tt inversion} discards some cases (which is precisely one of its roles): for the discarded cases, just use an empty list (i.e. $n_i=0$). The arguments of the $i^{th}$ constructor and the equalities that {\tt inversion} introduces in the context of the goal corresponding to the $i^{th}$ constructor, if it exists, get their names from the list $p_{i1}$ \ldots $p_{in_i}$ in order. If there are not enough names, {\tt inversion} invents names for the remaining variables to introduce. In case an equation splits into several equations (because {\tt inversion} applies {\tt injection} on the equalities it generates), the corresponding name $p_{ij}$ in the list must be replaced by a sublist of the form {\tt [$p_{ij1}$ \mbox{\dots} $p_{ijq}$]} (or, equivalently, {\tt ($p_{ij1}$, \dots, $p_{ijq}$)}) where $q$ is the number of subequalities obtained from splitting the original equation. Here is an example. The \texttt{inversion \dots\ as} variant of \texttt{inversion} generally behaves in a slightly more expectable way than \texttt{inversion} (no artificial duplication of some hypotheses referring to other hypotheses) To take benefit of these improvements, it is enough to use \texttt{inversion \dots\ as []}, letting the names being finally chosen by {\Coq}. \begin{coq_eval} Require Import List. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Inductive contains0 : list nat -> Prop := | in_hd : forall l, contains0 (0 :: l) | in_tl : forall l b, contains0 l -> contains0 (b :: l). Goal forall l:list nat, contains0 (1 :: l) -> contains0 l. intros l H; inversion H as [ | l' p Hl' [Heqp Heql'] ]. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \item \texttt{inversion {\num} as \intropattern} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced by \texttt{inversion \num} in the context. \item \tacindex{inversion\_clear \dots\ as} \texttt{inversion\_clear {\ident} as \intropattern} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced by \texttt{inversion\_clear} in the context. Notice that hypothesis names can be provided as if \texttt{inversion} were called, even though the \texttt{inversion\_clear} will eventually erase the hypotheses. \item \tacindex{inversion \dots\ in} \texttt{inversion {\ident} in \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} Let \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, be identifiers in the local context. This tactic behaves as generalizing \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, and then performing \texttt{inversion}. \item \tacindex{inversion \dots\ as \dots\ in} \texttt{inversion {\ident} as {\intropattern} in \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{inversion {\ident} in \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$}. \item \tacindex{inversion\_clear \dots\ in} \texttt{inversion\_clear {\ident} in \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} Let \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, be identifiers in the local context. This tactic behaves as generalizing \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, and then performing {\tt inversion\_clear}. \item \tacindex{inversion\_clear \dots\ as \dots\ in} \texttt{inversion\_clear {\ident} as {\intropattern} in \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{inversion\_clear {\ident} in \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$}. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion} \texttt{dependent inversion \ident} That must be used when \ident\ appears in the current goal. It acts like \texttt{inversion} and then substitutes \ident\ for the corresponding term in the goal. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion \dots\ as } \texttt{dependent inversion {\ident} as \intropattern} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion} {\ident}. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear} \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear \ident} Like \texttt{dependent inversion}, except that {\ident} is cleared from the local context. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear \dots\ as} \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear {\ident} as \intropattern} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear} {\ident}. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion \dots\ with} \texttt{dependent inversion {\ident} with \term} This variant allows you to specify the generalization of the goal. It is useful when the system fails to generalize the goal automatically. If {\ident} has type $(I~\vec{t})$ and $I$ has type $\forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), s$, then \term~ must be of type $I:\forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), I~\vec{x}\to s'$ where $s'$ is the type of the goal. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion \dots\ as \dots\ with} \texttt{dependent inversion {\ident} as {\intropattern} with \term} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion {\ident} with \term}. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear \dots\ with} \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear {\ident} with \term} Like \texttt{dependent inversion \dots\ with} but clears {\ident} from the local context. \item \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear \dots\ as \dots\ with} \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear {\ident} as {\intropattern} with \term} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear {\ident} with \term}. \item \tacindex{simple inversion} \texttt{simple inversion \ident} It is a very primitive inversion tactic that derives all the necessary equalities but it does not simplify the constraints as \texttt{inversion} does. \item \tacindex{simple inversion \dots\ as} \texttt{simple inversion {\ident} as \intropattern} This allows naming the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{simple inversion}. \item \tacindex{inversion \dots\ using} \texttt{inversion {\ident} using \ident$'$} Let {\ident} have type $(I~\vec{t})$ ($I$ an inductive predicate) in the local context, and \ident$'$ be a (dependent) inversion lemma. Then, this tactic refines the current goal with the specified lemma. \item \tacindex{inversion \dots\ using \dots\ in} \texttt{inversion {\ident} using \ident$'$ in \ident$_1$\dots\ \ident$_n$} This tactic behaves as generalizing \ident$_1$\dots\ \ident$_n$, then doing \texttt{inversion {\ident} using \ident$'$}. \end{Variants} \firstexample \example{Non-dependent inversion} \label{inversion-examples} Let us consider the relation \texttt{Le} over natural numbers and the following variables: \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Inductive Le : nat -> nat -> Set := | LeO : forall n:nat, Le 0 n | LeS : forall n m:nat, Le n m -> Le (S n) (S m). Variable P : nat -> nat -> Prop. Variable Q : forall n m:nat, Le n m -> Prop. \end{coq_example*} Let us consider the following goal: \begin{coq_eval} Lemma ex : forall n m:nat, Le (S n) m -> P n m. intros. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. \end{coq_example} To prove the goal, we may need to reason by cases on \texttt{H} and to derive that \texttt{m} is necessarily of the form $(S~m_0)$ for certain $m_0$ and that $(Le~n~m_0)$. Deriving these conditions corresponds to prove that the only possible constructor of \texttt{(Le (S n) m)} is \texttt{LeS} and that we can invert the \texttt{->} in the type of \texttt{LeS}. This inversion is possible because \texttt{Le} is the smallest set closed by the constructors \texttt{LeO} and \texttt{LeS}. \begin{coq_example} inversion_clear H. \end{coq_example} Note that \texttt{m} has been substituted in the goal for \texttt{(S m0)} and that the hypothesis \texttt{(Le n m0)} has been added to the context. Sometimes it is interesting to have the equality \texttt{m=(S m0)} in the context to use it after. In that case we can use \texttt{inversion} that does not clear the equalities: \begin{coq_eval} Undo. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} inversion H. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \example{Dependent inversion} Let us consider the following goal: \begin{coq_eval} Lemma ex_dep : forall (n m:nat) (H:Le (S n) m), Q (S n) m H. intros. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. \end{coq_example} As \texttt{H} occurs in the goal, we may want to reason by cases on its structure and so, we would like inversion tactics to substitute \texttt{H} by the corresponding term in constructor form. Neither \texttt{Inversion} nor {\tt Inversion\_clear} make such a substitution. To have such a behavior we use the dependent inversion tactics: \begin{coq_example} dependent inversion_clear H. \end{coq_example} Note that \texttt{H} has been substituted by \texttt{(LeS n m0 l)} and \texttt{m} by \texttt{(S m0)}. \subsection{\tt fix {\ident} {\num}} \tacindex{fix} \label{tactic:fix} This tactic is a primitive tactic to start a proof by induction. In general, it is easier to rely on higher-level induction tactics such as the ones described in Section~\ref{Tac-induction}. In the syntax of the tactic, the identifier {\ident} is the name given to the induction hypothesis. The natural number {\num} tells on which premise of the current goal the induction acts, starting from 1 and counting both dependent and non dependent products. Especially, the current lemma must be composed of at least {\num} products. Like in a {\tt fix} expression, the induction hypotheses have to be used on structurally smaller arguments. The verification that inductive proof arguments are correct is done only at the time of registering the lemma in the environment. To know if the use of induction hypotheses is correct at some time of the interactive development of a proof, use the command {\tt Guarded} (see Section~\ref{Guarded}). \begin{Variants} \item {\tt fix \ident$_1$ {\num} with ( \ident$_2$ \nelistnosep{\binder$_2$} \zeroone{\{ struct \ident$'_2$ \}} :~\type$_2$ ) \dots\ ( \ident$_n$ \nelistnosep{\binder$_n$} \zeroone{\{ struct \ident$'_n$ \}} :~\type$_n$ )} This starts a proof by mutual induction. The statements to be simultaneously proved are respectively {\tt forall} \nelistnosep{{\binder}$_2$}{\tt ,} {\type}$_2$, {\ldots}, {\tt forall} \nelistnosep{{\binder}$_n$}{\tt ,} {\type}$_n$. The identifiers {\ident}$_1$ {\ldots} {\ident}$_n$ are the names of the induction hypotheses. The identifiers {\ident}$'_2$ {\ldots} {\ident}$'_n$ are the respective names of the premises on which the induction is performed in the statements to be simultaneously proved (if not given, the system tries to guess itself what they are). \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt cofix \ident} \tacindex{cofix} \label{tactic:cofix} This tactic starts a proof by coinduction. The identifier {\ident} is the name given to the coinduction hypothesis. Like in a {\tt cofix} expression, the use of induction hypotheses have to guarded by a constructor. The verification that the use of co-inductive hypotheses is correct is done only at the time of registering the lemma in the environment. To know if the use of coinduction hypotheses is correct at some time of the interactive development of a proof, use the command {\tt Guarded} (see Section~\ref{Guarded}). \begin{Variants} \item {\tt cofix \ident$_1$ with ( \ident$_2$ \nelistnosep{\binder$_2$} :~\type$_2$ ) \dots\ ( \ident$_n$ \nelistnosep{\binder$_n$} :~\type$_n$ )} This starts a proof by mutual coinduction. The statements to be simultaneously proved are respectively {\tt forall} \nelistnosep{{\binder}$_2$}{\tt ,} {\type}$_2$, {\ldots}, {\tt forall} \nelistnosep{{\binder}$_n$}{\tt ,} {\type}$_n$. The identifiers {\ident}$_1$ {\ldots} {\ident}$_n$ are the names of the coinduction hypotheses. \end{Variants} \section{Rewriting expressions} These tactics use the equality {\tt eq:forall A:Type, A->A->Prop} defined in file {\tt Logic.v} (see Section~\ref{Equality}). The notation for {\tt eq}~$T~t~u$ is simply {\tt $t$=$u$} dropping the implicit type of $t$ and $u$. \subsection{\tt rewrite \term} \label{rewrite} \tacindex{rewrite} This tactic applies to any goal. The type of {\term} must have the form \texttt{forall (x$_1$:A$_1$) \dots\ (x$_n$:A$_n$)}\texttt{eq} \term$_1$ \term$_2$. \noindent where \texttt{eq} is the Leibniz equality or a registered setoid equality. \noindent Then {\tt rewrite \term} finds the first subterm matching \term$_1$ in the goal, resulting in instances \term$_1'$ and \term$_2'$ and then replaces every occurrence of \term$_1'$ by \term$_2'$. Hence, some of the variables x$_i$ are solved by unification, and some of the types \texttt{A}$_1$, \dots, \texttt{A}$_n$ become new subgoals. % \Rem In case the type of % \term$_1$ contains occurrences of variables bound in the % type of \term, the tactic tries first to find a subterm of the goal % which matches this term in order to find a closed instance \term$'_1$ % of \term$_1$, and then all instances of \term$'_1$ will be replaced. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{The term provided does not end with an equation} \item \errindex{Tactic generated a subgoal identical to the original goal} This happens if \term$_1$ does not occur in the goal. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt rewrite -> \term}\tacindex{rewrite ->} Is equivalent to {\tt rewrite \term} \item {\tt rewrite <- \term}\tacindex{rewrite <-} Uses the equality \term$_1${\tt=}\term$_2$ from right to left \item {\tt rewrite {\term} in \nterm{clause}} \tacindex{rewrite \dots\ in} Analogous to {\tt rewrite {\term}} but rewriting is done following \nterm{clause} (similarly to \ref{Conversion-tactics}). For instance: \begin{itemize} \item \texttt{rewrite H in H1} will rewrite \texttt{H} in the hypothesis \texttt{H1} instead of the current goal. \item \texttt{rewrite H in H1 at 1, H2 at - 2 |- *} means \texttt{rewrite H; rewrite H in H1 at 1; rewrite H in H2 at - 2}. In particular a failure will happen if any of these three simpler tactics fails. \item \texttt{rewrite H in * |- } will do \texttt{rewrite H in H$_i$} for all hypothesis \texttt{H$_i$ <> H}. A success will happen as soon as at least one of these simpler tactics succeeds. \item \texttt{rewrite H in *} is a combination of \texttt{rewrite H} and \texttt{rewrite H in * |-} that succeeds if at least one of these two tactics succeeds. \end{itemize} Orientation {\tt ->} or {\tt <-} can be inserted before the term to rewrite. \item {\tt rewrite {\term} at {\occlist}} \tacindex{rewrite \dots\ at} Rewrite only the given occurrences of \term$_1'$. Occurrences are specified from left to right as for \texttt{pattern} (\S \ref{pattern}). The rewrite is always performed using setoid rewriting, even for Leibniz's equality, so one has to \texttt{Import Setoid} to use this variant. \item {\tt rewrite {\term} by {\tac}} \tacindex{rewrite \dots\ by} Use {\tac} to completely solve the side-conditions arising from the rewrite. \item {\tt rewrite \term$_1$ , \mbox{\dots} , \term$_n$} Is equivalent to the $n$ successive tactics {\tt rewrite $\term_1$} up to {\tt rewrite $\term_n$}, each one working on the first subgoal generated by the previous one. Orientation {\tt ->} or {\tt <-} can be inserted before each term to rewrite. One unique \nterm{clause} can be added at the end after the keyword {\tt in}; it will then affect all rewrite operations. \item In all forms of {\tt rewrite} described above, a term to rewrite can be immediately prefixed by one of the following modifiers: \begin{itemize} \item {\tt ?} : the tactic {\tt rewrite ?$\term$} performs the rewrite of $\term$ as many times as possible (perhaps zero time). This form never fails. \item {\tt $n$?} : works similarly, except that it will do at most $n$ rewrites. \item {\tt !} : works as {\tt ?}, except that at least one rewrite should succeed, otherwise the tactic fails. \item {\tt $n$!} (or simply {\tt $n$}) : precisely $n$ rewrites of $\term$ will be done, leading to failure if these $n$ rewrites are not possible. \end{itemize} \item {\tt erewrite {\term}\tacindex{erewrite}} This tactic works as {\tt rewrite {\term}} but turning unresolved bindings into existential variables, if any, instead of failing. It has the same variants as {\tt rewrite} has. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt replace \term$_1$ with \term$_2$} \label{tactic:replace} \tacindex{replace \dots\ with} This tactic applies to any goal. It replaces all free occurrences of {\term$_1$} in the current goal with {\term$_2$} and generates the equality {\term$_2$}{\tt =}{\term$_1$} as a subgoal. This equality is automatically solved if it occurs among the assumption, or if its symmetric form occurs. It is equivalent to {\tt cut \term$_2$=\term$_1$; [intro H{\sl n}; rewrite <- H{\sl n}; clear H{\sl n}| assumption || symmetry; try assumption]}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{terms do not have convertible types} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt replace \term$_1$ with \term$_2$ by \tac} This acts as {\tt replace \term$_1$ with \term$_2$} but applies {\tt \tac} to solve the generated subgoal {\tt \term$_2$=\term$_1$}. \item {\tt replace {\term}} Replaces {\term} with {\term'} using the first assumption whose type has the form {\tt \term=\term'} or {\tt \term'=\term}. \item {\tt replace -> {\term}} Replaces {\term} with {\term'} using the first assumption whose type has the form {\tt \term=\term'} \item {\tt replace <- {\term}} Replaces {\term} with {\term'} using the first assumption whose type has the form {\tt \term'=\term} \item {\tt replace {\term$_1$} with {\term$_2$} in \nterm{clause} }\\ {\tt replace {\term$_1$} with {\term$_2$} in \nterm{clause} by \tac }\\ {\tt replace {\term} in \nterm{clause}}\\ {\tt replace -> {\term} in \nterm{clause}}\\ {\tt replace <- {\term} in \nterm{clause}} Acts as before but the replacements take place in \nterm{clause}~(see Section~\ref{Conversion-tactics}) and not only in the conclusion of the goal. The \nterm{clause} argument must not contain any \texttt{type of} nor \texttt{value of}. \item {\tt cutrewrite <- (\term$_1$ = \term$_2$)} %\label{cutrewrite} \tacindex{cutrewrite} This tactic is deprecated. It acts like {\tt replace {\term$_2$} with {\term$_1$}}, or, equivalently as {\tt enough} (\term$_1$ = \term$_2$) {\tt as <-}. \item {\tt cutrewrite -> (\term$_1$ = \term$_2$)} %\label{cutrewrite} \tacindex{cutrewrite} This tactic is deprecated. It can be replaced by {\tt enough} (\term$_1$ = \term$_2$) {\tt as ->}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt subst \ident} \tacindex{subst} \optindex{Regular Subst Tactic} This tactic applies to a goal that has \ident\ in its context and (at least) one hypothesis, say $H$, of type {\tt \ident} = $t$ or $t$ {\tt = \ident} with {\ident} not occurring in $t$. Then it replaces {\ident} by $t$ everywhere in the goal (in the hypotheses and in the conclusion) and clears {\ident} and $H$ from the context. If {\ident} is a local definition of the form {\ident} := $t$, it is also unfolded and cleared. \Rem When several hypotheses have the form {\tt \ident} = $t$ or {\tt $t$ = \ident}, the first one is used. \Rem If $H$ is itself dependent in the goal, it is replaced by the proof of reflexivity of equality. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt subst \ident$_1$ {\dots} \ident$_n$} This is equivalent to {\tt subst \ident$_1$; \dots; subst \ident$_n$}. \item {\tt subst} This applies {\tt subst} repeatedly from top to bottom to all identifiers of the context for which an equality of the form {\tt \ident} = $t$ or $t$ {\tt = \ident} or {\tt \ident} := $t$ exists, with {\ident} not occurring in $t$. \noindent {\bf Remark: } The behavior of {\tt subst} can be controlled using option {\tt Set Regular Subst Tactic}. When this option is activated, {\tt subst} also deals with the following corner cases: \begin{itemize} \item A context with ordered hypotheses {\tt \ident$_1$ = \ident$_2$} and {\tt \ident$_1$ = $t$}, or {$t'$ = \ident$_1$} with $t'$ not a variable, and no other hypotheses of the form {\tt \ident$_2$ = $u$} or {\tt $u$ = \ident$_2$}; without the option, a second call to {\tt subst} would be necessary to replace {\ident$_2$} by $t$ or $t'$ respectively. \item A context with cyclic dependencies as with hypotheses {\tt \ident$_1$ = f~\ident$_2$} and {\tt \ident$_2$ = g~\ident$_1$} which without the option would be a cause of failure of {\tt subst}. \end{itemize} Additionally, it prevents a local definition such as {\tt \ident} := $t$ to be unfolded which otherwise it would exceptionally unfold in configurations containing hypotheses of the form {\tt {\ident} = $u$}, or {\tt $u'$ = \ident} with $u'$ not a variable. Finally, it preserves the initial order of hypotheses, which without the option it may break. The option is on by default. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt stepl \term} \tacindex{stepl} This tactic is for chaining rewriting steps. It assumes a goal of the form ``$R$ {\term}$_1$ {\term}$_2$'' where $R$ is a binary relation and relies on a database of lemmas of the form {\tt forall} $x$ $y$ $z$, $R$ $x$ $y$ {\tt ->} $eq$ $x$ $z$ {\tt ->} $R$ $z$ $y$ where $eq$ is typically a setoid equality. The application of {\tt stepl {\term}} then replaces the goal by ``$R$ {\term} {\term}$_2$'' and adds a new goal stating ``$eq$ {\term} {\term}$_1$''. Lemmas are added to the database using the command \comindex{Declare Left Step} \begin{quote} {\tt Declare Left Step {\term}.} \end{quote} The tactic is especially useful for parametric setoids which are not accepted as regular setoids for {\tt rewrite} and {\tt setoid\_replace} (see Chapter~\ref{setoids}). \begin{Variants} \item{\tt stepl {\term} by {\tac}} This applies {\tt stepl {\term}} then applies {\tac} to the second goal. \item{\tt stepr {\term}}\\ {\tt stepr {\term} by {\tac}}\tacindex{stepr} This behaves as {\tt stepl} but on the right-hand-side of the binary relation. Lemmas are expected to be of the form ``{\tt forall} $x$ $y$ $z$, $R$ $x$ $y$ {\tt ->} $eq$ $y$ $z$ {\tt ->} $R$ $x$ $z$'' and are registered using the command \comindex{Declare Right Step} \begin{quote} {\tt Declare Right Step {\term}.} \end{quote} \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt change \term} \tacindex{change} \label{change} This tactic applies to any goal. It implements the rule ``Conv''\index{Typing rules!Conv} given in Section~\ref{Conv}. {\tt change U} replaces the current goal \T\ with \U\ providing that \U\ is well-formed and that \T\ and \U\ are convertible. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not convertible} \end{ErrMsgs} \tacindex{change \dots\ in} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt change \term$_1$ with \term$_2$} This replaces the occurrences of \term$_1$ by \term$_2$ in the current goal. The terms \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ must be convertible. \item {\tt change \term$_1$ at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$ with \term$_2$} This replaces the occurrences numbered \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$ of \term$_1$ by \term$_2$ in the current goal. The terms \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ must be convertible. \ErrMsg {\tt Too few occurrences} \item {\tt change {\term} in {\ident}} \item {\tt change \term$_1$ with \term$_2$ in {\ident}} \item {\tt change \term$_1$ at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$ with \term$_2$ in {\ident}} This applies the {\tt change} tactic not to the goal but to the hypothesis {\ident}. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso \ref{Conversion-tactics} \section{Performing computations \index{Conversion tactics} \label{Conversion-tactics}} This set of tactics implements different specialized usages of the tactic \texttt{change}. All conversion tactics (including \texttt{change}) can be parameterized by the parts of the goal where the conversion can occur. This is done using \emph{goal clauses} which consists in a list of hypotheses and, optionally, of a reference to the conclusion of the goal. For defined hypothesis it is possible to specify if the conversion should occur on the type part, the body part or both (default). \index{Clauses} \index{Goal clauses} Goal clauses are written after a conversion tactic (tactics \texttt{set}~\ref{tactic:set}, \texttt{rewrite}~\ref{rewrite}, \texttt{replace}~\ref{tactic:replace} and \texttt{autorewrite}~\ref{tactic:autorewrite} also use goal clauses) and are introduced by the keyword \texttt{in}. If no goal clause is provided, the default is to perform the conversion only in the conclusion. The syntax and description of the various goal clauses is the following: \begin{description} \item[]\texttt{in {\ident}$_1$ $\ldots$ {\ident}$_n$ |- } only in hypotheses {\ident}$_1$ \ldots {\ident}$_n$ \item[]\texttt{in {\ident}$_1$ $\ldots$ {\ident}$_n$ |- *} in hypotheses {\ident}$_1$ \ldots {\ident}$_n$ and in the conclusion \item[]\texttt{in * |-} in every hypothesis \item[]\texttt{in *} (equivalent to \texttt{in * |- *}) everywhere \item[]\texttt{in (type of {\ident}$_1$) (value of {\ident}$_2$) $\ldots$ |-} in type part of {\ident}$_1$, in the value part of {\ident}$_2$, etc. \end{description} For backward compatibility, the notation \texttt{in}~{\ident}$_1$\ldots {\ident}$_n$ performs the conversion in hypotheses {\ident}$_1$\ldots {\ident}$_n$. %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %voir reduction__conv_x : histoires d'univers. %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \subsection{{\tt cbv \flag$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \flag$_n$}, {\tt lazy \flag$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \flag$_n$}, and \tt compute} \tacindex{cbv} \tacindex{lazy} \tacindex{compute} \tacindex{vm\_compute}\label{vmcompute} \tacindex{native\_compute}\label{nativecompute} These parameterized reduction tactics apply to any goal and perform the normalization of the goal according to the specified flags. In correspondence with the kinds of reduction considered in \Coq\, namely $\beta$ (reduction of functional application), $\delta$ (unfolding of transparent constants, see \ref{Transparent}), $\iota$ (reduction of pattern-matching over a constructed term, and unfolding of {\tt fix} and {\tt cofix} expressions) and $\zeta$ (contraction of local definitions), the flag are either {\tt beta}, {\tt delta}, {\tt iota} or {\tt zeta}. The {\tt delta} flag itself can be refined into {\tt delta [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]} or {\tt delta -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]}, restricting in the first case the constants to unfold to the constants listed, and restricting in the second case the constant to unfold to all but the ones explicitly mentioned. Notice that the {\tt delta} flag does not apply to variables bound by a let-in construction inside the term itself (use here the {\tt zeta} flag). In any cases, opaque constants are not unfolded (see Section~\ref{Opaque}). Normalization according to the flags is done by first evaluating the head of the expression into a {\em weak-head} normal form, i.e. until the evaluation is bloked by a variable (or an opaque constant, or an axiom), as e.g. in {\tt x\;u$_1$\;...\;u$_n$}, or {\tt match x with ... end}, or {\tt (fix f x \{struct x\} := ...) x}, or is a constructed form (a $\lambda$-expression, a constructor, a cofixpoint, an inductive type, a product type, a sort), or is a redex that the flags prevent to reduce. Once a weak-head normal form is obtained, subterms are recursively reduced using the same strategy. Reduction to weak-head normal form can be done using two strategies: {\em lazy} ({\tt lazy} tactic), or {\em call-by-value} ({\tt cbv} tactic). The lazy strategy is a call-by-need strategy, with sharing of reductions: the arguments of a function call are weakly evaluated only when necessary, and if an argument is used several times then it is weakly computed only once. This reduction is efficient for reducing expressions with dead code. For instance, the proofs of a proposition {\tt exists~$x$. $P(x)$} reduce to a pair of a witness $t$, and a proof that $t$ satisfies the predicate $P$. Most of the time, $t$ may be computed without computing the proof of $P(t)$, thanks to the lazy strategy. The call-by-value strategy is the one used in ML languages: the arguments of a function call are systematically weakly evaluated first. Despite the lazy strategy always performs fewer reductions than the call-by-value strategy, the latter is generally more efficient for evaluating purely computational expressions (i.e. with few dead code). \begin{Variants} \item {\tt compute} \tacindex{compute}\\ {\tt cbv} These are synonyms for {\tt cbv beta delta iota zeta}. \item {\tt lazy} This is a synonym for {\tt lazy beta delta iota zeta}. \item {\tt compute [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]}\\ {\tt cbv [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]} These are synonyms of {\tt cbv beta delta [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$] iota zeta}. \item {\tt compute -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]}\\ {\tt cbv -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]} These are synonyms of {\tt cbv beta delta -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$] iota zeta}. \item {\tt lazy [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]}\\ {\tt lazy -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]} These are respectively synonyms of {\tt lazy beta delta [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$] iota zeta} and {\tt lazy beta delta -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$] iota zeta}. \item {\tt vm\_compute} \tacindex{vm\_compute} This tactic evaluates the goal using the optimized call-by-value evaluation bytecode-based virtual machine described in \cite{CompiledStrongReduction}. This algorithm is dramatically more efficient than the algorithm used for the {\tt cbv} tactic, but it cannot be fine-tuned. It is specially interesting for full evaluation of algebraic objects. This includes the case of reflection-based tactics. \item {\tt native\_compute} \tacindex{native\_compute} This tactic evaluates the goal by compilation to \ocaml{} as described in \cite{FullReduction}. If \Coq{} is running in native code, it can be typically two to five times faster than {\tt vm\_compute}. Note however that the compilation cost is higher, so it is worth using only for intensive computations. \end{Variants} % Obsolete? Anyway not very important message %\begin{ErrMsgs} %\item \errindex{Delta must be specified before} % % A list of constants appeared before the {\tt delta} flag. %\end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt red} \tacindex{red} This tactic applies to a goal that has the form {\tt forall (x:T1)\dots(xk:Tk), t} with {\tt t} $\beta\iota\zeta$-reducing to {\tt c t1 \dots\ tn} and {\tt c} a constant. If {\tt c} is transparent then it replaces {\tt c} with its definition (say {\tt t}) and then reduces {\tt (t t1 \dots\ tn)} according to $\beta\iota\zeta$-reduction rules. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not reducible} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt hnf} \tacindex{hnf} This tactic applies to any goal. It replaces the current goal with its head normal form according to the $\beta\delta\iota\zeta$-reduction rules, i.e. it reduces the head of the goal until it becomes a product or an irreducible term. All inner $\beta\iota$-redexes are also reduced. \Example The term \verb+forall n:nat, (plus (S n) (S n))+ is not reduced by {\tt hnf}. \Rem The $\delta$ rule only applies to transparent constants (see Section~\ref{Opaque} on transparency and opacity). \subsection{\texorpdfstring{\texttt{cbn}}{cbn} and \texorpdfstring{\texttt{simpl}}{simpl}} \tacindex{cbn} \tacindex{simpl} These tactics apply to any goal. They try to reduce a term to something still readable instead of fully normalizing it. They perform a sort of strong normalization with two key differences: \begin{itemize} \item They unfold a constant if and only if it leads to a $\iota$-reduction, i.e. reducing a match or unfolding a fixpoint. \item While reducing a constant unfolding to (co)fixpoints, the tactics use the name of the constant the (co)fixpoint comes from instead of the (co)fixpoint definition in recursive calls. \end{itemize} The \texttt{cbn} tactic is claimed to be a more principled, faster and more predictable replacement for \texttt{simpl}. The \texttt{cbn} tactic accepts the same flags as \texttt{cbv} and \texttt{lazy}. The behavior of both \texttt{simpl} and \texttt{cbn} can be tuned using the \texttt{Arguments} vernacular command as follows: \comindex{Arguments} \begin{itemize} \item A constant can be marked to be never unfolded by \texttt{cbn} or \texttt{simpl}: \begin{coq_example*} Arguments minus n m : simpl never. \end{coq_example*} After that command an expression like \texttt{(minus (S x) y)} is left untouched by the tactics \texttt{cbn} and \texttt{simpl}. \item A constant can be marked to be unfolded only if applied to enough arguments. The number of arguments required can be specified using the {\tt /} symbol in the arguments list of the {\tt Arguments} vernacular command. \begin{coq_example*} Definition fcomp A B C f (g : A -> B) (x : A) : C := f (g x). Notation "f \o g" := (fcomp f g) (at level 50). Arguments fcomp {A B C} f g x /. \end{coq_example*} After that command the expression {\tt (f \verb+\+o g)} is left untouched by {\tt simpl} while {\tt ((f \verb+\+o g) t)} is reduced to {\tt (f (g t))}. The same mechanism can be used to make a constant volatile, i.e. always unfolded. \begin{coq_example*} Definition volatile := fun x : nat => x. Arguments volatile / x. \end{coq_example*} \item A constant can be marked to be unfolded only if an entire set of arguments evaluates to a constructor. The {\tt !} symbol can be used to mark such arguments. \begin{coq_example*} Arguments minus !n !m. \end{coq_example*} After that command, the expression {\tt (minus (S x) y)} is left untouched by {\tt simpl}, while {\tt (minus (S x) (S y))} is reduced to {\tt (minus x y)}. \item A special heuristic to determine if a constant has to be unfolded can be activated with the following command: \begin{coq_example*} Arguments minus n m : simpl nomatch. \end{coq_example*} The heuristic avoids to perform a simplification step that would expose a {\tt match} construct in head position. For example the expression {\tt (minus (S (S x)) (S y))} is simplified to {\tt (minus (S x) y)} even if an extra simplification is possible. \end{itemize} In detail, the tactic \texttt{simpl} first applies $\beta\iota$-reduction. Then, it expands transparent constants and tries to reduce further using $\beta\iota$-reduction. But, when no $\iota$ rule is applied after unfolding then $\delta$-reductions are not applied. For instance trying to use \texttt{simpl} on \texttt{(plus n O)=n} changes nothing. Notice that only transparent constants whose name can be reused in the recursive calls are possibly unfolded by \texttt{simpl}. For instance a constant defined by \texttt{plus' := plus} is possibly unfolded and reused in the recursive calls, but a constant such as \texttt{succ := plus (S O)} is never unfolded. This is the main difference between \texttt{simpl} and \texttt{cbn}. The tactic \texttt{cbn} reduces whenever it will be able to reuse it or not: \texttt{succ t} is reduced to \texttt{S t}. \tacindex{simpl \dots\ in} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt cbn [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]}\\ {\tt cbn -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]} These are respectively synonyms of {\tt cbn beta delta [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$] iota zeta} and {\tt cbn beta delta -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$] iota zeta} (see \ref{vmcompute}). \item {\tt simpl {\pattern}} This applies {\tt simpl} only to the subterms matching {\pattern} in the current goal. \item {\tt simpl {\pattern} at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$} This applies {\tt simpl} only to the \num$_1$, \dots, \num$_i$ occurrences of the subterms matching {\pattern} in the current goal. \ErrMsg {\tt Too few occurrences} \item {\tt simpl {\qualid}}\\ {\tt simpl {\qstring}} This applies {\tt simpl} only to the applicative subterms whose head occurrence is the unfoldable constant {\qualid} (the constant can be referred to by its notation using {\qstring} if such a notation exists). \item {\tt simpl {\qualid} at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$}\\ {\tt simpl {\qstring} at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$}\\ This applies {\tt simpl} only to the \num$_1$, \dots, \num$_i$ applicative subterms whose head occurrence is {\qualid} (or {\qstring}). \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt unfold \qualid} \tacindex{unfold} \label{unfold} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\qualid} must denote a defined transparent constant or local definition (see Sections~\ref{Basic-definitions} and~\ref{Transparent}). The tactic {\tt unfold} applies the $\delta$ rule to each occurrence of the constant to which {\qualid} refers in the current goal and then replaces it with its $\beta\iota$-normal form. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item {\qualid} \errindex{does not denote an evaluable constant} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt unfold {\qualid}$_1$, \dots, \qualid$_n$} \tacindex{unfold \dots\ in} Replaces {\em simultaneously} {\qualid}$_1$, \dots, {\qualid}$_n$ with their definitions and replaces the current goal with its $\beta\iota$ normal form. \item {\tt unfold {\qualid}$_1$ at \num$_1^1$, \dots, \num$_i^1$, \dots,\ \qualid$_n$ at \num$_1^n$ \dots\ \num$_j^n$} The lists \num$_1^1$, \dots, \num$_i^1$ and \num$_1^n$, \dots, \num$_j^n$ specify the occurrences of {\qualid}$_1$, \dots, \qualid$_n$ to be unfolded. Occurrences are located from left to right. \ErrMsg {\tt bad occurrence number of {\qualid}$_i$} \ErrMsg {\qualid}$_i$ {\tt does not occur} \item {\tt unfold {\qstring}} If {\qstring} denotes the discriminating symbol of a notation (e.g. {\tt "+"}) or an expression defining a notation (e.g. \verb!"_ + _"!), and this notation refers to an unfoldable constant, then the tactic unfolds it. \item {\tt unfold {\qstring}\%{\delimkey}} This is variant of {\tt unfold {\qstring}} where {\qstring} gets its interpretation from the scope bound to the delimiting key {\delimkey} instead of its default interpretation (see Section~\ref{scopechange}). \item {\tt unfold \qualidorstring$_1$ at \num$_1^1$, \dots, \num$_i^1$, \dots,\ \qualidorstring$_n$ at \num$_1^n$ \dots\ \num$_j^n$} This is the most general form, where {\qualidorstring} is either a {\qualid} or a {\qstring} referring to a notation. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt fold \term} \tacindex{fold} This tactic applies to any goal. The term \term\ is reduced using the {\tt red} tactic. Every occurrence of the resulting term in the goal is then replaced by \term. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt fold} \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$ Equivalent to {\tt fold} \term$_1${\tt;}\ldots{\tt; fold} \term$_n$. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt pattern \term} \tacindex{pattern} \label{pattern} This command applies to any goal. The argument {\term} must be a free subterm of the current goal. The command {\tt pattern} performs $\beta$-expansion (the inverse of $\bt$-reduction) of the current goal (say \T) by \begin{enumerate} \item replacing all occurrences of {\term} in {\T} with a fresh variable \item abstracting this variable \item applying the abstracted goal to {\term} \end{enumerate} For instance, if the current goal $T$ is expressible has $\phi(t)$ where the notation captures all the instances of $t$ in $\phi(t)$, then {\tt pattern $t$} transforms it into {\tt (fun x:$A$ => $\phi(${\tt x}$)$) $t$}. This command can be used, for instance, when the tactic {\tt apply} fails on matching. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt pattern {\term} at {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$}} Only the occurrences {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$} of {\term} are considered for $\beta$-expansion. Occurrences are located from left to right. \item {\tt pattern {\term} at - {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$}} All occurrences except the occurrences of indexes {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$} of {\term} are considered for $\beta$-expansion. Occurrences are located from left to right. \item {\tt pattern {\term$_1$}, \dots, {\term$_m$}} Starting from a goal $\phi(t_1 \dots\ t_m)$, the tactic {\tt pattern $t_1$, \dots,\ $t_m$} generates the equivalent goal {\tt (fun (x$_1$:$A_1$) \dots\ (x$_m$:$A_m$) => $\phi(${\tt x$_1$\dots\ x$_m$}$)$) $t_1$ \dots\ $t_m$}. If $t_i$ occurs in one of the generated types $A_j$ these occurrences will also be considered and possibly abstracted. \item {\tt pattern {\term$_1$} at {\num$_1^1$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_1}^1$}, \dots, {\term$_m$} at {\num$_1^m$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_m}^m$}} This behaves as above but processing only the occurrences \num$_1^1$, \dots, \num$_i^1$ of \term$_1$, \dots, \num$_1^m$, \dots, \num$_j^m$ of \term$_m$ starting from \term$_m$. \item {\tt pattern} {\term$_1$} \zeroone{{\tt at \zeroone{-}} {\num$_1^1$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_1}^1$}} {\tt ,} \dots {\tt ,} {\term$_m$} \zeroone{{\tt at \zeroone{-}} {\num$_1^m$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_m}^m$}} This is the most general syntax that combines the different variants. \end{Variants} \subsection{Conversion tactics applied to hypotheses} {\convtactic} {\tt in} \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ Applies the conversion tactic {\convtactic} to the hypotheses \ident$_1$, \ldots, \ident$_n$. The tactic {\convtactic} is any of the conversion tactics listed in this section. If \ident$_i$ is a local definition, then \ident$_i$ can be replaced by (Type of \ident$_i$) to address not the body but the type of the local definition. Example: {\tt unfold not in (Type of H1) (Type of H3).} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} : {\ident}. \end{ErrMsgs} \section{Automation} \subsection{\tt auto} \label{auto} \tacindex{auto} This tactic implements a Prolog-like resolution procedure to solve the current goal. It first tries to solve the goal using the {\tt assumption} tactic, then it reduces the goal to an atomic one using {\tt intros} and introduces the newly generated hypotheses as hints. Then it looks at the list of tactics associated to the head symbol of the goal and tries to apply one of them (starting from the tactics with lower cost). This process is recursively applied to the generated subgoals. By default, \texttt{auto} only uses the hypotheses of the current goal and the hints of the database named {\tt core}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt auto \num} Forces the search depth to be \num. The maximal search depth is 5 by default. \item {\tt auto with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} Uses the hint databases $\ident_1$ \dots\ $\ident_n$ in addition to the database {\tt core}. See Section~\ref{Hints-databases} for the list of pre-defined databases and the way to create or extend a database. This option can be combined with the previous one. \item {\tt auto with *} Uses all existing hint databases, minus the special database {\tt v62}. See Section~\ref{Hints-databases} \item \texttt{auto using} \nterm{lemma}$_1$ {\tt ,} {\ldots} {\tt ,} \nterm{lemma}$_n$ Uses \nterm{lemma}$_1$, \ldots, \nterm{lemma}$_n$ in addition to hints (can be combined with the \texttt{with \ident} option). If $lemma_i$ is an inductive type, it is the collection of its constructors which is added as hints. \item \texttt{auto using} \nterm{lemma}$_1$ {\tt ,} {\ldots} {\tt ,} \nterm{lemma}$_n$ with \ident$_1$ {\ldots} \ident$_n$ This combines the effects of the {\tt using} and {\tt with} options. \item {\tt trivial}\tacindex{trivial} This tactic is a restriction of {\tt auto} that is not recursive and tries only hints that cost 0. Typically it solves trivial equalities like $X=X$. \item \texttt{trivial with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} \item \texttt{trivial with *} \end{Variants} \Rem {\tt auto} either solves completely the goal or else leaves it intact. \texttt{auto} and \texttt{trivial} never fail. \SeeAlso Section~\ref{Hints-databases} \subsection{\tt eauto} \tacindex{eauto} \label{eauto} This tactic generalizes {\tt auto}. While {\tt auto} does not try resolution hints which would leave existential variables in the goal, {\tt eauto} does try them (informally speaking, it uses {\tt eapply} where {\tt auto} uses {\tt apply}). As a consequence, {\tt eauto} can solve such a goal: \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Hint Resolve ex_intro. Goal forall P:nat -> Prop, P 0 -> exists n, P n. eauto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} Note that {\tt ex\_intro} should be declared as an hint. \SeeAlso Section~\ref{Hints-databases} \subsection{\tt autounfold with \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$} \tacindex{autounfold} \label{autounfold} This tactic unfolds constants that were declared through a {\tt Hint Unfold} in the given databases. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt autounfold with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ in \nterm{clause}} Performs the unfolding in the given clause. \item {\tt autounfold with *} Uses the unfold hints declared in all the hint databases. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt autorewrite with \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$} \label{tactic:autorewrite} \tacindex{autorewrite} This tactic \footnote{The behavior of this tactic has much changed compared to the versions available in the previous distributions (V6). This may cause significant changes in your theories to obtain the same result. As a drawback of the re-engineering of the code, this tactic has also been completely revised to get a very compact and readable version.} carries out rewritings according the rewriting rule bases {\tt \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$}. Each rewriting rule of a base \ident$_i$ is applied to the main subgoal until it fails. Once all the rules have been processed, if the main subgoal has progressed (e.g., if it is distinct from the initial main goal) then the rules of this base are processed again. If the main subgoal has not progressed then the next base is processed. For the bases, the behavior is exactly similar to the processing of the rewriting rules. The rewriting rule bases are built with the {\tt Hint~Rewrite} vernacular command. \Warning{} This tactic may loop if you build non terminating rewriting systems. \begin{Variant} \item {\tt autorewrite with \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$ using \tac} Performs, in the same way, all the rewritings of the bases {\tt \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$} applying {\tt \tac} to the main subgoal after each rewriting step. \item {\tt autorewrite with \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$ in \qualid} Performs all the rewritings in hypothesis {\qualid}. \item {\tt autorewrite with \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$ in {\qualid} using \tac} Performs all the rewritings in hypothesis {\qualid} applying {\tt \tac} to the main subgoal after each rewriting step. \item {\tt autorewrite with \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$ in \nterm{clause}} Performs all the rewriting in the clause \nterm{clause}. The \nterm{clause} argument must not contain any \texttt{type of} nor \texttt{value of}. \end{Variant} \SeeAlso Section~\ref{HintRewrite} for feeding the database of lemmas used by {\tt autorewrite}. \SeeAlso Section~\ref{autorewrite-example} for examples showing the use of this tactic. % En attente d'un moyen de valoriser les fichiers de demos %\SeeAlso file \texttt{contrib/Rocq/DEMOS/Demo\_AutoRewrite.v} \section{Controlling automation} \subsection{The hints databases for {\tt auto} and {\tt eauto}} \index{Hints databases} \label{Hints-databases} \comindex{Hint} The hints for \texttt{auto} and \texttt{eauto} are stored in databases. Each database maps head symbols to a list of hints. One can use the command \texttt{Print Hint \ident} to display the hints associated to the head symbol \ident{} (see \ref{PrintHint}). Each hint has a cost that is a nonnegative integer, and an optional pattern. The hints with lower cost are tried first. A hint is tried by \texttt{auto} when the conclusion of the current goal matches its pattern or when it has no pattern. \subsubsection*{Creating Hint databases \label{CreateHintDb}\comindex{CreateHintDb}} One can optionally declare a hint database using the command \texttt{Create HintDb}. If a hint is added to an unknown database, it will be automatically created. \medskip \texttt{Create HintDb} {\ident} [\texttt{discriminated}] \medskip This command creates a new database named \ident. The database is implemented by a Discrimination Tree (DT) that serves as an index of all the lemmas. The DT can use transparency information to decide if a constant should be indexed or not (c.f. \ref{HintTransparency}), making the retrieval more efficient. The legacy implementation (the default one for new databases) uses the DT only on goals without existentials (i.e., auto goals), for non-Immediate hints and do not make use of transparency hints, putting more work on the unification that is run after retrieval (it keeps a list of the lemmas in case the DT is not used). The new implementation enabled by the {\tt discriminated} option makes use of DTs in all cases and takes transparency information into account. However, the order in which hints are retrieved from the DT may differ from the order in which they were inserted, making this implementation observationally different from the legacy one. The general command to add a hint to some databases \ident$_1$, \dots, \ident$_n$ is \begin{tabbing} {\tt Hint {\hintdef} :~\ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$} \end{tabbing} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Hint \hintdef} No database name is given: the hint is registered in the {\tt core} database. \item {\tt Local Hint {\hintdef} :~\ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$} This is used to declare hints that must not be exported to the other modules that require and import the current module. Inside a section, the option {\tt Local} is useless since hints do not survive anyway to the closure of sections. \item {\tt Local Hint \hintdef} Idem for the {\tt core} database. \end{Variants} The {\hintdef} is one of the following expressions: \begin{itemize} \item {\tt Resolve \term} \comindex{Hint Resolve} This command adds {\tt simple apply {\term}} to the hint list with the head symbol of the type of \term. The cost of that hint is the number of subgoals generated by {\tt simple apply {\term}}. %{\tt auto} actually uses a slightly modified variant of {\tt simple apply} with use_metas_eagerly_in_conv_on_closed_terms set to false % Is it really needed? %% In case the inferred type of \term\ does not start with a product %% the tactic added in the hint list is {\tt exact {\term}}. In case %% this type can however be reduced to a type starting with a product, %% the tactic {\tt apply {\term}} is also stored in the hints list. If the inferred type of \term\ contains a dependent quantification on a variable which occurs only in the premisses of the type and not in its conclusion, no instance could be inferred for the variable by unification with the goal. In this case, the hint is added to the hint list of {\tt eauto} (see \ref{eauto}) instead of the hint list of {\tt auto} and a warning is printed. A typical example of a hint that is used only by \texttt{eauto} is a transitivity lemma. \begin{ErrMsgs} %% \item \errindex{Bound head variable} \item \term\ \errindex{cannot be used as a hint} The head symbol of the type of {\term} is a bound variable such that this tactic cannot be associated to a constant. %% The type of {\term} contains products over variables that do not %% appear in the conclusion. A typical example is a transitivity axiom. %% In that case the {\tt simple apply} tactic fails, and thus is useless. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Resolve \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_m$} Adds each \texttt{Resolve} {\term$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Immediate {\term}} \comindex{Hint Immediate} This command adds {\tt simple apply {\term}; trivial} to the hint list associated with the head symbol of the type of {\ident} in the given database. This tactic will fail if all the subgoals generated by {\tt simple apply {\term}} are not solved immediately by the {\tt trivial} tactic (which only tries tactics with cost $0$). This command is useful for theorems such as the symmetry of equality or $n+1=m+1 \to n=m$ that we may like to introduce with a limited use in order to avoid useless proof-search. The cost of this tactic (which never generates subgoals) is always 1, so that it is not used by {\tt trivial} itself. \begin{ErrMsgs} %% \item \errindex{Bound head variable} \item \term\ \errindex{cannot be used as a hint} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Immediate \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_m$} Adds each \texttt{Immediate} {\term$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Constructors} {\ident} \comindex{Hint Constructors} If {\ident} is an inductive type, this command adds all its constructors as hints of type \texttt{Resolve}. Then, when the conclusion of current goal has the form \texttt{({\ident} \dots)}, \texttt{auto} will try to apply each constructor. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item {\ident} \errindex{is not an inductive type} % No need to have this message here, is is generic to all commands % referring to globals %% \item {\ident} \errindex{not declared} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Constructors \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$} Adds each \texttt{Constructors} {\ident$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Unfold} {\qualid} \comindex{Hint Unfold} This adds the tactic {\tt unfold {\qualid}} to the hint list that will only be used when the head constant of the goal is \ident. Its cost is 4. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Unfold \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$} Adds each \texttt{Unfold} {\ident$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Transparent}, \texttt{Opaque} {\qualid} \label{HintTransparency} \comindex{Hint Transparent} \comindex{Hint Opaque} This adds a transparency hint to the database, making {\tt {\qualid}} a transparent or opaque constant during resolution. This information is used during unification of the goal with any lemma in the database and inside the discrimination network to relax or constrain it in the case of \texttt{discriminated} databases. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{Transparent}, \texttt{Opaque} {\ident$_1$} \mbox{\dots} {\ident$_m$} Declares each {\ident$_i$} as a transparent or opaque constant. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Extern \num\ [\pattern]\ => }\textsl{tactic} \comindex{Hint Extern} This hint type is to extend \texttt{auto} with tactics other than \texttt{apply} and \texttt{unfold}. For that, we must specify a cost, an optional pattern and a tactic to execute. Here is an example: \begin{quotation} \begin{verbatim} Hint Extern 4 (~(_ = _)) => discriminate. \end{verbatim} \end{quotation} Now, when the head of the goal is a disequality, \texttt{auto} will try \texttt{discriminate} if it does not manage to solve the goal with hints with a cost less than 4. One can even use some sub-patterns of the pattern in the tactic script. A sub-pattern is a question mark followed by an identifier, like \texttt{?X1} or \texttt{?X2}. Here is an example: % Require EqDecide. \begin{coq_example*} Require Import List. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} Hint Extern 5 ({?X1 = ?X2} + {?X1 <> ?X2}) => generalize X1, X2; decide equality : eqdec. Goal forall a b:list (nat * nat), {a = b} + {a <> b}. Info 1 auto with eqdec. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \item \texttt{Cut} {\textit{regexp}} \label{HintCut} \comindex{Hint Cut} \textit{Warning:} these hints currently only apply to typeclass proof search and the \texttt{typeclasses eauto} tactic. This command can be used to cut the proof-search tree according to a regular expression matching paths to be cut. The grammar for regular expressions is the following: \[\begin{array}{lcll} e & ::= & \ident & \text{ hint or instance identifier } \\ & & \texttt{*} & \text{ any hint } \\ & & e | e' & \text{ disjunction } \\ & & e ; e' & \text{ sequence } \\ & & ! e & \text{ Kleene star } \\ & & \texttt{emp} & \text{ empty } \\ & & \texttt{eps} & \text{ epsilon } \\ & & \texttt{(} e \texttt{)} & \end{array}\] The \texttt{emp} regexp does not match any search path while \texttt{eps} matches the empty path. During proof search, the path of successive successful hints on a search branch is recorded, as a list of identifiers for the hints (note \texttt{Hint Extern}'s do not have an associated identifier). Before applying any hint $\ident$ the current path $p$ extended with $\ident$ is matched against the current cut expression $c$ associated to the hint database. If matching succeeds, the hint is \emph{not} applied. The semantics of \texttt{Hint Cut} $e$ is to set the cut expression to $c | e$, the initial cut expression being \texttt{emp}. \item \texttt{Mode} {\tt (+ | -)}$^*$ {\qualid} \label{HintMode} \comindex{Hint Mode} This sets an optional mode of use of the identifier {\qualid}. When proof-search faces a goal that ends in an application of {\qualid} to arguments {\tt \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$}, the mode tells if the hints associated to qualid can be applied or not. A mode specification is a list of $n$ {\tt +} or {\tt -} items that specify if an argument is to be treated as an input {\tt +} or an output {\tt -} of the identifier. For a mode to match a list of arguments, input terms \emph{must not} contain existential variables, while outputs can be any term. Multiple modes can be declared for a single identifier, in that case only one mode needs to match the arguments for the hints to be applied. {\tt Hint Mode} is especially useful for typeclasses, when one does not want to support default instances and avoid ambiguity in general. Setting a parameter of a class as an input forces proof-search to be driven by that index of the class. \end{itemize} \Rem One can use an \texttt{Extern} hint with no pattern to do pattern-matching on hypotheses using \texttt{match goal with} inside the tactic. % There are shortcuts that allow to define several goal at once: % \begin{itemize} % \item \comindex{Hints Resolve}\texttt{Hints Resolve \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ : \ident.}\\ % This command is a shortcut for the following ones: % \begin{quotation} % \noindent\texttt{Hint \ident$_1$ : \ident\ := Resolve \ident$_1$}\\ % \dots\\ % \texttt{Hint \ident$_1$ : \ident := Resolve \ident$_1$} % \end{quotation} % Notice that the hint name is the same that the theorem given as % hint. % \item \comindex{Hints Immediate}\texttt{Hints Immediate \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ : \ident.}\\ % \item \comindex{Hints Unfold}\texttt{Hints Unfold \qualid$_1$ \dots\ \qualid$_n$ : \ident.}\\ % \end{itemize} %\begin{Warnings} % \item \texttt{Overriding hint named \dots\ in database \dots} %\end{Warnings} \subsection{Hint databases defined in the \Coq\ standard library} Several hint databases are defined in the \Coq\ standard library. The actual content of a database is the collection of the hints declared to belong to this database in each of the various modules currently loaded. Especially, requiring new modules potentially extend a database. At {\Coq} startup, only the {\tt core} and {\tt v62} databases are non empty and can be used. \begin{description} \item[\tt core] This special database is automatically used by \texttt{auto}, except when pseudo-database \texttt{nocore} is given to \texttt{auto}. The \texttt{core} database contains only basic lemmas about negation, conjunction, and so on from. Most of the hints in this database come from the \texttt{Init} and \texttt{Logic} directories. \item[\tt arith] This database contains all lemmas about Peano's arithmetic proved in the directories \texttt{Init} and \texttt{Arith} \item[\tt zarith] contains lemmas about binary signed integers from the directories \texttt{theories/ZArith}. When required, the module {\tt Omega} also extends the database {\tt zarith} with a high-cost hint that calls {\tt omega} on equations and inequalities in {\tt nat} or {\tt Z}. \item[\tt bool] contains lemmas about booleans, mostly from directory \texttt{theories/Bool}. \item[\tt datatypes] is for lemmas about lists, streams and so on that are mainly proved in the \texttt{Lists} subdirectory. \item[\tt sets] contains lemmas about sets and relations from the directories \texttt{Sets} and \texttt{Relations}. \item[\tt typeclass\_instances] contains all the type class instances declared in the environment, including those used for \texttt{setoid\_rewrite}, from the \texttt{Classes} directory. \end{description} There is also a special database called {\tt v62}. It collects all hints that were declared in the versions of {\Coq} prior to version 6.2.4 when the databases {\tt core}, {\tt arith}, and so on were introduced. The purpose of the database {\tt v62} is to ensure compatibility with further versions of {\Coq} for developments done in versions prior to 6.2.4 ({\tt auto} being replaced by {\tt auto with v62}). The database {\tt v62} is intended not to be extended (!). It is not included in the hint databases list used in the {\tt auto with *} tactic. Furthermore, you are advised not to put your own hints in the {\tt core} database, but use one or several databases specific to your development. \subsection{\tt Remove Hints \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$ :~ \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$} \label{RemoveHints} \comindex{Remove Hints} This command removes the hints associated to terms \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$ in databases \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$. \subsection{\tt Print Hint} \label{PrintHint} \comindex{Print Hint} This command displays all hints that apply to the current goal. It fails if no proof is being edited, while the two variants can be used at every moment. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Print Hint \ident} This command displays only tactics associated with \ident\ in the hints list. This is independent of the goal being edited, so this command will not fail if no goal is being edited. \item {\tt Print Hint *} This command displays all declared hints. \item {\tt Print HintDb \ident} \label{PrintHintDb} \comindex{Print HintDb} This command displays all hints from database \ident. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt Hint Rewrite \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$ :~ \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$} \label{HintRewrite} \comindex{Hint Rewrite} This vernacular command adds the terms {\tt \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$} (their types must be equalities) in the rewriting bases \ident$_1$, \dots, \ident$_m$ with the default orientation (left to right). Notice that the rewriting bases are distinct from the {\tt auto} hint bases and that {\tt auto} does not take them into account. This command is synchronous with the section mechanism (see \ref{Section}): when closing a section, all aliases created by \texttt{Hint Rewrite} in that section are lost. Conversely, when loading a module, all \texttt{Hint Rewrite} declarations at the global level of that module are loaded. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Hint Rewrite -> \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$ :~\ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$} This is strictly equivalent to the command above (we only make explicit the orientation which otherwise defaults to {\tt ->}). \item {\tt Hint Rewrite <- \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$ :~\ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$} Adds the rewriting rules {\tt \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$} with a right-to-left orientation in the bases \ident$_1$, \dots, \ident$_m$. \item {\tt Hint Rewrite \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$ using {\tac} :~\ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_m$} When the rewriting rules {\tt \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$} in \ident$_1$, \dots, \ident$_m$ will be used, the tactic {\tt \tac} will be applied to the generated subgoals, the main subgoal excluded. %% \item %% {\tt Hint Rewrite [ \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ ] in \ident}\\ %% {\tt Hint Rewrite [ \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ ] in {\ident} using {\tac}}\\ %% These are deprecated syntactic variants for %% {\tt Hint Rewrite \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ : \ident} and %% {\tt Hint Rewrite \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ using {\tac} : {\ident}}. \item \texttt{Print Rewrite HintDb {\ident}} This command displays all rewrite hints contained in {\ident}. \end{Variants} \subsection{Hint locality \label{Hint-Locality}} \optindex{Loose Hint Behavior} Hints provided by the \texttt{Hint} commands are erased when closing a section. Conversely, all hints of a module \texttt{A} that are not defined inside a section (and not defined with option {\tt Local}) become available when the module {\tt A} is imported (using e.g. \texttt{Require Import A.}). As of today, hints only have a binary behavior regarding locality, as described above: either they disappear at the end of a section scope, or they remain global forever. This causes a scalability issue, because hints coming from an unrelated part of the code may badly influence another development. It can be mitigated to some extent thanks to the {\tt Remove Hints} command (see ~\ref{RemoveHints}), but this is a mere workaround and has some limitations (for instance, external hints cannot be removed). A proper way to fix this issue is to bind the hints to their module scope, as for most of the other objects Coq uses. Hints should only made available when the module they are defined in is imported, not just required. It is very difficult to change the historical behavior, as it would break a lot of scripts. We propose a smooth transitional path by providing the {\tt Loose Hint Behavior} option which accepts three flags allowing for a fine-grained handling of non-imported hints. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Set Loose Hint Behavior "Lax"} This is the default, and corresponds to the historical behavior, that is, hints defined outside of a section have a global scope. \item {\tt Set Loose Hint Behavior "Warn"} When set, it outputs a warning when a non-imported hint is used. Note that this is an over-approximation, because a hint may be triggered by a run that will eventually fail and backtrack, resulting in the hint not being actually useful for the proof. \item {\tt Set Loose Hint Behavior "Strict"} When set, it changes the behavior of an unloaded hint to a immediate fail tactic, allowing to emulate an import-scoped hint mechanism. \end{Variants} \subsection{Setting implicit automation tactics} \subsubsection{\tt Proof with {\tac}} \label{ProofWith} \comindex{Proof with} This command may be used to start a proof. It defines a default tactic to be used each time a tactic command {\tac$_1$} is ended by ``\verb#...#''. In this case the tactic command typed by the user is equivalent to \tac$_1$;{\tac}. \SeeAlso {\tt Proof.} in Section~\ref{BeginProof}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Proof with {\tac} using \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$} Combines in a single line {\tt Proof with} and {\tt Proof using}, see~\ref{ProofUsing} \item {\tt Proof using \ident$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \ident$_n$ with {\tac}} Combines in a single line {\tt Proof with} and {\tt Proof using}, see~\ref{ProofUsing} \end{Variants} \subsubsection{\tt Declare Implicit Tactic {\tac}}\label{DeclareImplicit} \comindex{Declare Implicit Tactic} This command declares a tactic to be used to solve implicit arguments that {\Coq} does not know how to solve by unification. It is used every time the term argument of a tactic has one of its holes not fully resolved. Here is an example: \begin{coq_example} Parameter quo : nat -> forall n:nat, n<>0 -> nat. Notation "x // y" := (quo x y _) (at level 40). Declare Implicit Tactic assumption. Goal forall n m, m<>0 -> { q:nat & { r | q * m + r = n } }. intros. exists (n // m). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Clear Implicit Tactic. Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} The tactic {\tt exists (n // m)} did not fail. The hole was solved by {\tt assumption} so that it behaved as {\tt exists (quo n m H)}. \section{Decision procedures} \subsection{\tt tauto} \tacindex{tauto} \tacindex{dtauto} \label{tauto} This tactic implements a decision procedure for intuitionistic propositional calculus based on the contraction-free sequent calculi LJT* of Roy Dyckhoff \cite{Dyc92}. Note that {\tt tauto} succeeds on any instance of an intuitionistic tautological proposition. {\tt tauto} unfolds negations and logical equivalence but does not unfold any other definition. The following goal can be proved by {\tt tauto} whereas {\tt auto} would fail: \begin{coq_example} Goal forall (x:nat) (P:nat -> Prop), x = 0 \/ P x -> x <> 0 -> P x. intros. tauto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} Moreover, if it has nothing else to do, {\tt tauto} performs introductions. Therefore, the use of {\tt intros} in the previous proof is unnecessary. {\tt tauto} can for instance prove the following: \begin{coq_example} (* auto would fail *) Goal forall (A:Prop) (P:nat -> Prop), A \/ (forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x) -> forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x. tauto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \Rem In contrast, {\tt tauto} cannot solve the following goal \begin{coq_example*} Goal forall (A:Prop) (P:nat -> Prop), A \/ (forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x) -> forall x:nat, ~ ~ (A \/ P x). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} because \verb=(forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x)= cannot be treated as atomic and an instantiation of \verb=x= is necessary. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt dtauto} While {\tt tauto} recognizes inductively defined connectives isomorphic to the standard connective {\tt and}, {\tt prod}, {\tt or}, {\tt sum}, {\tt False}, {\tt Empty\_set}, {\tt unit}, {\tt True}, {\tt dtauto} recognizes also all inductive types with one constructors and no indices, i.e. record-style connectives. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt intuition \tac} \tacindex{intuition} \tacindex{dintuition} \label{intuition} The tactic \texttt{intuition} takes advantage of the search-tree built by the decision procedure involved in the tactic {\tt tauto}. It uses this information to generate a set of subgoals equivalent to the original one (but simpler than it) and applies the tactic {\tac} to them \cite{Mun94}. If this tactic fails on some goals then {\tt intuition} fails. In fact, {\tt tauto} is simply {\tt intuition fail}. For instance, the tactic {\tt intuition auto} applied to the goal \begin{verbatim} (forall (x:nat), P x)/\B -> (forall (y:nat),P y)/\ P O \/B/\ P O \end{verbatim} internally replaces it by the equivalent one: \begin{verbatim} (forall (x:nat), P x), B |- P O \end{verbatim} and then uses {\tt auto} which completes the proof. Originally due to C{\'e}sar~Mu{\~n}oz, these tactics ({\tt tauto} and {\tt intuition}) have been completely re-engineered by David~Delahaye using mainly the tactic language (see Chapter~\ref{TacticLanguage}). The code is now much shorter and a significant increase in performance has been noticed. The general behavior with respect to dependent types, unfolding and introductions has slightly changed to get clearer semantics. This may lead to some incompatibilities. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt intuition} Is equivalent to {\tt intuition auto with *}. \item {\tt dintuition} While {\tt intuition} recognizes inductively defined connectives isomorphic to the standard connective {\tt and}, {\tt prod}, {\tt or}, {\tt sum}, {\tt False}, {\tt Empty\_set}, {\tt unit}, {\tt True}, {\tt dintuition} recognizes also all inductive types with one constructors and no indices, i.e. record-style connectives. \end{Variants} \optindex{Intuition Negation Unfolding} \optindex{Intuition Iff Unfolding} Some aspects of the tactic {\tt intuition} can be controlled using options. To avoid that inner negations which do not need to be unfolded are unfolded, use: \begin{quote} {\tt Unset Intuition Negation Unfolding} \end{quote} To do that all negations of the goal are unfolded even inner ones (this is the default), use: \begin{quote} {\tt Set Intuition Negation Unfolding} \end{quote} To avoid that inner occurrence of {\tt iff} which do not need to be unfolded are unfolded (this is the default), use: \begin{quote} {\tt Unset Intuition Iff Unfolding} \end{quote} To do that all negations of the goal are unfolded even inner ones (this is the default), use: \begin{quote} {\tt Set Intuition Iff Unfolding} \end{quote} % En attente d'un moyen de valoriser les fichiers de demos %\SeeAlso file \texttt{contrib/Rocq/DEMOS/Demo\_tauto.v} \subsection{\tt rtauto} \tacindex{rtauto} \label{rtauto} The {\tt rtauto} tactic solves propositional tautologies similarly to what {\tt tauto} does. The main difference is that the proof term is built using a reflection scheme applied to a sequent calculus proof of the goal. The search procedure is also implemented using a different technique. Users should be aware that this difference may result in faster proof-search but slower proof-checking, and {\tt rtauto} might not solve goals that {\tt tauto} would be able to solve (e.g. goals involving universal quantifiers). \subsection{\tt firstorder} \tacindex{firstorder} \label{firstorder} The tactic \texttt{firstorder} is an {\it experimental} extension of \texttt{tauto} to first-order reasoning, written by Pierre Corbineau. It is not restricted to usual logical connectives but instead may reason about any first-order class inductive definition. The default tactic used by \texttt{firstorder} when no rule applies is {\tt auto with *}, it can be reset locally or globally using the {\nobreak {\tt Set Firstorder Solver {\tac}}} \optindex{Firstorder Solver} vernacular command and printed using {\nobreak {\tt Print Firstorder Solver}}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt firstorder {\tac}} \tacindex{firstorder {\tac}} Tries to solve the goal with {\tac} when no logical rule may apply. \item {\tt firstorder with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ } \tacindex{firstorder with} Adds lemmas \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ to the proof-search environment. \item {\tt firstorder using {\qualid}$_1$ , \dots\ , {\qualid}$_n$ } \tacindex{firstorder using} Adds lemmas in {\tt auto} hints bases {\qualid}$_1$ \dots\ {\qualid}$_n$ to the proof-search environment. If {\qualid}$_i$ refers to an inductive type, it is the collection of its constructors which is added as hints. \item \texttt{firstorder using {\qualid}$_1$ , \dots\ , {\qualid}$_n$ with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} This combines the effects of the {\tt using} and {\tt with} options. \end{Variants} Proof-search is bounded by a depth parameter which can be set by typing the {\nobreak \tt Set Firstorder Depth $n$} \optindex{Firstorder Depth} vernacular command. \subsection{\tt congruence} \tacindex{congruence} \label{congruence} The tactic {\tt congruence}, by Pierre Corbineau, implements the standard Nelson and Oppen congruence closure algorithm, which is a decision procedure for ground equalities with uninterpreted symbols. It also include the constructor theory (see \ref{injection} and \ref{discriminate}). If the goal is a non-quantified equality, {\tt congruence} tries to prove it with non-quantified equalities in the context. Otherwise it tries to infer a discriminable equality from those in the context. Alternatively, congruence tries to prove that a hypothesis is equal to the goal or to the negation of another hypothesis. {\tt congruence} is also able to take advantage of hypotheses stating quantified equalities, you have to provide a bound for the number of extra equalities generated that way. Please note that one of the members of the equality must contain all the quantified variables in order for {\tt congruence} to match against it. \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Variable A:Set. Variables a b:A. Variable f:A->A. Variable g:A->A->A. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Theorem T: a=(f a) -> (g b (f a))=(f (f a)) -> (g a b)=(f (g b a)) -> (g a b)=a. intros. congruence. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Variable A:Set. Variables a c d:A. Variable f:A->A*A. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Theorem inj : f = pair a -> Some (f c) = Some (f d) -> c=d. intros. congruence. \end{coq_example} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt congruence {\sl n}} Tries to add at most {\tt \sl n} instances of hypotheses stating quantified equalities to the problem in order to solve it. A bigger value of {\tt \sl n} does not make success slower, only failure. You might consider adding some lemmas as hypotheses using {\tt assert} in order for congruence to use them. \item {\tt congruence with \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$} Adds {\tt \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$} to the pool of terms used by {\tt congruence}. This helps in case you have partially applied constructors in your goal. \end{Variants} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{I don't know how to handle dependent equality} The decision procedure managed to find a proof of the goal or of a discriminable equality but this proof could not be built in {\Coq} because of dependently-typed functions. \item \errindex{Goal is solvable by congruence but some arguments are missing. Try "congruence with \dots", replacing metavariables by arbitrary terms.} The decision procedure could solve the goal with the provision that additional arguments are supplied for some partially applied constructors. Any term of an appropriate type will allow the tactic to successfully solve the goal. Those additional arguments can be given to {\tt congruence} by filling in the holes in the terms given in the error message, using the {\tt with} variant described above. \end{ErrMsgs} \section{Everything after this point has yet to be sorted} \subsection{\tt constr\_eq \term$_1$ \term$_2$} \tacindex{constr\_eq} \label{constreq} This tactic applies to any goal. It checks whether its arguments are equal modulo alpha conversion and casts. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not equal} \subsection{\tt unify \term$_1$ \term$_2$} \tacindex{unify} \label{unify} This tactic applies to any goal. It checks whether its arguments are unifiable, potentially instantiating existential variables. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not unifiable} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt unify \term$_1$ \term$_2$ with \ident} Unification takes the transparency information defined in the hint database {\tt \ident} into account (see Section~\ref{HintTransparency}). \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt is\_evar \term} \tacindex{is\_evar} \label{isevar} This tactic applies to any goal. It checks whether its argument is an existential variable. Existential variables are uninstantiated variables generated by e.g. {\tt eapply} (see Section~\ref{apply}). \ErrMsg \errindex{Not an evar} \subsection{\tt has\_evar \term} \tacindex{has\_evar} \label{hasevar} This tactic applies to any goal. It checks whether its argument has an existential variable as a subterm. Unlike {\tt context} patterns combined with {\tt is\_evar}, this tactic scans all subterms, including those under binders. \ErrMsg \errindex{No evars} \subsection{\tt is\_var \term} \tacindex{is\_var} \label{isvar} This tactic applies to any goal. It checks whether its argument is a variable or hypothesis in the current goal context or in the opened sections. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not a variable or hypothesis} \section{Equality} \subsection{\tt f\_equal} \label{f-equal} \tacindex{f\_equal} This tactic applies to a goal of the form $f\ a_1\ \ldots\ a_n = f'\ a'_1\ \ldots\ a'_n$. Using {\tt f\_equal} on such a goal leads to subgoals $f=f'$ and $a_1=a'_1$ and so on up to $a_n=a'_n$. Amongst these subgoals, the simple ones (e.g. provable by reflexivity or congruence) are automatically solved by {\tt f\_equal}. \subsection{\tt reflexivity} \label{reflexivity} \tacindex{reflexivity} This tactic applies to a goal that has the form {\tt t=u}. It checks that {\tt t} and {\tt u} are convertible and then solves the goal. It is equivalent to {\tt apply refl\_equal}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{The conclusion is not a substitutive equation} \item \errindex{Impossible to unify \dots\ with \dots} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt symmetry} \tacindex{symmetry} This tactic applies to a goal that has the form {\tt t=u} and changes it into {\tt u=t}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt symmetry in \ident} \tacindex{symmetry in} If the statement of the hypothesis {\ident} has the form {\tt t=u}, the tactic changes it to {\tt u=t}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt transitivity \term} \tacindex{transitivity} This tactic applies to a goal that has the form {\tt t=u} and transforms it into the two subgoals {\tt t={\term}} and {\tt {\term}=u}. \section{Equality and inductive sets} We describe in this section some special purpose tactics dealing with equality and inductive sets or types. These tactics use the equality {\tt eq:forall (A:Type), A->A->Prop}, simply written with the infix symbol {\tt =}. \subsection{\tt decide equality} \label{decideequality} \tacindex{decide equality} This tactic solves a goal of the form {\tt forall $x$ $y$:$R$, \{$x$=$y$\}+\{\verb|~|$x$=$y$\}}, where $R$ is an inductive type such that its constructors do not take proofs or functions as arguments, nor objects in dependent types. It solves goals of the form {\tt \{$x$=$y$\}+\{\verb|~|$x$=$y$\}} as well. \subsection{\tt compare \term$_1$ \term$_2$} \tacindex{compare} This tactic compares two given objects \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ of an inductive datatype. If $G$ is the current goal, it leaves the sub-goals \term$_1${\tt =}\term$_2$ {\tt ->} $G$ and \verb|~|\term$_1${\tt =}\term$_2$ {\tt ->} $G$. The type of \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ must satisfy the same restrictions as in the tactic \texttt{decide equality}. \subsection{\tt simplify\_eq \term} \tacindex{simplify\_eq} \tacindex{esimplify\_eq} \label{simplify-eq} Let {\term} be the proof of a statement of conclusion {\tt {\term$_1$}={\term$_2$}}. If {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} are structurally different (in the sense described for the tactic {\tt discriminate}), then the tactic {\tt simplify\_eq} behaves as {\tt discriminate {\term}}, otherwise it behaves as {\tt injection {\term}}. \Rem If some quantified hypothesis of the goal is named {\ident}, then {\tt simplify\_eq {\ident}} first introduces the hypothesis in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{simplify\_eq} \num This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} then \texttt{simplify\_eq \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item \texttt{simplify\_eq} \term{} {\tt with} {\bindinglist} This does the same as \texttt{simplify\_eq {\term}} but using the given bindings to instantiate parameters or hypotheses of {\term}. \item \texttt{esimplify\_eq} \num\\ \texttt{esimplify\_eq} \term{} \zeroone{{\tt with} {\bindinglist}} This works the same as {\tt simplify\_eq} but if the type of {\term}, or the type of the hypothesis referred to by {\num}, has uninstantiated parameters, these parameters are left as existential variables. \item{\tt simplify\_eq} If the current goal has form $t_1\verb=<>=t_2$, it behaves as \texttt{intro {\ident}; simplify\_eq {\ident}}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt dependent rewrite -> \ident} \tacindex{dependent rewrite ->} \label{dependent-rewrite} This tactic applies to any goal. If \ident\ has type \verb+(existT B a b)=(existT B a' b')+ in the local context (i.e. each term of the equality has a sigma type $\{ a:A~ \&~(B~a)\}$) this tactic rewrites \verb+a+ into \verb+a'+ and \verb+b+ into \verb+b'+ in the current goal. This tactic works even if $B$ is also a sigma type. This kind of equalities between dependent pairs may be derived by the injection and inversion tactics. \begin{Variants} \item{\tt dependent rewrite <- {\ident}} \tacindex{dependent rewrite <-} Analogous to {\tt dependent rewrite ->} but uses the equality from right to left. \end{Variants} \section{Inversion \label{inversion}} \subsection{\tt functional inversion \ident} \tacindex{functional inversion} \label{sec:functional-inversion} \texttt{functional inversion} is a tactic that performs inversion on hypothesis {\ident} of the form \texttt{\qualid\ \term$_1$\dots\term$_n$\ = \term} or \texttt{\term\ = \qualid\ \term$_1$\dots\term$_n$} where \qualid\ must have been defined using \texttt{Function} (see Section~\ref{Function}). \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Hypothesis {\ident} must contain at least one Function} \item \errindex{Cannot find inversion information for hypothesis \ident} This error may be raised when some inversion lemma failed to be generated by Function. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt functional inversion \num} This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} then \texttt{functional inversion \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item {\tt functional inversion \ident\ \qualid}\\ {\tt functional inversion \num\ \qualid} If the hypothesis {\ident} (or {\num}) has a type of the form \texttt{\qualid$_1$\ \term$_1$\dots\term$_n$\ =\ \qualid$_2$\ \term$_{n+1}$\dots\term$_{n+m}$} where \qualid$_1$ and \qualid$_2$ are valid candidates to functional inversion, this variant allows choosing which {\qualid} is inverted. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt quote \ident} \tacindex{quote} \index{2-level approach} This kind of inversion has nothing to do with the tactic \texttt{inversion} above. This tactic does \texttt{change (\ident\ t)}, where \texttt{t} is a term built in order to ensure the convertibility. In other words, it does inversion of the function \ident. This function must be a fixpoint on a simple recursive datatype: see~\ref{quote-examples} for the full details. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{quote: not a simple fixpoint} Happens when \texttt{quote} is not able to perform inversion properly. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{quote {\ident} [ \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$ ]} All terms that are built only with \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$ will be considered by \texttt{quote} as constants rather than variables. \end{Variants} % En attente d'un moyen de valoriser les fichiers de demos % \SeeAlso file \texttt{theories/DEMOS/DemoQuote.v} in the distribution \section{Classical tactics} \label{ClassicalTactics} In order to ease the proving process, when the {\tt Classical} module is loaded. A few more tactics are available. Make sure to load the module using the \texttt{Require Import} command. \subsection{{\tt classical\_left} and \tt classical\_right} \tacindex{classical\_left} \tacindex{classical\_right} The tactics \texttt{classical\_left} and \texttt{classical\_right} are the analog of the \texttt{left} and \texttt{right} but using classical logic. They can only be used for disjunctions. Use \texttt{classical\_left} to prove the left part of the disjunction with the assumption that the negation of right part holds. Use \texttt{classical\_right} to prove the right part of the disjunction with the assumption that the negation of left part holds. \section{Automatizing \label{Automatizing}} % EXISTE ENCORE ? % % \subsection{\tt Prolog [ \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$ ] \num} % \tacindex{Prolog}\label{Prolog} % This tactic, implemented by Chet Murthy, is based upon the concept of % existential variables of Gilles Dowek, stating that resolution is a % kind of unification. It tries to solve the current goal using the {\tt % Assumption} tactic, the {\tt intro} tactic, and applying hypotheses % of the local context and terms of the given list {\tt [ \term$_1$ % \dots\ \term$_n$\ ]}. It is more powerful than {\tt auto} since it % may apply to any theorem, even those of the form {\tt (x:A)(P x) -> Q} % where {\tt x} does not appear free in {\tt Q}. The maximal search % depth is {\tt \num}. % \begin{ErrMsgs} % \item \errindex{Prolog failed}\\ % The Prolog tactic was not able to prove the subgoal. % \end{ErrMsgs} %% \subsection{{\tt jp} {\em (Jprover)} %% \tacindex{jp} %% \label{jprover}} %% The tactic \texttt{jp}, due to Huang Guan-Shieng, is an experimental %% port of the {\em Jprover}\cite{SLKN01} semi-decision procedure for %% first-order intuitionistic logic implemented in {\em %% NuPRL}\cite{Kre02}. %% The tactic \texttt{jp}, due to Huang Guan-Shieng, is an {\it %% experimental} port of the {\em Jprover}\cite{SLKN01} semi-decision %% procedure for first-order intuitionistic logic implemented in {\em %% NuPRL}\cite{Kre02}. %% Search may optionally be bounded by a multiplicity parameter %% indicating how many (at most) copies of a formula may be used in %% the proof process, its absence may lead to non-termination of the tactic. %% %\begin{coq_eval} %% %Variable S:Set. %% %Variables P Q:S->Prop. %% %Variable f:S->S. %% %\end{coq_eval} %% %\begin{coq_example*} %% %Lemma example: (exists x |P x\/Q x)->(exists x |P x)\/(exists x |Q x). %% %jp. %% %Qed. %% %Lemma example2: (forall x ,P x->P (f x))->forall x,P x->P (f(f x)). %% %jp. %% %Qed. %% %\end{coq_example*} %% \begin{Variants} %% \item {\tt jp $n$}\\ %% \tacindex{jp $n$} %% Tries the {\em Jprover} procedure with multiplicities up to $n$, %% starting from 1. %% \item {\tt jp}\\ %% Tries the {\em Jprover} procedure without multiplicity bound, %% possibly running forever. %% \end{Variants} %% \begin{ErrMsgs} %% \item \errindex{multiplicity limit reached}\\ %% The procedure tried all multiplicities below the limit and %% failed. Goal might be solved by increasing the multiplicity limit. %% \item \errindex{formula is not provable}\\ %% The procedure determined that goal was not provable in %% intuitionistic first-order logic, no matter how big the %% multiplicity is. %% \end{ErrMsgs} % \subsection[\tt Linear]{\tt Linear\tacindex{Linear}\label{Linear}} % The tactic \texttt{Linear}, due to Jean-Christophe Filli{\^a}atre % \cite{Fil94}, implements a decision procedure for {\em Direct % Predicate Calculus}, that is first-order Gentzen's Sequent Calculus % without contraction rules \cite{KeWe84,BeKe92}. Intuitively, a % first-order goal is provable in Direct Predicate Calculus if it can be % proved using each hypothesis at most once. % Unlike the previous tactics, the \texttt{Linear} tactic does not belong % to the initial state of the system, and it must be loaded explicitly % with the command % \begin{coq_example*} % Require Linear. % \end{coq_example*} % For instance, assuming that \texttt{even} and \texttt{odd} are two % predicates on natural numbers, and \texttt{a} of type \texttt{nat}, the % tactic \texttt{Linear} solves the following goal % \begin{coq_eval} % Variables even,odd : nat -> Prop. % Variable a:nat. % \end{coq_eval} % \begin{coq_example*} % Lemma example : (even a) % -> ((x:nat)((even x)->(odd (S x)))) % -> (EX y | (odd y)). % \end{coq_example*} % You can find examples of the use of \texttt{Linear} in % \texttt{theories/DEMOS/DemoLinear.v}. % \begin{coq_eval} % Abort. % \end{coq_eval} % \begin{Variants} % \item {\tt Linear with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$}\\ % \tacindex{Linear with} % Is equivalent to apply first {\tt generalize \ident$_1$ \dots % \ident$_n$} (see Section~\ref{generalize}) then the \texttt{Linear} % tactic. So one can use axioms, lemmas or hypotheses of the local % context with \texttt{Linear} in this way. % \end{Variants} % \begin{ErrMsgs} % \item \errindex{Not provable in Direct Predicate Calculus} % \item \errindex{Found $n$ classical proof(s) but no intuitionistic one}\\ % The decision procedure looks actually for classical proofs of the % goals, and then checks that they are intuitionistic. In that case, % classical proofs have been found, which do not correspond to % intuitionistic ones. % \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt btauto} \tacindex{btauto} \label{btauto} The tactic \texttt{btauto} implements a reflexive solver for boolean tautologies. It solves goals of the form {\tt t = u} where {\tt t} and {\tt u} are constructed over the following grammar: $$\mathtt{t} ::= x \mid \mathtt{true} \mid \mathtt{false}\mid \mathtt{orb\ t_1\ t_2} \mid \mathtt{andb\ t_1\ t_2} \mid\mathtt{xorb\ t_1\ t_2} \mid\mathtt{negb\ t} \mid\mathtt{if\ t_1\ then\ t_2\ else\ t_3} $$ Whenever the formula supplied is not a tautology, it also provides a counter-example. Internally, it uses a system very similar to the one of the {\tt ring} tactic. \subsection{\tt omega} \tacindex{omega} \label{omega} The tactic \texttt{omega}, due to Pierre Cr{\'e}gut, is an automatic decision procedure for Presburger arithmetic. It solves quantifier-free formulas built with \verb|~|, \verb|\/|, \verb|/\|, \verb|->| on top of equalities, inequalities and disequalities on both the type \texttt{nat} of natural numbers and \texttt{Z} of binary integers. This tactic must be loaded by the command \texttt{Require Import Omega}. See the additional documentation about \texttt{omega} (see Chapter~\ref{OmegaChapter}). \subsection{{\tt ring} and \tt ring\_simplify \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$} \tacindex{ring} \tacindex{ring\_simplify} \comindex{Add Ring} \comindex{Print Rings} The {\tt ring} tactic solves equations upon polynomial expressions of a ring (or semi-ring) structure. It proceeds by normalizing both hand sides of the equation (w.r.t. associativity, commutativity and distributivity, constant propagation) and comparing syntactically the results. {\tt ring\_simplify} applies the normalization procedure described above to the terms given. The tactic then replaces all occurrences of the terms given in the conclusion of the goal by their normal forms. If no term is given, then the conclusion should be an equation and both hand sides are normalized. See Chapter~\ref{ring} for more information on the tactic and how to declare new ring structures. All declared field structures can be printed with the {\tt Print Rings} command. \subsection{{\tt field}, {\tt field\_simplify \term$_1$ \mbox{\dots} \term$_n$}, and \tt field\_simplify\_eq} \tacindex{field} \tacindex{field\_simplify} \tacindex{field\_simplify\_eq} \comindex{Add Field} \comindex{Print Fields} The {\tt field} tactic is built on the same ideas as {\tt ring}: this is a reflexive tactic that solves or simplifies equations in a field structure. The main idea is to reduce a field expression (which is an extension of ring expressions with the inverse and division operations) to a fraction made of two polynomial expressions. Tactic {\tt field} is used to solve subgoals, whereas {\tt field\_simplify \term$_1$\dots\term$_n$} replaces the provided terms by their reduced fraction. {\tt field\_simplify\_eq} applies when the conclusion is an equation: it simplifies both hand sides and multiplies so as to cancel denominators. So it produces an equation without division nor inverse. All of these 3 tactics may generate a subgoal in order to prove that denominators are different from zero. See Chapter~\ref{ring} for more information on the tactic and how to declare new field structures. All declared field structures can be printed with the {\tt Print Fields} command. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Require Import Reals. Goal forall x y:R, (x * y > 0)%R -> (x * (1 / x + x / (x + y)))%R = ((- 1 / y) * y * (- x * (x / (x + y)) - 1))%R. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} intros; field. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \SeeAlso file {\tt plugins/setoid\_ring/RealField.v} for an example of instantiation,\\ \phantom{\SeeAlso}theory {\tt theories/Reals} for many examples of use of {\tt field}. \subsection{\tt fourier} \tacindex{fourier} This tactic written by Lo{\"\i}c Pottier solves linear inequalities on real numbers using Fourier's method~\cite{Fourier}. This tactic must be loaded by {\tt Require Import Fourier}. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Require Import Reals. Require Import Fourier. Goal forall x y:R, (x < y)%R -> (y + 1 >= x - 1)%R. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} intros; fourier. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \section{Non-logical tactics} \subsection[\tt cycle \num]{\tt cycle \num\tacindex{cycle}} This tactic puts the {\num} first goals at the end of the list of goals. If {\num} is negative, it will put the last $\left|\num\right|$ goals at the beginning of the list. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Parameter P : nat -> Prop. Goal P 1 /\ P 2 /\ P 3 /\ P 4 /\ P 5. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} repeat split. all: cycle 2. all: cycle -3. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \subsection[\tt swap \num$_1$ \num$_2$]{\tt swap \num$_1$ \num$_2$\tacindex{swap}} This tactic switches the position of the goals of indices $\num_1$ and $\num_2$. If either $\num_1$ or $\num_2$ is negative then goals are counted from the end of the focused goal list. Goals are indexed from $1$, there is no goal with position $0$. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Parameter P : nat -> Prop. Goal P 1 /\ P 2 /\ P 3 /\ P 4 /\ P 5. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} repeat split. all: swap 1 3. all: swap 1 -1. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \subsection[\tt revgoals]{\tt revgoals\tacindex{revgoals}} This tactics reverses the list of the focused goals. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Parameter P : nat -> Prop. Goal P 1 /\ P 2 /\ P 3 /\ P 4 /\ P 5. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} repeat split. all: revgoals. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \subsection[\tt shelve]{\tt shelve\tacindex{shelve}\label{shelve}} This tactic moves all goals under focus to a shelf. While on the shelf, goals will not be focused on. They can be solved by unification, or they can be called back into focus with the command {\tt Unshelve} (Section~\ref{unshelve}). \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{shelve\_unifiable}\tacindex{shelve\_unifiable} Shelves only the goals under focus that are mentioned in other goals. Goals that appear in the type of other goals can be solved by unification. \Example \begin{coq_example} Goal exists n, n=0. refine (ex_intro _ _ _). all:shelve_unifiable. reflexivity. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \end{Variants} \subsection[\tt Unshelve]{\tt Unshelve\comindex{Unshelve}\label{unshelve}} This command moves all the goals on the shelf (see Section~\ref{shelve}) from the shelf into focus, by appending them to the end of the current list of focused goals. \subsection[\tt give\_up]{\tt give\_up\tacindex{give\_up}} This tactic removes the focused goals from the proof. They are not solved, and cannot be solved later in the proof. As the goals are not solved, the proof cannot be closed. The {\tt give\_up} tactic can be used while editing a proof, to choose to write the proof script in a non-sequential order. \section{Simple tactic macros} \index{Tactic macros} \label{TacticDefinition} A simple example has more value than a long explanation: \begin{coq_example} Ltac Solve := simpl; intros; auto. Ltac ElimBoolRewrite b H1 H2 := elim b; [ intros; rewrite H1; eauto | intros; rewrite H2; eauto ]. \end{coq_example} The tactics macros are synchronous with the \Coq\ section mechanism: a tactic definition is deleted from the current environment when you close the section (see also \ref{Section}) where it was defined. If you want that a tactic macro defined in a module is usable in the modules that require it, you should put it outside of any section. Chapter~\ref{TacticLanguage} gives examples of more complex user-defined tactics. %%% Local Variables: %%% mode: latex %%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual" %%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual" %%% End: