\achapter{Micromega: tactics for solving arithmetic goals over ordered rings} %HEVEA\cutname{micromega.html} \aauthor{Frédéric Besson and Evgeny Makarov} \newtheorem{theorem}{Theorem} \asection{Short description of the tactics} \tacindex{psatz} \tacindex{lra} \tacindex{lia} \tacindex{nia} \tacindex{nra} \label{sec:psatz-hurry} The {\tt Psatz} module ({\tt Require Import Psatz.}) gives access to several tactics for solving arithmetic goals over {\tt Z}, {\tt Q}, and {\tt R}:\footnote{Support for {\tt nat} and {\tt N} is obtained by pre-processing the goal with the {\tt zify} tactic.}. It also possible to get the tactics for integers by a {\tt Require Import Lia}, rationals {\tt Require Import Lqa} and reals {\tt Require Import Lra}. \begin{itemize} \item {\tt lia} is a decision procedure for linear integer arithmetic (see Section~\ref{sec:lia}); \item {\tt nia} is an incomplete proof procedure for integer non-linear arithmetic (see Section~\ref{sec:nia}); \item {\tt lra} is a decision procedure for linear (real or rational) arithmetic (see Section~\ref{sec:lra}); \item {\tt nra} is an incomplete proof procedure for non-linear (real or rational) arithmetic (see Section~\ref{sec:nra}); \item {\tt psatz D n} where {\tt D} is {\tt Z} or {\tt Q} or {\tt R}, and {\tt n} is an optional integer limiting the proof search depth is is an incomplete proof procedure for non-linear arithmetic. It is based on John Harrison's HOL Light driver to the external prover {\tt csdp}\footnote{Sources and binaries can be found at \url{https://projects.coin-or.org/Csdp}}. Note that the {\tt csdp} driver is generating a \emph{proof cache} which makes it possible to rerun scripts even without {\tt csdp} (see Section~\ref{sec:psatz}). \end{itemize} The tactics solve propositional formulas parameterized by atomic arithmetic expressions interpreted over a domain $D \in \{\mathbb{Z}, \mathbb{Q}, \mathbb{R} \}$. The syntax of the formulas is the following: \[ \begin{array}{lcl} F &::=& A \mid P \mid \mathit{True} \mid \mathit{False} \mid F_1 \land F_2 \mid F_1 \lor F_2 \mid F_1 \leftrightarrow F_2 \mid F_1 \to F_2 \mid \neg F\\ A &::=& p_1 = p_2 \mid p_1 > p_2 \mid p_1 < p_2 \mid p_1 \ge p_2 \mid p_1 \le p_2 \\ p &::=& c \mid x \mid {-}p \mid p_1 - p_2 \mid p_1 + p_2 \mid p_1 \times p_2 \mid p \verb!^! n \end{array} \] where $c$ is a numeric constant, $x\in D$ is a numeric variable, the operators $-$, $+$, $\times$ are respectively subtraction, addition, product, $p \verb!^!n $ is exponentiation by a constant $n$, $P$ is an arbitrary proposition. % For {\tt Q}, equality is not Leibniz equality {\tt =} but the equality of rationals {\tt ==}. For {\tt Z} (resp. {\tt Q} ), $c$ ranges over integer constants (resp. rational constants). %% The following table details for each domain $D \in \{\mathbb{Z},\mathbb{Q},\mathbb{R}\}$ the range of constants $c$ and exponent $n$. %% \[ %% \begin{array}{|c|c|c|c|} %% \hline %% &\mathbb{Z} & \mathbb{Q} & \mathbb{R} \\ %% \hline %% c &\mathtt{Z} & \mathtt{Q} & (see below) \\ %% \hline %% n &\mathtt{Z} & \mathtt{Z} & \mathtt{nat}\\ %% \hline %% \end{array} %% \] For {\tt R}, the tactic recognizes as real constants the following expressions: \begin{verbatim} c ::= R0 | R1 | Rmul(c,c) | Rplus(c,c) | Rminus(c,c) | IZR z | IQR q | Rdiv(c,c) | Rinv c \end{verbatim} where {\tt z} is a constant in {\tt Z} and {\tt q} is a constant in {\tt Q}. This includes integer constants written using the decimal notation \emph{i.e.,} {\tt c\%R}. \asection{\emph{Positivstellensatz} refutations} \label{sec:psatz-back} The name {\tt psatz} is an abbreviation for \emph{positivstellensatz} -- literally positivity theorem -- which generalizes Hilbert's \emph{nullstellensatz}. % It relies on the notion of $\mathit{Cone}$. Given a (finite) set of polynomials $S$, $\mathit{Cone}(S)$ is inductively defined as the smallest set of polynomials closed under the following rules: \[ \begin{array}{l} \dfrac{p \in S}{p \in \mathit{Cone}(S)} \quad \dfrac{}{p^2 \in \mathit{Cone}(S)} \quad \dfrac{p_1 \in \mathit{Cone}(S) \quad p_2 \in \mathit{Cone}(S) \quad \Join \in \{+,*\}} {p_1 \Join p_2 \in \mathit{Cone}(S)}\\ \end{array} \] The following theorem provides a proof principle for checking that a set of polynomial inequalities does not have solutions.\footnote{Variants deal with equalities and strict inequalities.} \begin{theorem} \label{thm:psatz} Let $S$ be a set of polynomials.\\ If ${-}1$ belongs to $\mathit{Cone}(S)$ then the conjunction $\bigwedge_{p \in S} p\ge 0$ is unsatisfiable. \end{theorem} A proof based on this theorem is called a \emph{positivstellensatz} refutation. % The tactics work as follows. Formulas are normalized into conjunctive normal form $\bigwedge_i C_i$ where $C_i$ has the general form $(\bigwedge_{j\in S_i} p_j \Join 0) \to \mathit{False})$ and $\Join \in \{>,\ge,=\}$ for $D\in \{\mathbb{Q},\mathbb{R}\}$ and $\Join \in \{\ge, =\}$ for $\mathbb{Z}$. % For each conjunct $C_i$, the tactic calls a oracle which searches for $-1$ within the cone. % Upon success, the oracle returns a \emph{cone expression} that is normalized by the {\tt ring} tactic (see chapter~\ref{ring}) and checked to be $-1$. \asection{{\tt lra}: a decision procedure for linear real and rational arithmetic} \label{sec:lra} The {\tt lra} tactic is searching for \emph{linear} refutations using Fourier elimination.\footnote{More efficient linear programming techniques could equally be employed.} As a result, this tactic explores a subset of the $\mathit{Cone}$ defined as \[ \mathit{LinCone}(S) =\left\{ \left. \sum_{p \in S} \alpha_p \times p~\right| ~\alpha_p \mbox{ are positive constants} \right\}. \] The deductive power of {\tt lra} is the combined deductive power of {\tt ring\_simplify} and {\tt fourier}. % There is also an overlap with the {\tt field} tactic {\emph e.g.}, {\tt x = 10 * x / 10} is solved by {\tt lra}. \asection{{\tt lia}: a tactic for linear integer arithmetic} \tacindex{lia} \label{sec:lia} The tactic {\tt lia} offers an alternative to the {\tt omega} and {\tt romega} tactic (see Chapter~\ref{OmegaChapter}). % Roughly speaking, the deductive power of {\tt lia} is the combined deductive power of {\tt ring\_simplify} and {\tt omega}. % However, it solves linear goals that {\tt omega} and {\tt romega} do not solve, such as the following so-called \emph{omega nightmare}~\cite{TheOmegaPaper}. \begin{coq_example*} Goal forall x y, 27 <= 11 * x + 13 * y <= 45 -> -10 <= 7 * x - 9 * y <= 4 -> False. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} intros x y; lia. \end{coq_eval} The estimation of the relative efficiency of {\tt lia} \emph{vs} {\tt omega} and {\tt romega} is under evaluation. \paragraph{High level view of {\tt lia}.} Over $\mathbb{R}$, \emph{positivstellensatz} refutations are a complete proof principle.\footnote{In practice, the oracle might fail to produce such a refutation.} % However, this is not the case over $\mathbb{Z}$. % Actually, \emph{positivstellensatz} refutations are not even sufficient to decide linear \emph{integer} arithmetic. % The canonical example is {\tt 2 * x = 1 -> False} which is a theorem of $\mathbb{Z}$ but not a theorem of $\mathbb{R}$. % To remedy this weakness, the {\tt lia} tactic is using recursively a combination of: % \begin{itemize} \item linear \emph{positivstellensatz} refutations; \item cutting plane proofs; \item case split. \end{itemize} \paragraph{Cutting plane proofs} are a way to take into account the discreetness of $\mathbb{Z}$ by rounding up (rational) constants up-to the closest integer. % \begin{theorem} Let $p$ be an integer and $c$ a rational constant. \[ p \ge c \Rightarrow p \ge \lceil c \rceil \] \end{theorem} For instance, from $2 x = 1$ we can deduce \begin{itemize} \item $x \ge 1/2$ which cut plane is $ x \ge \lceil 1/2 \rceil = 1$; \item $ x \le 1/2$ which cut plane is $ x \le \lfloor 1/2 \rfloor = 0$. \end{itemize} By combining these two facts (in normal form) $x - 1 \ge 0$ and $-x \ge 0$, we conclude by exhibiting a \emph{positivstellensatz} refutation: $-1 \equiv \mathbf{x-1} + \mathbf{-x} \in \mathit{Cone}(\{x-1,x\})$. Cutting plane proofs and linear \emph{positivstellensatz} refutations are a complete proof principle for integer linear arithmetic. \paragraph{Case split} enumerates over the possible values of an expression. \begin{theorem} Let $p$ be an integer and $c_1$ and $c_2$ integer constants. \[ c_1 \le p \le c_2 \Rightarrow \bigvee_{x \in [c_1,c_2]} p = x \] \end{theorem} Our current oracle tries to find an expression $e$ with a small range $[c_1,c_2]$. % We generate $c_2 - c_1$ subgoals which contexts are enriched with an equation $e = i$ for $i \in [c_1,c_2]$ and recursively search for a proof. \asection{{\tt nra}: a proof procedure for non-linear arithmetic} \tacindex{nra} \label{sec:nra} The {\tt nra} tactic is an {\emph experimental} proof procedure for non-linear arithmetic. % The tactic performs a limited amount of non-linear reasoning before running the linear prover of {\tt lra}. This pre-processing does the following: \begin{itemize} \item If the context contains an arithmetic expression of the form $e[x^2]$ where $x$ is a monomial, the context is enriched with $x^2\ge 0$; \item For all pairs of hypotheses $e_1\ge 0$, $e_2 \ge 0$, the context is enriched with $e_1 \times e_2 \ge 0$. \end{itemize} After this pre-processing, the linear prover of {\tt lra} searches for a proof by abstracting monomials by variables. \asection{{\tt nia}: a proof procedure for non-linear integer arithmetic} \tacindex{nia} \label{sec:nia} The {\tt nia} tactic is a proof procedure for non-linear integer arithmetic. % It performs a pre-processing similar to {\tt nra}. The obtained goal is solved using the linear integer prover {\tt lia}. \asection{{\tt psatz}: a proof procedure for non-linear arithmetic} \label{sec:psatz} The {\tt psatz} tactic explores the $\mathit{Cone}$ by increasing degrees -- hence the depth parameter $n$. In theory, such a proof search is complete -- if the goal is provable the search eventually stops. Unfortunately, the external oracle is using numeric (approximate) optimization techniques that might miss a refutation. To illustrate the working of the tactic, consider we wish to prove the following Coq goal. \begin{coq_eval} Require Import ZArith Psatz. Open Scope Z_scope. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example*} Goal forall x, -x^2 >= 0 -> x - 1 >= 0 -> False. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} intro x; psatz Z 2. \end{coq_eval} Such a goal is solved by {\tt intro x; psatz Z 2}. The oracle returns the cone expression $2 \times (\mathbf{x-1}) + (\mathbf{x-1}) \times (\mathbf{x-1}) + \mathbf{-x^2}$ (polynomial hypotheses are printed in bold). By construction, this expression belongs to $\mathit{Cone}(\{-x^2, x -1\})$. Moreover, by running {\tt ring} we obtain $-1$. By Theorem~\ref{thm:psatz}, the goal is valid. % %% \paragraph{The {\tt sos} tactic} -- where {\tt sos} stands for \emph{sum of squares} -- tries to prove that a %% single polynomial $p$ is positive by expressing it as a sum of squares \emph{i.e.,} $\sum_{i\in S} p_i^2$. %% This amounts to searching for $p$ in the cone without generators \emph{i.e.}, $Cone(\{\})$. % %%% Local Variables: %%% mode: latex %%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual" %%% End: