\chapter{Tactics} \index{Tactics} \label{Tactics} A deduction rule is a link between some (unique) formula, that we call the {\em conclusion} and (several) formul{\ae} that we call the {\em premises}. Indeed, a deduction rule can be read in two ways. The first one has the shape: {\it ``if I know this and this then I can deduce this''}. For instance, if I have a proof of $A$ and a proof of $B$ then I have a proof of $A \land B$. This is forward reasoning from premises to conclusion. The other way says: {\it ``to prove this I have to prove this and this''}. For instance, to prove $A \land B$, I have to prove $A$ and I have to prove $B$. This is backward reasoning which proceeds from conclusion to premises. We say that the conclusion is {\em the goal}\index{goal} to prove and premises are {\em the subgoals}\index{subgoal}. The tactics implement {\em backward reasoning}. When applied to a goal, a tactic replaces this goal with the subgoals it generates. We say that a tactic reduces a goal to its subgoal(s). Each (sub)goal is denoted with a number. The current goal is numbered 1. By default, a tactic is applied to the current goal, but one can address a particular goal in the list by writing {\sl n:\tac} which means {\it ``apply tactic {\tac} to goal number {\sl n}''}. We can show the list of subgoals by typing {\tt Show} (see section \ref{Show}). Since not every rule applies to a given statement, every tactic cannot be used to reduce any goal. In other words, before applying a tactic to a given goal, the system checks that some {\em preconditions} are satisfied. If it is not the case, the tactic raises an error message. Tactics are build from atomic tactics and tactic expressions (which extends the folklore notion of tactical) to combine those atomic tactics. This chapter is devoted to atomic tactics. The tactic language will be described in chapter~\ref{TacticLanguage}. There are, at least, three levels of atomic tactics. The simplest one implements basic rules of the logical framework. The second level is the one of {\em derived rules} which are built by combination of other tactics. The third one implements heuristics or decision procedures to build a complete proof of a goal. \section{Invocation of tactics} \label{tactic-syntax} \index{tactic@{\tac}} A tactic is applied as an ordinary command. If the tactic does not address the first subgoal, the command may be preceded by the wished subgoal number as shown below: \begin{tabular}{lcl} {\commandtac} & ::= & {\num} {\tt :} {\tac} {\tt .}\\ & $|$ & {\tac} {\tt .} \end{tabular} \section{Explicit proof as a term} \subsection{\tt exact \term} \tacindex{exact} \label{exact} This tactic applies to any goal. It gives directly the exact proof term of the goal. Let {\T} be our goal, let {\tt p} be a term of type {\tt U} then {\tt exact p} succeeds iff {\tt T} and {\tt U} are convertible (see section \ref{conv-rules}). \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not an exact proof} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt refine \term} \tacindex{refine} \label{refine} \index{?@{\texttt{?}}} This tactic allows to give an exact proof but still with some holes. The holes are noted ``\texttt{\_}''. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{invalid argument}: the tactic \texttt{refine} doesn't know what to do with the term you gave. \item \texttt{Refine passed ill-formed term}: the term you gave is not a valid proof (not easy to debug in general). This message may also occur in higher-level tactics, which call \texttt{refine} internally. \item \errindex{There is an unknown subterm I cannot solve}: there is a hole in the term you gave which type cannot be inferred. Put a cast around it. \end{ErrMsgs} This tactic is currently given as an experiment. An example of use is given in section~\ref{refine-example}. \section{Basics} \index{Typing rules} Tactics presented in this section implement the basic typing rules of {\sc Cic} given in chapter \ref{Cic}. \subsection{{\tt assumption}} \tacindex{assumption} This tactic applies to any goal. It implements the ``Var''\index{Typing rules!Var} rule given in section \ref{Typed-terms}. It looks in the local context for an hypothesis which type is equal to the goal. If it is the case, the subgoal is proved. Otherwise, it fails. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such assumption} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt clear {\ident}}\tacindex{clear}\label{clear} This tactic erases the hypothesis named {\ident} in the local context of the current goal. Then {\ident} is no more displayed and no more usable in the proof development. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt clear {\ident$_1$} {\ldots} {\ident$_n$}.}\\ This is equivalent to {\tt clear {\ident$_1$}. {\ldots} clear {\ident$_n$}.} \item {\tt clearbody {\ident}.}\tacindex{clearbody}\\ This tactic expects {\ident} to be a local definition then clears its body. Otherwise said, this tactic turns a definition into an assumption. \end{Variants} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such assumption} \item \errindex{{\ident} is used in the conclusion} \item \errindex{{\ident} is used in the hypothesis {\ident'}} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt move {\ident$_1$} after {\ident$_2$}} \tacindex{Move} This moves the hypothesis named {\ident$_1$} in the local context after the hypothesis named {\ident$_2$}. If {\ident$_1$} comes before {\ident$_2$} in the order of dependences, then all hypotheses between {\ident$_1$} and {\ident$_2$} which (possibly indirectly) depend on {\ident$_1$} are moved also. If {\ident$_1$} comes after {\ident$_2$} in the order of dependences, then all hypotheses between {\ident$_1$} and {\ident$_2$} which (possibly indirectly) occur in {\ident$_1$} are moved also. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such assumption: {\ident$_i$}} \item \errindex{Cannot move {\ident$_1$} after {\ident$_2$}: it occurs in {\ident$_2$}} \item \errindex{Cannot move {\ident$_1$} after {\ident$_2$}: it depends on {\ident$_2$}} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt rename {\ident$_1$} into {\ident$_2$}} \tacindex{Rename} This renames hypothesis {\ident$_1$} into {\ident$_2$} in the current context\footnote{but it does not rename the hypothesis in the proof-term...} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such assumption} \item \errindex{{\ident$_2$} is already used} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt intro} \tacindex{intro} \label{intro} This tactic applies to a goal which is either a product or starts with a let binder. If the goal is a product, the tactic implements the ``Lam''\index{Typing rules!Lam} rule given in section \ref{Typed-terms}\footnote{Actually, only the second subgoal will be generated since the other one can be automatically checked.}. If the goal starts with a let binder then the tactic implements a mix of the ``Let''\index{Typing rules!Let} and ``Conv''\index{Typing rules!Conv}. If the current goal is a dependent product {\tt forall (x:T), U} (resp {\tt let x:=t in U}) then {\tt intro} puts {\tt x:T} (resp {\tt x:=t}) in the local context. % Obsolete (quantified names already avoid hypotheses names): % Otherwise, it puts % {\tt x}{\it n}{\tt :T} where {\it n} is such that {\tt x}{\it n} is a %fresh name. The new subgoal is {\tt U}. % If the {\tt x} has been renamed {\tt x}{\it n} then it is replaced % by {\tt x}{\it n} in {\tt U}. If the goal is a non dependent product T -> U, then it puts in the local context either {\tt H}{\it n}{\tt :T} (if {\tt T} is {\tt Set} or {\tt Prop}) or {\tt X}{\it n}{\tt :T} (if the type of {\tt T} is {\tt Type}) {\it n} is such that {\tt H}{\it n} or {\tt X}{\it n} {\tt l}{\it n} or are fresh identifiers. In both cases the new subgoal is {\tt U}. If the goal is neither a product nor starting with a let definition, the tactic {\tt intro} applies the tactic {\tt red} until the tactic {\tt intro} can be applied or the goal is not reducible. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No product even after head-reduction} \item \errindex{\texttt{{\ident} is already used}} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt intros}\tacindex{intros} Repeats {\tt intro} until it meets the head-constant. It never reduces head-constants and it never fails. \item {\tt intro {\ident}} Applies {\tt intro} but forces {\ident} to be the name of the introduced hypothesis. \ErrMsg \errindex{name {\ident} is already bound } \Rem If a name used by {\tt intro} hides the base name of a global constant then the latter can still be referred to by a qualified name (see \ref{LongNames}). \item {\tt intros \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$} Is equivalent to the composed tactic {\tt intro \ident$_1$; \dots\ ; intro \ident$_n$}. More generally, the \texttt{intros} tactic takes a pattern as argument in order to introduce names for components of an inductive definition or to clear introduced hypotheses; This is explained in~\ref{intros-pattern}. \item {\tt intros until {\ident}} \tacindex{intros until} Repeats {\tt intro} until it meets a premise of the goal having form {\tt (} {\ident}~{\tt :}~{\term} {\tt )} and discharges the variable named {\ident} of the current goal. \ErrMsg \errindex{No such hypothesis in current goal} \item {\tt intros until {\num}} \tacindex{intros until} Repeats {\tt intro} until the {\num}-th non-dependent premise. For instance, on the subgoal \verb+forall x y:nat, x=y -> forall z:nat,z=x->z=y+ the tactic \texttt{intros until 2} is equivalent to \texttt{intros x y H z H0} (assuming \texttt{x, y, H, z} and \texttt{H0} do not already occur in context). \ErrMsg \errindex{No such hypothesis in current goal} Happens when {\num} is 0 or is greater than the number of non-dependent products of the goal. \item {\tt intro after \ident} \tacindex{intro after} Applies {\tt intro} but puts the introduced hypothesis after the hypothesis \ident{} in the hypotheses. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No product even after head-reduction} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} : {\ident} \end{ErrMsgs} \item {\tt intro \ident$_1$ after \ident$_2$} \tacindex{intro ... after} Behaves as previously but \ident$_1$ is the name of the introduced hypothesis. It is equivalent to {\tt intro \ident$_1$; move \ident$_1$ after \ident$_2$}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No product even after head-reduction} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} : {\ident} \end{ErrMsgs} \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt apply \term} \tacindex{apply}\label{apply} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\term} is a term well-formed in the local context. The tactic {\tt apply} tries to match the current goal against the conclusion of the type of {\term}. If it succeeds, then the tactic returns as many subgoals as the instantiations of the premises of the type of {\term}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Impossible to unify \dots\ with \dots} Since higher order unification is undecidable, the {\tt apply} tactic may fail when you think it should work. In this case, if you know that the conclusion of {\term} and the current goal are unifiable, you can help the {\tt apply} tactic by transforming your goal with the {\tt change} or {\tt pattern} tactics (see sections \ref{pattern}, \ref{change}). \item \errindex{Cannot refine to conclusions with meta-variables} This occurs when some instantiations of premises of {\term} are not deducible from the unification. This is the case, for instance, when you want to apply a transitivity property. In this case, you have to use one of the variants below: \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt apply {\term} with {\term$_1$} \dots\ {\term$_n$}} \tacindex{apply \dots\ with} Provides {\tt apply} with explicit instantiations for all dependent premises of the type of {\term} which do not occur in the conclusion and consequently cannot be found by unification. Notice that {\term$_1$} \dots\ {\term$_n$} must be given according to the order of these dependent premises of the type of {\term}. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not the right number of missing arguments} \item{\tt apply {\term} with ({\vref$_1$} := {\term$_1$}) \dots\ ({\vref$_n$} := {\term$_n$})} This also provides {\tt apply} with values for instantiating premises. But variables are referred by names and non dependent products by order (see syntax in the section~\ref{Binding-list}). \item{\tt eapply \term}\tacindex{eapply}\label{eapply} The tactic {\tt eapply} behaves as {\tt apply} but does not fail when no instantiation are deducible for some variables in the premises. Rather, it turns these variables into so-called existential variables which are variables still to instantiate. An existential variable is identified by a name of the form {\tt ?$n$} where $n$ is a number. The instantiation is intended to be found later in the proof. An example of use of {\tt eapply} is given in section \ref{eapply-example}. \item{\tt lapply {\term}} \tacindex{lapply} This tactic applies to any goal, say {\tt G}. The argument {\term} has to be well-formed in the current context, its type being reducible to a non-dependent product {\tt A -> B} with {\tt B} possibly containing products. Then it generates two subgoals {\tt B->G} and {\tt A}. Applying {\tt lapply H} (where {\tt H} has type {\tt A->B} and {\tt B} does not start with a product) does the same as giving the sequence {\tt cut B. 2:apply H.} where {\tt cut} is described below. \Warning Be careful, when {\term} contains more than one non dependent product the tactic {\tt lapply} only takes into account the first product. \end{Variants} \subsection{{\tt set ( {\ident} {\tt :=} {\term} \tt )}} \tacindex{set} This replaces {\term} by {\ident} in the conclusion or in the hypotheses of the current goal and adds the new definition {\ident {\tt :=} \term} to the local context. The default is to make this replacement only in the conclusion. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt set ( } {\ident} {\tt :=} {\term} {\tt ) in *} This is equivalent to the above form but applies everywhere in the goal (both in conclusion and hypotheses). \item {\tt set ( {\ident$_0$} {\tt :=} {\term} {\tt ) in} {\ident$_1$}} This behaves the same but substitutes {\term} not in the goal but in the hypothesis named {\ident$_1$}. \item {\tt set (} {\ident$_0$} {\tt :=} {\term} {\tt ) in} {\ident$_1$} {\tt at} {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$} This notation allows to specify which occurrences of the hypothesis named {\ident$_1$} (or the goal if {\ident$_1$} is the word {\tt Goal}) should be substituted. The occurrences are numbered from left to right. A negative occurrence number means an occurrence which should not be substituted. \item {\tt set (} {\ident$_0$} {\tt :=} {\term} {\tt ) in} {\ident$_1$} {\tt at} {\num$_1^1$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_1}^1$} \dots {\ident$_m$} {\tt at} {\num$_1^m$} \dots {\num$_{n_m}^m$} This is the general form. It substitutes {\term} at occurrences {\num$_1^i$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_i}^i$} of hypothesis {\ident$_i$}. One of the {\ident}'s may be the word {\tt Goal}. \item {\tt pose ( {\ident} {\tt :=} {\term} {\tt )}} \tacindex{pose} This is equivalent to the default behavior in {\tt set}. % This adds the local definition {\ident} := {\term} to the current % context without performing any replacement in the goal or in the % hypotheses. \item{\tt pose {\term}} This behaves as {\tt pose (} {\ident} := {\term} {\tt )} but {\ident} is generated by {\Coq}. \end{Variants} \subsection{{\tt assert ( {\ident} : {\form} \tt )}} \tacindex{assert} This tactic applies to any goal. {\tt assert (H : U)} adds a new hypothesis of name \texttt{H} asserting \texttt{U} to the current goal and opens a new subgoal \texttt{U}\footnote{This corresponds to the cut rule of sequent calculus.}. The subgoal {\texttt U} comes first in the list of subgoals remaining to prove. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not a proposition or a type} Arises when the argument {\form} is neither of type {\tt Prop}, {\tt Set} nor {\tt Type}. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt assert {\form}} This behaves as {\tt assert (} {\ident} : {\form} {\tt )} but {\ident} is generated by {\Coq}. \item{\tt assert (} {\ident} := {\term} {\tt )} This behaves as {\tt assert ({\ident} : {\type});[exact {\term}|idtac]} where {\type} is the type of {\term}. \item {\tt cut {\form}}\tacindex{cut} This tactic applies to any goal. It implements the non dependent case of the ``App''\index{Typing rules!App} rule given in section \ref{Typed-terms}. (This is Modus Ponens inference rule.) {\tt cut U} transforms the current goal \texttt{T} into the two following subgoals: {\tt U -> T} and \texttt{U}. The subgoal {\tt U -> T} comes first in the list of remaining subgoal to prove. \end{Variants} % PAS CLAIR; % DEVRAIT AU MOINS FAIRE UN INTRO; % DEVRAIT ETRE REMPLACE PAR UN LET; % MESSAGE D'ERREUR STUPIDE % POURQUOI Specialize trans_equal ECHOUE ? %\begin{Variants} %\item {\tt Specialize \term} % \tacindex{Specialize} \\ % The argument {\tt t} should be a well-typed % term of type {\tt T}. This tactics is to make a cut of a % proposition when you have already the proof of this proposition % (for example it is a theorem applied to variables of local % context). It is equivalent to {\tt Assert T. exact t}. % %\item {\tt Specialize {\term} with \vref$_1$ := {\term$_1$} \dots % \vref$_n$ := \term$_n$} % \tacindex{Specialize \dots\ with} \\ % It is to provide the tactic with some explicit values to instantiate % premises of {\term} (see section \ref{Binding-list}). % Some other premises are inferred using type information and % unification. The resulting well-formed % term being {\tt (\term~\term'$_1$\dots\term'$_k$)} % this tactic behaves as is used as % {\tt Specialize (\term~\term'$_1$\dots\term'$_k$)} \\ % % \ErrMsg {\tt Metavariable wasn't in the metamap} \\ % Arises when the information provided in the bindings list is not % sufficient. %\item {\tt Specialize {\num} {\term} with \vref$_1$ := {\term$_1$} \dots\ % \vref$_n$:= \term$_n$}\\ % The behavior is the same as before but only \num\ premises of % \term\ will be kept. %\end{Variants} \subsection{\tt generalize \term} \tacindex{generalize}\label{generalize} This tactic applies to any goal. It generalizes the conclusion w.r.t. one subterm of it. For example: \begin{coq_eval} Goal forall x y:nat, (0 <= x + y + y). intros. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. generalize (x + y + y). \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} If the goal is $G$ and $t$ is a subterm of type $T$ in the goal, then {\tt generalize} \textit{t} replaces the goal by {\tt forall (x:$T$), $G'$} where $G'$ is obtained from $G$ by replacing all occurrences of $t$ by {\tt x}. The name of the variable (here {\tt n}) is chosen accordingly to $T$. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt generalize \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$} Is equivalent to {\tt generalize \term$_n$; \dots\ ; generalize \term$_1$}. Note that the sequence of \term$_i$'s are processed from $n$ to $1$. \item {\tt generalize dependent \term} \tacindex{generalize dependent} This generalizes {\term} but also {\em all} hypotheses which depend on {\term}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt change \term} \tacindex{change}\label{change} This tactic applies to any goal. It implements the rule ``Conv''\index{Typing rules!Conv} given in section \ref{Conv}. {\tt change U} replaces the current goal \T\ with a \U\ providing that \U\ is well-formed and that \T\ and \U\ are convertible. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not convertible} \end{ErrMsgs} \tacindex{change \dots\ in} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt change \term$_1$ with \term$_2$} This replaces the occurrences of \term$_1$ by \term$_2$ in the current goal. The terms \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ must be convertible. \item {\tt change \term$_1$ at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$ with \term$_2$} This replaces the occurrences numbered \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$ of \term$_1$ by \term$_2$ in the current goal. The terms \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ must be convertible. \ErrMsg {\tt Too few occurrences} \item {\tt change {\term} in {\ident}} \item {\tt change \term$_1$ with \term$_2$ in {\ident}} \item {\tt change \term$_1$ at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$ with \term$_2$ in {\ident}} This applies the {\tt change} tactic not to the goal but to the hypothesis {\ident}. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso \ref{Conversion-tactics} \subsection{Bindings list} \index{Binding list}\label{Binding-list} \index[tactic]{Binding list} A bindings list is generally used after the keyword {\tt with} in tactics. The general shape of a bindings list is {\tt (\vref$_1$ := \term$_1$) \dots\ (\vref$_n$ := \term$_n$)} where {\vref} is either an {\ident} or a {\num}. It is used to provide a tactic with a list of values (\term$_1$, \dots, \term$_n$) that have to be substituted respectively to \vref$_1$, \dots, \vref$_n$. For all $i \in [1\dots\ n]$, if \vref$_i$ is \ident$_i$ then it references the dependent product {\tt \ident$_i$:T} (for some type \T); if \vref$_i$ is \num$_i$ then it references the \num$_i$-th non dependent premise. A bindings list can also be a simple list of terms {\tt \term$_1$ \term$_2$ \dots\term$_n$}. In that case the references to which these terms correspond are determined by the tactic. In case of {\tt elim \term} (see section \ref{elim}) the terms should correspond to all the dependent products in the type of \term\ while in the case of {\tt apply \term} only the dependent products which are not bound in the conclusion of the type are given. \section{Negation and contradiction} \subsection{\tt absurd \term} \tacindex{absurd}\label{absurd} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\term} is any proposition {\tt P} of type {\tt Prop}. This tactic applies {\tt False} elimination, that is it deduces the current goal from {\tt False}, and generates as subgoals {\tt $\sim$P} and {\tt P}. It is very useful in proofs by cases, where some cases are impossible. In most cases, \texttt{P} or $\sim$\texttt{P} is one of the hypotheses of the local context. \subsection{\tt contradiction} \label{contradiction} \tacindex{contradiction} This tactic applies to any goal. The {\tt contradiction} tactic attempts to find in the current context (after all {\tt intros}) one which is equivalent to {\tt False}. It permits to prune irrelevant cases. This tactic is a macro for the tactics sequence {\tt intros; elimtype False; assumption}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such assumption} \end{ErrMsgs} \section{Conversion tactics} \index{Conversion tactics} \index[tactic]{Conversion tactics} \label{Conversion-tactics} This set of tactics implements different specialized usages of the tactic \texttt{change}. %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% %voir reduction__conv_x : histoires d'univers. %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% \subsection{{\tt cbv} \flag$_1$ \dots\ \flag$_n$, {\tt Lazy} \flag$_1$ \dots\ \flag$_n$ {\rm and} {\tt compute}} \tacindex{cbv}\tacindex{lazy} These parameterized reduction tactics apply to any goal and perform the normalization of the goal according to the specified flags. Since the reduction considered in \Coq\ include $\beta$ (reduction of functional application), $\delta$ (unfolding of transparent constants, see \ref{Transparent}), $\iota$ (reduction of {\tt Cases}, {\tt Fix} and {\tt CoFix} expressions) and $\zeta$ (removal of local definitions), every flag is one of {\tt beta}, {\tt delta}, {\tt iota}, {\tt zeta}, {\tt [\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]} and {\tt -[\qualid$_1$\ldots\qualid$_k$]}. The last two flags give the list of constants to unfold, or the list of constants not to unfold. These two flags can occur only after the {\tt delta} flag. For these tactics, the {\tt delta} flag does not apply to variables bound by a let-in construction of which the unfolding is controlled by the {\tt zeta} flag only. In addition, there is a flag {\tt Evar} to perform instantiation of existential variables (``?'') when an instantiation actually exists. The goal may be normalized with two strategies: {\em lazy} ({\tt lazy} tactic), or {\em call-by-value} ({\tt cbv} tactic). Notice that, for these tactics, the {\tt delta} flag without rest should be understood as unfolding all The lazy strategy is a call-by-need strategy, with sharing of reductions: the arguments of a function call are partially evaluated only when necessary, but if an argument is used several times, it is computed only once. This reduction is efficient for reducing expressions with dead code. For instance, the proofs of a proposition $\exists_T ~x. P(x)$ reduce to a pair of a witness $t$, and a proof that $t$ verifies the predicate $P$. Most of the time, $t$ may be computed without computing the proof of $P(t)$, thanks to the lazy strategy. The call-by-value strategy is the one used in ML languages: the arguments of a function call are evaluated first, using a weak reduction (no reduction under the $\lambda$-abstractions). Despite the lazy strategy always performs fewer reductions than the call-by-value strategy, the latter should be preferred for evaluating purely computational expressions (i.e. with few dead code). \begin{Variants} \item {\tt compute} \tacindex{Compute} This tactic is an alias for {\tt cbv beta delta evar iota zeta}. \end{Variants} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Delta must be specified before} A list of constants appeared before the {\tt delta} flag. \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{{\tt red}} \tacindex{red} This tactic applies to a goal which have form {\tt forall (x:T1)\dots(xk:Tk), c t1 \dots\ tn} where {\tt c} is a constant. If {\tt c} is transparent then it replaces {\tt c} with its definition (say {\tt t}) and then reduces {\tt (t t1 \dots\ tn)} according to $\beta\iota$-reduction rules. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not reducible} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{{\tt hnf}} \tacindex{hnf} This tactic applies to any goal. It replaces the current goal with its head normal form according to the $\beta\delta\iota$-reduction rules. {\tt hnf} does not produce a real head normal form but either a product or an applicative term in head normal form or a variable. \Example The term \verb+forall (n:nat), (plus (S n) (S n))+ is not reduced by {\tt hnf}. \Rem The $\delta$ rule will only be applied to transparent constants (i.e. which have not been frozen with an {\tt Opaque} command; see section \ref{Opaque}). \subsection{\tt simpl} \tacindex{simpl} This tactic applies to any goal. The tactic {\tt simpl} first applies $\beta\iota$-reduction rule. Then it expands transparent constants and tries to reduce {\tt T'} according, once more, to $\beta\iota$ rules. But when the $\iota$ rule is not applicable then possible $\delta$-reductions are not applied. For instance trying to use {\tt simpl} on {\tt (plus n O)=n} will change nothing. \tacindex{simpl \dots\ in} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt simpl {\term}} This applies {\tt simpl} only to the occurrences of {\term} in the current goal. \item {\tt simpl {\term} at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$} This applies {\tt simpl} only to the \num$_1$, \dots, \num$_i$ occurrences of {\term} in the current goal. \ErrMsg {\tt Too few occurrences} \item {\tt simpl {\ident}} This applies {\tt simpl} only to the applicative subterms whose head occurrence is {\ident}. \item {\tt simpl {\ident} at \num$_1$ \dots\ \num$_i$} This applies {\tt simpl} only to the \num$_1$, \dots, \num$_i$ applicative subterms whose head occurrence is {\ident}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt unfold \qualid} \tacindex{unfold}\label{unfold} This tactic applies to any goal. The argument {\qualid} must denote a defined transparent constant or local definition (see section \ref{Simpl-definitions} and \ref{Transparent}). The tactic {\tt unfold} applies the $\delta$ rule to each occurrence of the constant to which {\qualid} refers in the current goal and then replaces it with its $\beta\iota$-normal form. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item {\qualid} \errindex{does not denote an evaluable constant} is printed. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt unfold {\qualid}$_1$ \dots\ \qualid$_n$} \tacindex{unfold \dots\ in} Replaces {\em simultaneously} {\qualid}$_1$, \dots, {\qualid}$_n$ with their definitions and replaces the current goal with its $\beta\iota$ normal form. \item {\tt unfold \num$_1^1$ \dots\ \num$_i^1$ {\qualid}$_1$ \dots\ \num$_1^n$ \dots\ \num$_j^n$ \qualid$_n$} The lists \num$_1^1$, \dots, \num$_i^1$ and \num$_1^n$, \dots, \num$_j^n$ are to specify the occurrences of {\qualid}$_1$, \dots, \qualid$_n$ to be unfolded. Occurrences are located from left to right in the linear notation of terms. \ErrMsg {\tt bad occurrence numbers of {\qualid}$_i$} \end{Variants} \subsection{{\tt fold} \term} \tacindex{fold} This tactic applies to any goal. \term\ is reduced using the {\tt red} tactic. Every occurrence of the resulting term in the goal is then substituted for \term. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt fold} \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$ Equivalent to {\tt fold} \term$_1${\tt;}\ldots{\tt; fold} \term$_n$. \end{Variants} \subsection{{\tt pattern {\term}}} \tacindex{pattern}\label{pattern} This command applies to any goal. The argument {\term} must be a free subterm of the current goal. The command {\tt pattern} performs $\beta$-expansion (the inverse of $\bt$-reduction) of the current goal (say \T) by \begin{enumerate} \item replacing all occurrences of {\term} in {\T} with a fresh variable \item abstracting this variable \item applying the abstracted goal to {\term} \end{enumerate} For instance, if the current goal {\T} is {\tt (P t)} when {\tt t} does not occur in {\tt P} then {\tt pattern t} transforms it into {\tt ([x:A](P x) t)}. This command has to be used, for instance, when an {\tt apply} command fails on matching. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt pattern {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$} {\term}} Only the occurrences {\num$_1$} \dots\ {\num$_n$} of {\term} will be considered for $\beta$-expansion. Occurrences are located from left to right. \item {\tt pattern {\num$_1^1$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_1}^1$} {\term$_1$} \dots {\num$_1^m$} \dots\ {\num$_{n_m}^m$} {\term$_m$}} Will process occurrences \num$_1^1$, \dots, \num$_i^1$ of \term$_1$, \dots, \num$_1^m$, \dots, \num$_j^m$ of \term$_m$ starting from \term$_m$. Starting from a goal {\tt (P t$_1$\dots\ t$_m$)} with the {\tt t$_i$} which do not occur in $P$, the tactic {\tt pattern t$_1$\dots\ t$_m$} generates the equivalent goal {\tt ([x$_1$:A$_1$]\dots\ [x$_m$:A$_m$](P x$_1$\dots\ x$_m$) t$_1$\dots\ t$_m$)}.\\ If $t_i$ occurs in one of the generated types A$_j$ these occurrences will also be considered and possibly abstracted. \end{Variants} \subsection{Conversion tactics applied to hypotheses} {\convtactic} {\tt in} \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ Applies the conversion tactic {\convtactic} to the hypotheses \ident$_1$, \ldots, \ident$_n$. The tactic {\convtactic} is any of the conversion tactics listed in this section. If \ident$_i$ is a local definition, then \ident$_i$ can be replaced by (Type of \ident$_i$) to address not the body but the type of the local definition. Example: {\tt unfold not in (Type of H1) (Type of H3).} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} : {\ident}. \end{ErrMsgs} \section{Introductions} Introduction tactics address goals which are inductive constants. They are used when one guesses that the goal can be obtained with one of its constructors' type. \subsection{\tt constructor \num} \label{constructor} \tacindex{constructor} This tactic applies to a goal such that the head of its conclusion is an inductive constant (say {\tt I}). The argument {\num} must be less or equal to the numbers of constructor(s) of {\tt I}. Let {\tt ci} be the {\tt i}-th constructor of {\tt I}, then {\tt constructor i} is equivalent to {\tt intros; apply ci}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not an inductive product} \item \errindex{Not enough constructors} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{constructor} This tries \texttt{constructor 1} then \texttt{constructor 2}, \dots\ , then \texttt{constructor} \textit{n} where \textit{n} if the number of constructors of the head of the goal. \item {\tt constructor \num~with} {\bindinglist} \tacindex{constructor \dots\ with} Let {\tt ci} be the {\tt i}-th constructor of {\tt I}, then {\tt constructor i with \bindinglist} is equivalent to {\tt intros; apply ci with \bindinglist}. \Warning the terms in the \bindinglist\ are checked in the context where {\tt constructor} is executed and not in the context where {\tt apply} is executed (the introductions are not taken into account). \item {\tt split}\tacindex{split} Applies if {\tt I} has only one constructor, typically in the case of conjunction $A\land B$. It is equivalent to {\tt constructor 1}. \item {\tt exists {\bindinglist}}\tacindex{exists} Applies if {\tt I} has only one constructor, for instance in the case of existential quantification $\exists x\cdot P(x)$. It is equivalent to {\tt intros; constructor 1 with \bindinglist}. \item {\tt left}\tacindex{left}, {\tt right}\tacindex{right} Apply if {\tt I} has two constructors, for instance in the case of disjunction $A\lor B$. They are respectively equivalent to {\tt constructor 1} and {\tt constructor 2}. \item {\tt left \bindinglist}, {\tt right \bindinglist}, {\tt split \bindinglist} Are equivalent to the corresponding {\tt constructor $i$ with \bindinglist}. \end{Variants} \section{Eliminations (Induction and Case Analysis)} Elimination tactics are useful to prove statements by induction or case analysis. Indeed, they make use of the elimination (or induction) principles generated with inductive definitions (see section~\ref{Cic-inductive-definitions}). \subsection{\tt induction \term} \tacindex{induction} This tactic applies to any goal. The type of the argument {\term} must be an inductive constant. Then, the tactic {\tt induction} generates subgoals, one for each possible form of {\term}, i.e. one for each constructor of the inductive type. The tactic {\tt induction} automatically replaces every occurrences of {\term} in the conclusion and the hypotheses of the goal. It automatically adds induction hypotheses (using names of the form {\tt IHn1}) to the local context. If some hypothesis must not be taken into account in the induction hypothesis, then it needs to be removed first (you can also use the tactics {\tt elim} or {\tt simple induction}, see below). There are particular cases: \begin{itemize} \item If {\term} is an identifier {\ident} denoting a quantified variable of the conclusion of the goal, then {\tt induction {\ident}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; induction {\ident}} \item If {\term} is a {\num}, then {\tt induction {\num}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}} followed by {\tt induction} applied to the last introduced hypothesis. \Rem For simple induction on a numeral, use syntax {\tt induction ({\num})} (not very interesting anyway). \end{itemize} \begin{coq_example} Lemma induction_test : forall n:nat, n = n -> n <= n. intros n H. induction n. \end{coq_example} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Not an inductive product} \item \errindex{Cannot refine to conclusions with meta-variables} As {\tt induction} uses {\tt apply}, see section \ref{apply} and the variant {\tt elim \dots\ with \dots} below. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt induction {\term} as {\intropattern}} This behaves as {\tt induction {\term}} but uses the names in {\intropattern} to names the variables introduced in the context. The {\intropattern} must have the form {\tt [} $p_{11}$ \ldots $p_{1n_1}$ {\tt |} {\ldots} {\tt |} $p_{m1}$ \ldots $p_{mn_m}$ {\tt ]} with $m$ being the number of constructors of the type of {\term}. Each variable introduced by {\tt induction} in the context of the $i^{th}$ goal gets its name from the list $p_{i1}$ \ldots $p_{in_i}$ in order. If there are not enough names, {\tt induction} invents names for the remaining variables to introduce. More generally, the $p$'s can be any introduction patterns (see section \ref{intros-pattern}). This provides a concise notation for nested induction. It is recommended to use this variant of {\tt induction} for robust proof scripts. \item {\tt induction {\term} using {\qualid}} This behaves as {\tt induction {\term}} but using the induction scheme of name {\qualid}. It does not expect that the type of {\term} is inductive. \item {\tt induction {\term} using {\qualid} as {\intropattern}} This combines {\tt induction {\term} using {\qualid}} and {\tt induction {\term} as {\intropattern}}. \item {\tt elim \term}\label{elim} This is a more basic induction tactic. Again, the type of the argument {\term} must be an inductive constant. Then according to the type of the goal, the tactic {\tt elim} chooses the right destructor and applies it (as in the case of the {\tt apply} tactic). For instance, assume that our proof context contains {\tt n:nat}, assume that our current goal is {\tt T} of type {\tt Prop}, then {\tt elim n} is equivalent to {\tt apply nat\_ind with (n:=n)}. The tactic {\tt elim} does not affect the hypotheses of the goal, neither introduces the induction loading into the context of hypotheses. \item {\tt elim \term} also works when the type of {\term} starts with products and the head symbol is an inductive definition. In that case the tactic tries both to find an object in the inductive definition and to use this inductive definition for elimination. In case of non-dependent products in the type, subgoals are generated corresponding to the hypotheses. In the case of dependent products, the tactic will try to find an instance for which the elimination lemma applies. \item {\tt elim {\term} with \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$} \tacindex{elim \dots\ with} \ Allows the user to give explicitly the values for dependent premises of the elimination schema. All arguments must be given. \ErrMsg \errindex{Not the right number of dependent arguments} \item{\tt elim {\term} with {\vref$_1$} := {\term$_1$} \dots\ {\vref$_n$} := {\term$_n$}} Provides also {\tt elim} with values for instantiating premises by associating explicitly variables (or non dependent products) with their intended instance. \item{\tt elim {\term$_1$} using {\term$_2$}} \tacindex{elim \dots\ using} Allows the user to give explicitly an elimination predicate {\term$_2$} which is not the standard one for the underlying inductive type of {\term$_1$}. Each of the {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} is either a simple term or a term with a bindings list (see \ref{Binding-list}). \item {\tt elimtype \form}\tacindex{elimtype} The argument {\form} must be inductively defined. {\tt elimtype I} is equivalent to {\tt cut I. intro H{\rm\sl n}; elim H{\rm\sl n}; clear H{\rm\sl n}}. Therefore the hypothesis {\tt H{\rm\sl n}} will not appear in the context(s) of the subgoal(s). Conversely, if {\tt t} is a term of (inductive) type {\tt I} and which does not occur in the goal then {\tt elim t} is equivalent to {\tt elimtype I; 2: exact t.} \ErrMsg \errindex{Impossible to unify \dots\ with \dots} Arises when {\form} needs to be applied to parameters. \item {\tt simple induction \ident}\tacindex{simple induction} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; elim {\tt {\ident}}} when {\ident} is a quantified variable of the goal. \item {\tt simple induction {\num}} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}; elim {\tt {\ident}}} where {\ident} is the name given by {\tt intros until {\num}} to the {\num}-th non-dependent premise of the goal. %% \item {\tt simple induction {\term}}\tacindex{simple induction} %% If {\term} is an {\ident} corresponding to a quantified variable of %% the goal then the tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; elim %% {\tt {\ident}}}. If {\term} is a {\num} then the tactic behaves as %% {\tt intros until {\ident}; elim {\tt {\ident}}}. Otherwise, it is %% a synonym for {\tt elim {\term}}. %% \Rem For simple induction on a numeral, use syntax {\tt simple %% induction ({\num})}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt destruct \term} \tacindex{destruct} The tactic {\tt destruct} is used to perform case analysis without recursion. Its behavior is similar to {\tt induction} except that no induction hypothesis is generated. It applies to any goal and the type of {\term} must be inductively defined. There are particular cases: \begin{itemize} \item If {\term} is an identifier {\ident} denoting a quantified variable of the conclusion of the goal, then {\tt destruct {\ident}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; destruct {\ident}} \item If {\term} is a {\num}, then {\tt destruct {\num}} behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}} followed by {\tt destruct} applied to the last introduced hypothesis. \Rem For destruction of a numeral, use syntax {\tt destruct ({\num})} (not very interesting anyway). \end{itemize} \begin{Variants} \item{\tt destruct {\term} as {\intropattern}} This behaves as {\tt destruct {\term}} but uses the names in {\intropattern} to names the variables introduced in the context. The {\intropattern} must have the form {\tt [} $p_{11}$ \ldots $p_{1n_1}$ {\tt |} {\ldots} {\tt |} $p_{m1}$ \ldots $p_{mn_m}$ {\tt ]} with $m$ being the number of constructors of the type of {\term}. Each variable introduced by {\tt destruct} in the context of the $i^{th}$ goal gets its name from the list $p_{i1}$ \ldots $p_{in_i}$ in order. If there are not enough names, {\tt destruct} invents names for the remaining variables to introduce. More generally, the $p$'s can be any introduction patterns (see section \ref{intros-pattern}). This provides a concise notation for nested destruction. % It is recommended to use this variant of {\tt destruct} for % robust proof scripts. \item{\tt destruct {\term} using {\qualid}} This is a synonym of {\tt induction {\term} using {\qualid}}. \item{\tt destruct {\term} as {\intropattern} using {\qualid}} This is a synonym of {\tt induction {\term} using {\qualid} as {\intropattern}}. \item{\tt case \term}\label{case}\tacindex{case} The tactic {\tt case} is a more basic tactic to perform case analysis without recursion. It behaves as {\tt elim \term} but using a case-analysis elimination principle and not a recursive one. \item {\tt case {\term} with \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$} \tacindex{case \dots\ with} Analogous to {\tt elim \dots\ with} above. \item {\tt simple destruct \ident}\tacindex{simple destruct} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\ident}; case {\tt {\ident}}} when {\ident} is a quantified variable of the goal. \item {\tt simple destruct {\num}} This tactic behaves as {\tt intros until {\num}; case {\tt {\ident}}} where {\ident} is the name given by {\tt intros until {\num}} to the {\num}-th non-dependent premise of the goal. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt intros {\intropattern} {\ldots} {\intropattern}} \label{intros-pattern} \tacindex{intros \intropattern} The tactic {\tt intros} applied to introduction patterns performs both introduction of variables and case analysis in order to give names to components of an hypothesis. An introduction pattern is either: \begin{itemize} \item the wildcard: {\tt \_} \item a variable \item a disjunction of lists of patterns: {\tt [$p_{11}$ {\ldots} $p_{1m_1}$ | {\ldots} | $p_{11}$ {\ldots} $p_{nm_n}$]} \item a conjunction of patterns: {\tt (} $p_1$ {\tt ,} {\ldots} {\tt ,} $p_n$ {\tt )} \end{itemize} The behavior of \texttt{intros} is defined inductively over the structure of the pattern given as argument: \begin{itemize} \item introduction on the wildcard do the introduction and then immediately clear (cf~\ref{clear}) the corresponding hypothesis; \item introduction on a variable behaves like described in~\ref{intro}; \item introduction over a list of patterns $p_1~\ldots~p_n$ is equivalent to the sequence of introductions over the patterns namely: \texttt{intros $p_1$;\ldots; intros $p_n$}, the goal should start with at least $n$ products; \item introduction over a disjunction of list of patterns {\tt [$p_{11}$ {\ldots} $p_{1m_1}$ | {\ldots} | $p_{11}$ {\ldots} $p_{nm_n}$]}. It introduces a new variable $X$, its type should be an inductive definition with $n$ constructors, then it performs a case analysis over $X$ (which generates $n$ subgoals), it clears $X$ and performs on each generated subgoals the corresponding \texttt{intros}~$p_{i1}$ {\ldots} $p_{im_i}$ tactic; \item introduction over a conjunction of patterns $(p_1,\ldots,p_n)$, it introduces a new variable $X$, its type should be an inductive definition with $1$ constructor with (at least) $n$ arguments, then it performs a case analysis over $X$ (which generates $1$ subgoal with at least $n$ products), it clears $X$ and performs an introduction over the list of patterns $p_1~\ldots~p_n$. \end{itemize} \Rem The pattern {\tt ($p_1$, {\ldots}, $p_n$)} is a synonym for the pattern {\tt [$p_1$ {\ldots} $p_n$]}, i.e. it corresponds to the decomposition of an hypothesis typed by an inductive type with a single constructor. \begin{coq_example} Lemma intros_test : forall A B C:Prop, A \/ B /\ C -> (A -> C) -> C. intros A B C [a| [_ c]] f. apply (f a). Proof c. \end{coq_example} %\subsection{\tt FixPoint \dots}\tacindex{Fixpoint} %Not yet documented. \subsection {\tt double induction \ident$_1$ \ident$_2$} \tacindex{double induction} This tactic applies to any goal. If the variables {\ident$_1$} and {\ident$_2$} of the goal have an inductive type, then this tactic performs double induction on these variables. For instance, if the current goal is \verb+(n,m:nat)(P n m)+ then, {\tt double induction n m} yields the four cases with their respective inductive hypotheses. In particular the case for \verb+(P (S n) (S m))+ with the induction hypotheses \verb+(P (S n) m)+ and \verb+(m:nat)(P n m)+ (hence \verb+(P n m)+ and \verb+(P n (S m))+). \Rem When the induction hypothesis \verb+(P (S n) m)+ is not needed, {\tt induction \ident$_1$; destruct \ident$_2$} produces more concise subgoals. \begin{Variant} \item {\tt double induction \num$_1$ \num$_2$}\\ This applies double induction on the \num$_1^{th}$ and \num$_2^{th}$ {\it non dependent} premises of the goal. More generally, any combination of an {\ident} and an {\num} is valid. \end{Variant} \subsection{\tt decompose [ {\ident$_1$} \dots\ {\ident$_n$} ] \term} \label{decompose} \tacindex{decompose} This tactic allows to recursively decompose a complex proposition in order to obtain atomic ones. Example: \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Lemma ex1 : forall A B C:Prop, A /\ B /\ C \/ B /\ C \/ C /\ A -> C. intros A B C H; decompose [and or] H; assumption. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} Qed. \end{coq_example*} {\tt decompose} does not work on right-hand sides of implications or products. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt decompose sum \term}\tacindex{decompose sum} This decomposes sum types (like \texttt{or}). \item {\tt decompose record \term}\tacindex{decompose record} This decomposes record types (inductive types with one constructor, like \texttt{and} and \texttt{exists} and those defined with the \texttt{Record} macro, see p.~\pageref{Record}). \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt functional induction \ident\ \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$.} \tacindex{functional induction} \label{FunInduction} The tactic \texttt{functional induction} performs case analysis and induction following the definition of a function. \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Lemma le_minus : forall n m:nat, (n - m <= n). intros n m. functional induction minus n m; simpl; auto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example*} Qed. \end{coq_example*} \texttt{functional induction} is a shorthand for the more general command \texttt{Functional Scheme} which builds induction principles following the recursive structure of (possibly mutually recursive) functions. \Rem \texttt{functional induction} does not work on polymorphic and dependently typed functions yet. It may also fail on functions built by certain tactics. \SeeAlso{\ref{FunScheme},\ref{FunScheme-examples}} \section{Equality} These tactics use the equality {\tt eq:forall A:Type, A->A->Prop} defined in file {\tt Logic.v} (see section \ref{Equality}). The notation for {\tt eq}~$T~t~u$ is simply {\tt $t$=$u$} dropping the implicit type of $t$ and $u$. \subsection{\tt rewrite \term} \label{rewrite} \tacindex{rewrite} This tactic applies to any goal. The type of {\term} must have the form \texttt{(x$_1$:A$_1$) \dots\ (x$_n$:A$_n$)}\term$_1${\tt =}\term$_2$. \noindent Then {\tt rewrite \term} replaces every occurrence of \term$_1$ by \term$_2$ in the goal. Some of the variables x$_1$ are solved by unification, and some of the types \texttt{A}$_1$, \dots, \texttt{A}$_n$ become new subgoals. \Rem In case the type of \term$_1$ contains occurrences of variables bound in the type of \term, the tactic tries first to find a subterm of the goal which matches this term in order to find a closed instance \term$'_1$ of \term$_1$, and then all instances of \term$'_1$ will be replaced. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{The term provided does not end with an equation} \item \errindex{Tactic generated a subgoal identical to the original goal}\\ This happens if \term$_1$ does not occur in the goal. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt rewrite -> {\term}}\tacindex{rewrite ->}\\ Is equivalent to {\tt rewrite \term} \item {\tt rewrite <- {\term}}\tacindex{rewrite <-}\\ Uses the equality \term$_1${\tt=}\term$_2$ from right to left \item {\tt rewrite {\term} in {\ident}} \tacindex{rewrite \dots\ in}\\ Analogous to {\tt rewrite {\term}} but rewriting is done in the hypothesis named {\ident}. \item {\tt rewrite -> {\term} in {\ident}} \tacindex{rewrite -> \dots\ in}\\ Behaves as {\tt rewrite {\term} in {\ident}}. \item {\tt rewrite <- {\term} in {\ident}}\\ \tacindex{rewrite <- \dots\ in} Uses the equality \term$_1${\tt=}\term$_2$ from right to left to rewrite in the hypothesis named {\ident}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt cutrewrite -> \term$_1$ = \term$_2$} \label{cutrewrite} \tacindex{cutrewrite} This tactic acts like {\tt replace {\term$_1$} with {\term$_2$}} (see below). \subsection{\tt replace {\term$_1$} with {\term$_2$}} \tacindex{replace \dots\ with} This tactic applies to any goal. It replaces all free occurrences of {\term$_1$} in the current goal with {\term$_2$} and generates the equality {\term$_2$}{\tt =}{\term$_1$} as a subgoal. It is equivalent to {\tt cut \term$_2$=\term$_1$; intro H{\sl n}; rewrite <- H{\sl n}; clear H{\sl n}}. %N'existe pas... %\begin{Variants} % %\item {\tt replace {\term$_1$} with {\term$_2$} in \ident} % This replaces {\term$_1$} with {\term$_2$} in the hypothesis named % \ident, and generates the subgoal {\term$_2$}{\tt =}{\term$_1$}. % \begin{ErrMsgs} % \item \errindex{No such hypothesis} % \end{ErrMsgs} % %\end{Variants} \subsection{\tt reflexivity} \label{reflexivity} \tacindex{reflexivity} This tactic applies to a goal which has the form {\tt t=u}. It checks that {\tt t} and {\tt u} are convertible and then solves the goal. It is equivalent to {\tt apply refl\_equal}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{The conclusion is not a substitutive equation} \item \errindex{Impossible to unify \dots\ with ..} \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt symmetry} \tacindex{symmetry} \tacindex{symmetry in} This tactic applies to a goal which has form {\tt t=u} and changes it into {\tt u=t}. \variant {\tt symmetry in {\ident}}\\ If the statement of the hypothesis {\ident} has the form {\tt t=u}, the tactic changes it to {\tt u=t}. \subsection{\tt transitivity \term}\tacindex{transitivity} This tactic applies to a goal which have form {\tt t=u} and transforms it into the two subgoals {\tt t={\term}} and {\tt {\term}=u}. \subsection{\tt subst {\ident}}\tacindex{subst} This tactic applies to a goal which have \ident\ in its context and (at least) one hypothesis, say {\tt H}, of type {\tt \ident=t} or {\tt t=\ident}. Then it replaces \ident\ by {\tt t} everywhere in the goal (in the hypotheses and in the conclusion) and clears \ident\ and {\tt H} from the context. \Rem When several hypotheses have the form {\tt \ident=t} or {\tt t=\ident}, the first one is used. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt subst \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$} \\ Is equivalent to {\tt subst \ident$_1$; \dots; subst \ident$_n$}. \item {\tt subst} \\ Applies {\tt subst} repeatedly to all identifiers from the context for which an equality exists. \end{Variants} \section{Equality and inductive sets} We describe in this section some special purpose tactics dealing with equality and inductive sets or types. These tactics use the equality {\tt eq:forall (A:Type), A->A->Prop}, simply written with the infix symbol {\tt =}. \subsection{\tt decide equality} \label{decideequality} \tacindex{decide equality} This tactic solves a goal of the form {\tt forall $x$ $y$:$R$, \{$x$=$y$\}+\{\verb|~|$x$=$y$\}}, where $R$ is an inductive type such that its constructors do not take proofs or functions as arguments, nor objects in dependent types. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt decide equality {\term}$_1$ {\term}$_2$ }.\\ Solves a goal of the form {\tt \{}\term$_1${\tt =}\term$_2${\tt \}+\{\verb|~|}\term$_1${\tt =}\term$_2${\tt \}}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt compare \term$_1$ \term$_2$} \tacindex{compare} This tactic compares two given objects \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ of an inductive datatype. If $G$ is the current goal, it leaves the sub-goals \term$_1${\tt =}\term$_2$ {\tt ->} $G$ and \verb|~|\term$_1${\tt =}\term$_2$ {\tt ->} $G$. The type of \term$_1$ and \term$_2$ must satisfy the same restrictions as in the tactic \texttt{decide equality}. \subsection {\tt discriminate {\ident}} \label{discriminate} \tacindex{discriminate} This tactic proves any goal from an absurd hypothesis stating that two structurally different terms of an inductive set are equal. For example, from the hypothesis {\tt (S (S O))=(S O)} we can derive by absurdity any proposition. Let {\ident} be a hypothesis of type {\tt{\term$_1$} = {\term$_2$}} in the local context, {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} being elements of an inductive set. To build the proof, the tactic traverses the normal forms\footnote{Recall: opaque constants will not be expanded by $\delta$ reductions} of {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} looking for a couple of subterms {\tt u} and {\tt w} ({\tt u} subterm of the normal form of {\term$_1$} and {\tt w} subterm of the normal form of {\term$_2$}), placed at the same positions and whose head symbols are two different constructors. If such a couple of subterms exists, then the proof of the current goal is completed, otherwise the tactic fails. \Rem If {\ident} does not denote an hypothesis in the local context but refers to an hypothesis quantified in the goal, then the latter is first introduced in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item {\ident} \errindex{Not a discriminable equality} \\ occurs when the type of the specified hypothesis is not an equation. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{discriminate} \num\\ This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} then \texttt{discriminate \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item {\tt discriminate}\tacindex{discriminate} \\ It applies to a goal of the form {\tt \verb=~={\term$_1$}={\term$_2$}} and it is equivalent to: {\tt unfold not; intro {\ident}}; {\tt discriminate {\ident}}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{No discriminable equalities} \\ occurs when the goal does not verify the expected preconditions. \end{ErrMsgs} \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt injection {\ident}} \label{injection} \tacindex{injection} The {\tt injection} tactic is based on the fact that constructors of inductive sets are injections. That means that if $c$ is a constructor of an inductive set, and if $(c~\vec{t_1})$ and $(c~\vec{t_2})$ are two terms that are equal then $~\vec{t_1}$ and $~\vec{t_2}$ are equal too. If {\ident} is an hypothesis of type {\tt {\term$_1$} = {\term$_2$}}, then {\tt injection} behaves as applying injection as deep as possible to derive the equality of all the subterms of {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} placed in the same positions. For example, from the hypothesis {\tt (S (S n))=(S (S (S m))} we may derive {\tt n=(S m)}. To use this tactic {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} should be elements of an inductive set and they should be neither explicitly equal, nor structurally different. We mean by this that, if {\tt n$_1$} and {\tt n$_2$} are their respective normal forms, then: \begin{itemize} \item {\tt n$_1$} and {\tt n$_2$} should not be syntactically equal, \item there must not exist any couple of subterms {\tt u} and {\tt w}, {\tt u} subterm of {\tt n$_1$} and {\tt w} subterm of {\tt n$_2$} , placed in the same positions and having different constructors as head symbols. \end{itemize} If these conditions are satisfied, then, the tactic derives the equality of all the subterms of {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} placed in the same positions and puts them as antecedents of the current goal. \Example Consider the following goal: \begin{coq_example*} Inductive list : Set := | nil : list | cons : nat -> list -> list. Variable P : list -> Prop. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} Lemma ex : forall (l:list) (n:nat), P nil -> cons n l = cons 0 nil -> P l. intros l n H H0. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Show. injection H0. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} Beware that \texttt{injection} yields always an equality in a sigma type whenever the injected object has a dependent type. \Rem If {\ident} does not denote an hypothesis in the local context but refers to an hypothesis quantified in the goal, then the latter is first introduced in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item {\ident} \errindex{is not a projectable equality} occurs when the type of the hypothesis $id$ does not verify the preconditions. \item \errindex{Not an equation} occurs when the type of the hypothesis $id$ is not an equation. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{injection} \num\\ This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} then \texttt{injection \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item{\tt injection}\tacindex{injection} \\ If the current goal is of the form {\tt \verb=~={\term$_1$}={\term$_2$}}, the tactic computes the head normal form of the goal and then behaves as the sequence: {\tt unfold not; intro {\ident}; injection {\ident}}. \\ \ErrMsg \errindex{goal does not satisfy the expected preconditions} \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt simplify\_eq {\ident}} \tacindex{simplify\_eq} \label{simplify-eq} Let {\ident} be the name of an hypothesis of type {\tt {\term$_1$}={\term$_2$}} in the local context. If {\term$_1$} and {\term$_2$} are structurally different (in the sense described for the tactic {\tt discriminate}), then the tactic {\tt simplify\_eq} behaves as {\tt discriminate {\ident}} otherwise it behaves as {\tt injection {\ident}}. \Rem If {\ident} does not denote an hypothesis in the local context but refers to an hypothesis quantified in the goal, then the latter is first introduced in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{simplify\_eq} \num\\ This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} then \texttt{simplify\_eq \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item{\tt simplify\_eq} If the current goal has form $\verb=~=t_1=t_2$, then this tactic does \texttt{hnf; intro {\ident}; simplify\_eq {\ident}}. \end{Variants} \subsection{\tt dependent rewrite -> {\ident}} \tacindex{dependent rewrite ->} \label{dependent-rewrite} This tactic applies to any goal. If \ident\ has type \verb+(existS A B a b)=(existS A B a' b')+ in the local context (i.e. each term of the equality has a sigma type $\{ a:A~ \&~(B~a)\}$) this tactic rewrites \verb+a+ into \verb+a'+ and \verb+b+ into \verb+b'+ in the current goal. This tactic works even if $B$ is also a sigma type. This kind of equalities between dependent pairs may be derived by the injection and inversion tactics. \begin{Variants} \item{\tt dependent rewrite <- {\ident}} \tacindex{dependent rewrite <-} \\ Analogous to {\tt dependent rewrite ->} but uses the equality from right to left. \end{Variants} \section{inversion} \label{inversion} \subsection{\tt inversion {\ident}}\tacindex{inversion} Let the type of \ident~ in the local context be $(I~\vec{t})$, where $I$ is a (co)inductive predicate. Then, \texttt{inversion} applied to \ident~ derives for each possible constructor $c_i$ of $(I~\vec{t})$, {\bf all} the necessary conditions that should hold for the instance $(I~\vec{t})$ to be proved by $c_i$. \Rem If {\ident} does not denote an hypothesis in the local context but refers to an hypothesis quantified in the goal, then the latter is first introduced in the local context using \texttt{intros until \ident}. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{inversion} \num\\ This does the same thing as \texttt{intros until \num} then \texttt{inversion \ident} where {\ident} is the identifier for the last introduced hypothesis. \item \texttt{inversion\_clear} \ident\\ \tacindex{inversion\_clear} This behaves as \texttt{inversion} and then erases \ident~ from the context. \item \texttt{inversion} {\ident} \texttt{as} {\intropattern} \\ \tacindex{inversion \dots\ as} This behaves as \texttt{inversion} but using names in {\intropattern} for naming hypotheses. The {\intropattern} must have the form {\tt [} $p_{11}$ \ldots $p_{1n_1}$ {\tt |} {\ldots} {\tt |} $p_{m1}$ \ldots $p_{mn_m}$ {\tt ]} with $m$ being the number of constructors of the type of {\ident}. Be careful that the list must be of length $m$ even if {\tt inversion} discards some cases (which is precisely one of its roles): for the discarded cases, just use an empty list (i.e. $n_i=0$). The arguments of the $i^{th}$ constructor and the equalities that {\tt inversion} introduces in the context of the goal corresponding to the $i^{th}$ constructor, if it exists, get their names from the list $p_{i1}$ \ldots $p_{in_i}$ in order. If there are not enough names, {\tt induction} invents names for the remaining variables to introduce. In case an equation splits into several equations (because {\tt inversion} applies {\tt injection} on the equalities it generates), the corresponding name $p_{ij}$ in the list must be replaced by a sublist of the form {\tt [$p_{ij1}$ \ldots $p_{ijq}$]} (or, equivalently, {\tt ($p_{ij1}$, \ldots, $p_{ijq}$)}) where $q$ is the number of subequations obtained from splitting the original equation. Here is an example. \begin{coq_eval} Require Import List. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Inductive contains0 : list nat -> Prop := | in_hd : forall l, contains0 (0 :: l) | in_tl : forall l b, contains0 l -> contains0 (b :: l). Goal forall l:list nat, contains0 (1 :: l) -> contains0 l. intros l H; inversion H as [ | l' p Hl' [Heqp Heql'] ]. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \item \texttt{inversion} {\num} {\tt as} {\intropattern} \\ This allows to name the hypotheses introduced by \texttt{inversion} {\num} in the context. \item \texttt{inversion\_clear} {\ident} {\tt as} {\intropattern} \\ \tacindex{inversion\_cleardots\ as} This allows to name the hypotheses introduced by \texttt{inversion\_clear} in the context. \item \texttt{inversion } {\ident} \texttt{in} \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$\\ \tacindex{inversion \dots\ in} Let \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, be identifiers in the local context. This tactic behaves as generalizing \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, and then performing \texttt{inversion}. \item \texttt{inversion } {\ident} {\tt as} {\intropattern} \texttt{in} \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$\\ \tacindex{inversion \dots\ as \dots\ in} This allows to name the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{inversion} {\ident} \texttt{in} \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$. \item \texttt{inversion\_clear} {\ident} \texttt{in} \ident$_1$ \ldots \ident$_n$\\ \tacindex{inversion\_clear \dots\ in} Let \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, be identifiers in the local context. This tactic behaves as generalizing \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$, and then performing {\tt inversion\_clear}. \item \texttt{inversion\_clear} {\ident} \texttt{as} {\intropattern} \texttt{in} \ident$_1$ \ldots \ident$_n$\\ \tacindex{inversion\_clear \dots\ as \dots\ in} This allows to name the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{inversion\_clear} {\ident} \texttt{in} \ident$_1$ \ldots \ident$_n$. \item \texttt{dependent inversion} {\ident}\\ \tacindex{dependent inversion} That must be used when \ident\ appears in the current goal. It acts like \texttt{inversion} and then substitutes \ident\ for the corresponding term in the goal. \item \texttt{dependent inversion} {\ident} \texttt{as} {\intropattern} \\ \tacindex{dependent inversion \dots\ as } This allows to name the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion} {\ident}. \item \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear} {\ident}\\ \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear} Like \texttt{dependent inversion}, except that {\ident} is cleared from the local context. \item \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear} {\ident}\texttt{as} {\intropattern}\\ \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear \dots\ as} This allows to name the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear} {\ident} \item \texttt{dependent inversion } {\ident} \texttt{ with } \term \\ \tacindex{dependent inversion \dots\ with} This variant allow to give the good generalization of the goal. It is useful when the system fails to generalize the goal automatically. If {\ident} has type $(I~\vec{t})$ and $I$ has type $forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), s$, then \term~ must be of type $I:forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), I~\vec{x}\to s'$ where $s'$ is the type of the goal. \item \texttt{dependent inversion } {\ident} \texttt{as} {\intropattern} \texttt{ with } \term \\ \tacindex{dependent inversion \dots\ as \dots\ with} This allows to name the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion } {\ident} \texttt{ with } \term. \item \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear } {\ident} \texttt{ with } \term\\ \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear \dots\ with} Like \texttt{dependent inversion \dots\ with} but clears \ident from the local context. \item \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear } {\ident} \texttt{as} {\intropattern} \texttt{ with } \term\\ \tacindex{dependent inversion\_clear \dots\ as \dots\ with} This allows to name the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear } {\ident} \texttt{ with } \term. \item \texttt{simple inversion} {\ident}\\ \tacindex{simple inversion} It is a very primitive inversion tactic that derives all the necessary equalities but it does not simplify the constraints as \texttt{inversion} do. \item \texttt{simple inversion} {\ident} \texttt{as} {\intropattern}\\ \tacindex{simple inversion \dots\ as} This allows to name the hypotheses introduced in the context by \texttt{simple inversion}. \item \texttt{inversion} \ident \texttt{ using} \ident$'$ \\ \tacindex{inversion \dots\ using} Let {\ident} have type $(I~\vec{t})$ ($I$ an inductive predicate) in the local context, and \ident$'$ be a (dependent) inversion lemma. Then, this tactic refines the current goal with the specified lemma. \item \texttt{inversion} {\ident} \texttt{using} \ident$'$ \texttt{in} \ident$_1$\dots\ \ident$_n$\\ \tacindex{inversion \dots\ using \dots\ in} This tactic behaves as generalizing \ident$_1$\dots\ \ident$_n$, then doing \texttt{inversion}{\ident}\texttt{using} \ident$'$. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso~\ref{inversion-examples} for detailed examples \subsection{\tt Derive Inversion {\ident} with $forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), I~\vec{t}$ Sort \sort} \label{Derive-Inversion} \comindex{Derive Inversion} \index[tactic]{Derive Inversion@{\tt Derive Inversion}} This command generates an inversion principle for the \texttt{inversion \dots\ using} tactic. Let $I$ be an inductive predicate and $\vec{x}$ the variables occurring in $\vec{t}$. This command generates and stocks the inversion lemma for the sort \sort~ corresponding to the instance $forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), I~\vec{t}$ with the name {\ident} in the {\bf global} environment. When applied it is equivalent to have inverted the instance with the tactic {\tt inversion}. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{Derive Inversion\_clear} {\ident} \texttt{with} \comindex{Derive Inversion\_clear} $forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), I~\vec{t}$ \texttt{Sort} \sort~ \\ \index{Derive Inversion\_clear \dots\ with} When applied it is equivalent to having inverted the instance with the tactic \texttt{inversion} replaced by the tactic \texttt{inversion\_clear}. \item \texttt{Derive Dependent Inversion} {\ident} \texttt{with} $forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), I~\vec{t}$ \texttt{Sort} \sort~\\ \comindex{Derive Dependent Inversion} When applied it is equivalent to having inverted the instance with the tactic \texttt{dependent inversion}. \item \texttt{Derive Dependent Inversion\_clear} {\ident} \texttt{with} $forall (\vec{x}:\vec{T}), I~\vec{t}$ \texttt{Sort} \sort~\\ \comindex{Derive Dependent Inversion\_clear} When applied it is equivalent to having inverted the instance with the tactic \texttt{dependent inversion\_clear}. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso \ref{inversion-examples} for examples \subsection{\tt quote \ident}\tacindex{quote} \index{2-level approach} This kind of inversion has nothing to do with the tactic \texttt{inversion} above. This tactic does \texttt{change (\ident\ t)}, where \texttt{t} is a term build in order to ensure the convertibility. In other words, it does inversion of the function \ident. This function must be a fixpoint on a simple recursive datatype: see~\ref{quote-examples} for the full details. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{quote: not a simple fixpoint}\\ Happens when \texttt{quote} is not able to perform inversion properly. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{quote {\ident} [ \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$ ]}\\ All terms that are build only with \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$ will be considered by \texttt{quote} as constants rather than variables. \end{Variants} % En attente d'un moyen de valoriser les fichiers de demos % \SeeAlso file \texttt{theories/DEMOS/DemoQuote.v} in the distribution \section{Automatizing} \label{Automatizing} \subsection{\tt auto} \label{auto}\tacindex{auto} This tactic implements a Prolog-like resolution procedure to solve the current goal. It first tries to solve the goal using the {\tt assumption} tactic, then it reduces the goal to an atomic one using {\tt intros} and introducing the newly generated hypotheses as hints. Then it looks at the list of tactics associated to the head symbol of the goal and tries to apply one of them (starting from the tactics with lower cost). This process is recursively applied to the generated subgoals. By default, \texttt{auto} only uses the hypotheses of the current goal and the hints of the database named {\tt core}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt auto \num}\\ Forces the search depth to be \num. The maximal search depth is 5 by default. \item {\tt auto with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$}\\ Uses the hint databases $\ident_1$ \dots\ $\ident_n$ in addition to the database {\tt core}. See section \ref{Hints-databases} for the list of pre-defined databases and the way to create or extend a database. This option can be combined with the previous one. \item {\tt auto with *}\\ Uses all existing hint databases, minus the special database {\tt v62}. See section \ref{Hints-databases} \item {\tt trivial}\tacindex{trivial}\\ This tactic is a restriction of {\tt auto} that is not recursive and tries only hints which cost is 0. Typically it solves trivial equalities like $X=X$. \item \texttt{trivial with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$}\\ \item \texttt{trivial with *}\\ \end{Variants} \Rem {\tt auto} either solves completely the goal or else leave it intact. \texttt{auto} and \texttt{trivial} never fail. \SeeAlso section \ref{Hints-databases} \subsection{\tt eauto}\tacindex{eauto}\label{eauto} This tactic generalizes {\tt auto}. In contrast with the latter, {\tt eauto} uses unification of the goal against the hints rather than pattern-matching (in other words, it uses {\tt eapply} instead of {\tt apply}). As a consequence, {\tt eauto} can solve such a goal: \begin{coq_example} Hint Resolve ex_intro. Goal forall P:nat -> Prop, P 0 -> exists n, P n. eauto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} Note that {\tt ex\_intro} should be declared as an hint. \SeeAlso section~\ref{Hints-databases} % EXISTE ENCORE ? % % \subsection{\tt Prolog [ \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$ ] \num} % \tacindex{Prolog}\label{Prolog} % This tactic, implemented by Chet Murthy, is based upon the concept of % existential variables of Gilles Dowek, stating that resolution is a % kind of unification. It tries to solve the current goal using the {\tt % Assumption} tactic, the {\tt intro} tactic, and applying hypotheses % of the local context and terms of the given list {\tt [ \term$_1$ % \dots\ \term$_n$\ ]}. It is more powerful than {\tt auto} since it % may apply to any theorem, even those of the form {\tt (x:A)(P x) -> Q} % where {\tt x} does not appear free in {\tt Q}. The maximal search % depth is {\tt \num}. % \begin{ErrMsgs} % \item \errindex{Prolog failed}\\ % The Prolog tactic was not able to prove the subgoal. % \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt tauto} \tacindex{tauto}\label{tauto} This tactic implements a decision procedure for intuitionistic propositional calculus based on the contraction-free sequent calculi LJT* of Roy Dyckhoff \cite{Dyc92}. Note that {\tt tauto} succeeds on any instance of an intuitionistic tautological proposition. {\tt tauto} unfolds negations and logical equivalence but does not unfold any other definition. The following goal can be proved by {\tt tauto} whereas {\tt auto} would fail: \begin{coq_example} Goal forall (x:nat) (P:nat -> Prop), x = 0 \/ P x -> x <> 0 -> P x. intros. tauto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} Moreover, if it has nothing else to do, {\tt tauto} performs introductions. Therefore, the use of {\tt intros} in the previous proof is unnecessary. {\tt tauto} can for instance prove the following: \begin{coq_example} (* auto would fail *) Goal forall (A:Prop) (P:nat -> Prop), A \/ (forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x) -> forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x. tauto. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \Rem In contrast, {\tt tauto} cannot solve the following goal \begin{coq_example*} Goal forall (A:Prop) (P:nat -> Prop), A \/ (forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x) -> forall x:nat, ~ ~ (A \/ P x). \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} because \verb=(forall x:nat, ~ A -> P x)= cannot be treated as atomic and an instantiation of \verb=x= is necessary. \subsection{\tt intuition {\tac}} \tacindex{intuition}\label{intuition} The tactic \texttt{intuition} takes advantage of the search-tree builded by the decision procedure involved in the tactic {\tt tauto}. It uses this information to generate a set of subgoals equivalent to the original one (but simpler than it) and applies the tactic {\tac} to them \cite{Mun94}. If this tactic fails on some goals then {\tt intuition} fails. In fact, {\tt tauto} is simply {\tt intuition fail}. For instance, the tactic {\tt intuition auto} applied to the goal \begin{verbatim} (forall (x:nat), P x)/\B -> (forall (y:nat),P y)/\ P O \/B/\ P O \end{verbatim} internally replaces it by the equivalent one: \begin{verbatim} (forall (x:nat), P x), B |- P O \end{verbatim} and then uses {\tt auto} which completes the proof. Originally due to C{\'e}sar~Mu{\~n}oz, these tactics ({\tt tauto} and {\tt intuition}) have been completely reenginered by David~Delahaye using mainly the tactic language (see chapter~\ref{TacticLanguage}). The code is now quite shorter and a significant increase in performances has been noticed. The general behavior with respect to dependent types, unfolding and introductions has slightly changed to get clearer semantics. This may lead to some incompatibilities. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt intuition}\\ Is equivalent to {\tt intuition auto with *}. \end{Variants} % En attente d'un moyen de valoriser les fichiers de demos %\SeeAlso file \texttt{contrib/Rocq/DEMOS/Demo\_tauto.v} \subsection{{\tt firstorder}\tacindex{firstorder}} \label{firstorder} The tactic \texttt{firstorder} is an {\it experimental} extension of \texttt{tauto} to first-order reasoning, written by Pierre Corbineau. It is not restricted to usual logical connectives but instead may reason about any first-order class inductive definition. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt firstorder {\tac}}\\ \tacindex{\tt firstorder {\tac}} Tries to solve the goal with {\tac} when no logical rule may apply. \item {\tt firstorder with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ }\\ \tacindex{\tt firstorder with} Adds lemmata \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ to the proof-search environment. \item {\tt firstorder using \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ }\\ \tacindex{\tt firstorder using} Adds lemmata in {\tt auto} hints bases \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ to the proof-search environment. \end{Variants} Proof-search is bounded by a depth parameter which can be set by typing the {\nobreak \tt Set Firstorder Depth $n$} \comindex{Set Firstorder Depth} vernacular command. \subsection{{\tt jp} {\em (Jprover)}}\tacindex{jp {\em (Jprover)}} \label{jprover} The tactic \texttt{jp}, due to Huang Guan-Shieng, is an {\it experimental} port of the {\em Jprover}\cite{SLKN01} semi-decision procedure for first-order intuitionistic logic implemented in {\em NuPRL}\cite{Kre02}. Search may optionnaly be bounded by a multiplicity parameter indicating how many (at most) copies of a formula may be used in the proof process, its absence may lead to non-termination of the tactic. %\begin{coq_eval} %Variable S:Set. %Variables P Q:S->Prop. %Variable f:S->S. %\end{coq_eval} %\begin{coq_example*} %Lemma example: (exists x |P x\/Q x)->(exists x |P x)\/(exists x |Q x). %jp. %Qed. %Lemma example2: (forall x ,P x->P (f x))->forall x,P x->P (f(f x)). %jp. %Qed. %\end{coq_example*} \begin{Variants} \item {\tt jp $n$}\\ \tacindex{jp $n$} Tries the {\em Jprover} procedure with multiplicities up to $n$, starting from 1. \item {\tt jp}\\ Tries the {\em Jprover} procedure without multiplicity bound, possibly running forever. \end{Variants} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{multiplicity limit reached}\\ The procedure tried all multiplicities below the limit and failed. Goal might be solved by increasing the multiplicity limit. \item \errindex{formula is not provable}\\ The procedure determined that goal was not provable in intuitionistic first-order logic, no matter how big the multiplicity is. \end{ErrMsgs} % \subsection{\tt Linear}\tacindex{Linear}\label{Linear} % The tactic \texttt{Linear}, due to Jean-Christophe Filli{\^a}atre % \cite{Fil94}, implements a decision procedure for {\em Direct % Predicate Calculus}, that is first-order Gentzen's Sequent Calculus % without contraction rules \cite{KeWe84,BeKe92}. Intuitively, a % first-order goal is provable in Direct Predicate Calculus if it can be % proved using each hypothesis at most once. % Unlike the previous tactics, the \texttt{Linear} tactic does not belong % to the initial state of the system, and it must be loaded explicitly % with the command % \begin{coq_example*} % Require Linear. % \end{coq_example*} % For instance, assuming that \texttt{even} and \texttt{odd} are two % predicates on natural numbers, and \texttt{a} of type \texttt{nat}, the % tactic \texttt{Linear} solves the following goal % \begin{coq_eval} % Variables even,odd : nat -> Prop. % Variable a:nat. % \end{coq_eval} % \begin{coq_example*} % Lemma example : (even a) % -> ((x:nat)((even x)->(odd (S x)))) % -> (EX y | (odd y)). % \end{coq_example*} % You can find examples of the use of \texttt{Linear} in % \texttt{theories/DEMOS/DemoLinear.v}. % \begin{coq_eval} % Abort. % \end{coq_eval} % \begin{Variants} % \item {\tt Linear with \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$}\\ % \tacindex{Linear with} % Is equivalent to apply first {\tt generalize \ident$_1$ \dots % \ident$_n$} (see section \ref{generalize}) then the \texttt{Linear} % tactic. So one can use axioms, lemmas or hypotheses of the local % context with \texttt{Linear} in this way. % \end{Variants} % \begin{ErrMsgs} % \item \errindex{Not provable in Direct Predicate Calculus} % \item \errindex{Found $n$ classical proof(s) but no intuitionistic one}\\ % The decision procedure looks actually for classical proofs of the % goals, and then checks that they are intuitionistic. In that case, % classical proofs have been found, which do not correspond to % intuitionistic ones. % \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt congruence} \tacindex{congruence} \label{congruence} The tactic {\tt congruence}, by Pierre Corbineau, implements the standard Nelson and Oppen congruence closure algorithm, which is a decision procedure for ground equalities with uninterpreted symbols. It also include the constructor theory (see \ref{injection} and \ref{discriminate}). If the goal is a non-quantified equality, {\tt congruence} tries to prove it with non-quantified equalities in the constext. Otherwise it tries to infer a discriminable equality from those in the context. \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Variable A:Set. Variables a b:A. Variable f:A->A. Variable g:A->A->A. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Theorem T: a=(f a) -> (g b (f a))=(f (f a)) -> (g a b)=(f (g b a)) -> (g a b)=a. intros. congruence. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Variable A:Set. Variables a c d:A. Variable f:A->A*A. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Theorem inj : f = pair a -> Some (f c) = Some (f d) -> c=d. intros. congruence. \end{coq_example} \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{I don't know how to handle dependent equality} The decision procedure managed to find a proof of the goal or of a discriminable equality but this proof couldn't be built in Coq because of dependently-typed functions. \item \errindex{I couldn't solve goal} The decision procedure didn't managed to find a proof of the goal or of a discriminable equality. \end{ErrMsgs} \subsection{\tt omega} \tacindex{omega} \label{omega} The tactic \texttt{omega}, due to Pierre Cr{\'e}gut, is an automatic decision procedure for Prestburger arithmetic. It solves quantifier-free formulae build with \verb|~|, \verb|\/|, \verb|/\|, \verb|->| on top of equations and inequations on both the type \texttt{nat} of natural numbers and \texttt{Z} of binary integers. This tactic must be loaded by the command \texttt{Require Import Omega}. See the additional documentation about \texttt{omega} (chapter~\ref{OmegaChapter}). \subsection{\tt ring \term$_1$ \dots\ \term$_n$} \tacindex{ring} \comindex{Add Ring} \comindex{Add Semi Ring} This tactic, written by Samuel Boutin and Patrick Loiseleur, applies associative commutative rewriting on every ring. The tactic must be loaded by \texttt{Require Import Ring}. The ring must be declared in the \texttt{Add Ring} command (see \ref{ring}). The ring of booleans is predefined; if one wants to use the tactic on \texttt{nat} one must first require the module \texttt{ArithRing}; for \texttt{Z}, do \texttt{Require Import ZArithRing}; for \texttt{N}, do \texttt{Require Import NArithRing}. The terms \term$_1$, \dots, \term$_n$ must be subterms of the goal conclusion. The tactic \texttt{ring} normalizes these terms w.r.t. associativity and commutativity and replace them by their normal form. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{ring} When the goal is an equality $t_1=t_2$, it acts like \texttt{ring} $t_1$ $t_2$ and then simplifies or solves the equality. \item \texttt{ring\_nat} is a tactic macro for \texttt{repeat rewrite S\_to\_plus\_one; ring}. The theorem \texttt{S\_to\_plus\_one} is a proof that \texttt{forall (n:nat), S n = plus (S O) n}. \end{Variants} \Example \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. Require Import ZArith. Open Scope Z_scope. \end{coq_eval} \begin{coq_example} Require Import ZArithRing. Goal forall a b c:Z, (a + b + c) * (a + b + c) = a * a + b * b + c * c + 2 * a * b + 2 * a * c + 2 * b * c. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_example} intros; ring. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} You can have a look at the files \texttt{Ring.v}, \texttt{ArithRing.v}, \texttt{ZArithRing.v} to see examples of the \texttt{Add Ring} command. \SeeAlso Chapter~\ref{ring} for more detailed explanations about this tactic. \subsection{\tt field} \tacindex{field} This tactic written by David~Delahaye and Micaela~Mayero solves equalities using commutative field theory. Denominators have to be non equal to zero and, as this is not decidable in general, this tactic may generate side conditions requiring some expressions to be non equal to zero. This tactic must be loaded by {\tt Require Import Field}. Field theories are declared (as for {\tt ring}) with the {\tt Add Field} command. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Require Import Reals. Goal forall x y:R, (x * y > 0)%R -> (x * (1 / x + x / (x + y)))%R = ((- 1 / y) * y * (- x * (x / (x + y)) - 1))%R. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} intros; field. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \subsection{\tt Add Field} \comindex{Add Field} This vernacular command adds a commutative field theory to the database for the tactic {\tt field}. You must provide this theory as follows:\\ {\tt Add Field {\it A} {\it Aplus} {\it Amult} {\it Aone} {\it Azero} {\it Aopp} {\it Aeq} {\it Ainv} {\it Rth} {\it Tinvl}}\\ \noindent where {\tt {\it A}} is a term of type {\tt Type}, {\tt {\it Aplus}} is a term of type {\tt A->A->A}, {\tt {\it Amult}} is a term of type {\tt A->A->A}, {\tt {\it Aone}} is a term of type {\tt A}, {\tt {\it Azero}} is a term of type {\tt A}, {\tt {\it Aopp}} is a term of type {\tt A->A}, {\tt {\it Aeq}} is a term of type {\tt A->bool}, {\tt {\it Ainv}} is a term of type {\tt A->A}, {\tt {\it Rth}} is a term of type {\tt (Ring\_Theory {\it A Aplus Amult Aone Azero Ainv Aeq})}, and {\tt {\it Tinvl}} is a term of type {\tt forall n:{\it A}, {\~{}}(n={\it Azero})->({\it Amult} ({\it Ainv} n) n)={\it Aone}}. To build a ring theory, refer to chapter~\ref{ring} for more details. This command adds also an entry in the ring theory table if this theory is not already declared. So, it is useless to keep, for a given type, the {\tt Add Ring} command if you declare a theory with {\tt Add Field}, except if you plan to use specific features of {\tt ring} (see chapter~\ref{ring}). However, the module {\tt ring} is not loaded by {\tt Add Field} and you have to make a {\tt Require Import Ring} if you want to call the {\tt ring} tactic. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Add Field {\it A} {\it Aplus} {\it Amult} {\it Aone} {\it Azero} {\it Aopp} {\it Aeq} {\it Ainv} {\it Rth} {\it Tinvl}}\\ {\tt \phantom{Add Field }with minus:={\it Aminus}}\\ Adds also the term {\it Aminus} which must be a constant expressed by means of {\it Aopp}. \item {\tt Add Field {\it A} {\it Aplus} {\it Amult} {\it Aone} {\it Azero} {\it Aopp} {\it Aeq} {\it Ainv} {\it Rth} {\it Tinvl}}\\ {\tt \phantom{Add Field }with div:={\it Adiv}}\\ Adds also the term {\it Adiv} which must be a constant expressed by means of {\it Ainv}. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso file {\tt theories/Reals/Rbase.v} for an example of instantiation,\\ \phantom{\SeeAlso}theory {\tt theories/Reals} for many examples of use of {\tt field}. \SeeAlso \cite{DelMay01} for more details regarding the implementation of {\tt field}. \subsection{\tt fourier} \tacindex{fourier} This tactic written by Lo{\"\i}c Pottier solves linear inequations on real numbers using Fourier's method (\cite{Fourier}). This tactic must be loaded by {\tt Require Import Fourier}. \Example \begin{coq_example*} Require Import Reals. Require Import Fourier. Goal forall x y:R, (x < y)%R -> (y + 1 >= x - 1)%R. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} intros; fourier. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Reset Initial. \end{coq_eval} \subsection{\tt autorewrite [ \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$ ]} \tacindex{autorewrite} This tactic \footnote{The behavior of this tactic has much changed compared to the versions available in the previous distributions (V6). This may cause significant changes in your theories to obtain the same result. As a drawback of the reenginering of the code, this tactic has also been completely revised to get a very compact and readable version.} carries out rewritings according the rewriting rule bases {\tt \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$}. Each rewriting rule of a base \ident$_i$ is applied to the main subgoal until it fails. Once all the rules have been processed, if the main subgoal has progressed (e.g., if it is distinct from the initial main goal) then the rules of this base are processed again. If the main subgoal has not progressed then the next base is processed. For the bases, the behavior is exactly similar to the processing of the rewriting rules. The rewriting rule bases are built with the {\tt Hint~Rewrite} vernacular command. \Warning{} This tactic may loop if you build non terminating rewriting systems. \begin{Variant} \item {\tt autorewrite [ \ident$_1$ \dots \ident$_n$ ] using \tac}\\ Performs, in the same way, all the rewritings of the bases {\tt $ident_1$ $...$ $ident_n$} applying {\tt \tac} to the main subgoal after each rewriting step. \end{Variant} \subsection{\tt Hint Rewrite \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ : \ident} \comindex{Hint Rewrite} This vernacular command adds the terms {\tt \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$} (their types must be equalities) in the rewriting base {\tt \ident} with the default orientation (left to right). Notice that the rewriting bases are distinct from the {\tt auto} hint bases and that {\tt auto} does not take them into account. This command is synchronous with the section mechanism (see \ref{Section}): when closing a section, all aliases created by \texttt{Hint Rewrite} in that section are lost. Conversely, when loading a module, all \texttt{Hint Rewrite} declarations at the global level of that module are loaded. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Hint Rewrite -> \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ : \ident}\\ This is strictly equivalent to the command above (we only precise the orientation which is the default one). \item {\tt Hint Rewrite <- \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ : \ident}\\ Adds the rewriting rules {\tt \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$} with a right-to-left orientation in the base {\tt \ident}. \item {\tt Hint Rewrite \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$ using {\tac} : {\ident}}\\ When the rewriting rules {\tt \term$_1$ \dots \term$_n$} in {\tt \ident} will be used, the tactic {\tt \tac} will be applied to the generated subgoals, the main subgoal excluded. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso \ref{autorewrite-example} for examples showing the use of this tactic. % En attente d'un moyen de valoriser les fichiers de demos %\SeeAlso file \texttt{contrib/Rocq/DEMOS/Demo\_AutoRewrite.v} \section{The hints databases for auto and eauto} \index{Hints databases}\label{Hints-databases}\comindex{Hint} The hints for \texttt{auto} and \texttt{eauto} are stored in databases. Each databases maps head symbols to list of hints. One can use the command \texttt{Print Hint \ident} to display the hints associated to the head symbol \ident{} (see \ref{PrintHint}). Each hint has a cost that is an nonnegative integer, and a pattern. The hint is tried by \texttt{auto} if the conclusion of current goal matches its pattern, and after hints with a lower cost. The general command to add a hint to some databases \ident$_1$, \dots, \ident$_n$ is: \comindex{Hint} \begin{quotation} \texttt{Hint} \textsl{hint\_definition} \texttt{:} \ident$_1$ \ldots\ \ident$_n$ \end{quotation} \noindent where {\sl hint\_definition} is one of the following expressions: \begin{itemize} \item \texttt{Resolve} {\term} \index[command]{Hint!Resolve}\\ This command adds {\tt apply {\term}} to the hint list with the head symbol of the type of \term. The cost of that hint is the number of subgoals generated by {\tt apply {\term}}. In case the inferred type of \term\ does not start with a product the tactic added in the hint list is {\tt exact {\term}}. In case this type can be reduced to a type starting with a product, the tactic {\tt apply {\term}} is also stored in the hints list. If the inferred type of \term\ does contain a dependent quantification on a predicate, it is added to the hint list of {\tt eapply} instead of the hint list of {\tt apply}. In this case, a warning is printed since the hint is only used by the tactic {\tt eauto} (see \ref{eauto}). A typical example of hint that is used only by \texttt{eauto} is a transitivity lemma. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Bound head variable} \\ The head symbol of the type of {\term} is a bound variable such that this tactic cannot be associated to a constant. \item \term\ \errindex{cannot be used as a hint} \\ The type of \term\ contains products over variables which do not appear in the conclusion. A typical example is a transitivity axiom. In that case the {\tt apply} tactic fails, and thus is useless. \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{Resolve} {\term$_1$} \dots {\term$_m$} \\ Adds each \texttt{Resolve} {\term$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Immediate {\term}} \index[command]{Hint!Immediate}\\ This command adds {\tt apply {\term}; trivial} to the hint list associated with the head symbol of the type of \ident in the given database. This tactic will fail if all the subgoals generated by {\tt apply {\term}} are not solved immediately by the {\tt trivial} tactic which only tries tactics with cost $0$. This command is useful for theorems such that the symmetry of equality or $n+1=m+1 \to n=m$ that we may like to introduce with a limited use in order to avoid useless proof-search. The cost of this tactic (which never generates subgoals) is always 1, so that it is not used by {\tt trivial} itself. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item \errindex{Bound head variable}\\ \item \term\ \errindex{cannot be used as a hint} \\ \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{Immediate} {\term$_1$} \dots {\term$_m$} \\ Adds each \texttt{Immediate} {\term$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Constructors} {\ident}\index[command]{Hint!Constructors}\\ If {\ident} is an inductive type, this command adds all its constructors as hints of type \texttt{Resolve}. Then, when the conclusion of current goal has the form \texttt{({\ident} \dots)}, \texttt{auto} will try to apply each constructor. \begin{ErrMsgs} \item {\ident} \errindex{is not an inductive type} \item {\ident} \errindex{not declared} \end{ErrMsgs} \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{Constructors} {\ident$_1$} \dots {\ident$_m$} \\ Adds each \texttt{Constructors} {\ident$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Unfold} {\qualid}\index[command]{Hint!unfold}\\ This adds the tactic {\tt unfold {\qualid}} to the hint list that will only be used when the head constant of the goal is \ident. Its cost is 4. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{Unfold} {\ident$_1$} \dots {\ident$_m$} \\ Adds each \texttt{Unfold} {\ident$_i$}. \end{Variants} \item \texttt{Extern \num\ \pattern\ => }\textsl{tactic}\index[command]{Hint!Extern}\\ This hint type is to extend \texttt{auto} with tactics other than \texttt{apply} and \texttt{unfold}. For that, we must specify a cost, a pattern and a tactic to execute. Here is an example: \begin{quotation} \begin{verbatim} Hint Extern 4 ~(?=?) => discriminate. \end{verbatim} \end{quotation} Now, when the head of the goal is a disequality, \texttt{auto} will try \texttt{discriminate} if it does not succeed to solve the goal with hints with a cost less than 4. One can even use some sub-patterns of the pattern in the tactic script. A sub-pattern is a question mark followed by an ident, like \texttt{?X1} or \texttt{?X2}. Here is an example: % Require EqDecide. \begin{coq_example*} Require Import List. \end{coq_example*} \begin{coq_example} Hint Extern 5 ({?X1 = ?X2} + {?X1 <> ?X2}) => generalize X1 X2; decide equality : eqdec. Goal forall a b:list (nat * nat), {a = b} + {a <> b}. info auto with eqdec. \end{coq_example} \begin{coq_eval} Abort. \end{coq_eval} \end{itemize} \Rem There is currently (in the \coqversion\ release) no way to do pattern-matching on hypotheses. \begin{Variants} \item \texttt{Hint} \textsl{hint\_definition} \\ No database name is given : the hint is registered in the {\tt core} database. \item\texttt{Hint Local} \textsl{hint\_definition} \texttt{:} \ident$_1$ \ldots\ \ident$_n$\\ This is used to declare hints that must not be exported to the other modules that require and import the current module. Inside a section, the option {\tt Local} is useless since hints do not survive anyway to the closure of sections. \item\texttt{Hint Local} \textsl{hint\_definition} \\ Idem for the {\tt core} database. \end{Variants} % There are shortcuts that allow to define several goal at once: % \begin{itemize} % \item \comindex{Hints Resolve}\texttt{Hints Resolve \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ : \ident.}\\ % This command is a shortcut for the following ones: % \begin{quotation} % \noindent\texttt{Hint \ident$_1$ : \ident\ := Resolve \ident$_1$}\\ % \dots\\ % \texttt{Hint \ident$_1$ : \ident := Resolve \ident$_1$} % \end{quotation} % Notice that the hint name is the same that the theorem given as % hint. % \item \comindex{Hints Immediate}\texttt{Hints Immediate \ident$_1$ \dots\ \ident$_n$ : \ident.}\\ % \item \comindex{Hints Unfold}\texttt{Hints Unfold \qualid$_1$ \dots\ \qualid$_n$ : \ident.}\\ % \end{itemize} %\begin{Warnings} % \item \texttt{Overriding hint named \dots\ in database \dots} %\end{Warnings} \subsection{Hint databases defined in the \Coq\ standard library} Several hint databases are defined in the \Coq\ standard library. There is no systematic relation between the directories of the library and the databases. \begin{description} \item[\tt core] This special database is automatically used by \texttt{auto}. It contains only basic lemmas about negation, conjunction, and so on from. Most of the hints in this database come from the \texttt{Init} and \texttt{Logic} directories. \item[\tt arith] This database contains all lemmas about Peano's arithmetic proven in the directories \texttt{Init} and \texttt{Arith} \item[\tt zarith] contains lemmas about binary signed integers from the directories \texttt{theories/ZArith} and \texttt{contrib/omega}. It contains also a hint with a high cost that calls {\tt omega}. \item[\tt bool] contains lemmas about booleans, mostly from directory \texttt{theories/Bool}. \item[\tt datatypes] is for lemmas about lists, streams and so on that are mainly proven in the \texttt{Lists} subdirectory. \item[\tt sets] contains lemmas about sets and relations from the directories \texttt{Sets} and \texttt{Relations}. \end{description} There is also a special database called {\tt v62}. It collects all hints that were declared in the versions of {\Coq} prior to version 6.2.4 when the databases {\tt core}, {\tt arith}, and so on were introduced. The purpose of the database {\tt v62} is to ensure compatibility with further versions of Coq for developments done in versions prior to 6.2.4 ({\tt auto} being replaced by {\tt auto with v62}). The database {\tt v62} is intended not to be extended (!). It is not included in the hint databases list used in the {\tt auto with *} tactic. Furthermore, you are advised not to put your own hints in the {\tt core} database, but use one or several databases specific to your development. \subsection{\tt Print Hint} \label{PrintHint} \comindex{Print Hint} \index[tactic]{Hint!\texttt{Print Hint}} This command displays all hints that apply to the current goal. It fails if no proof is being edited, while the two variants can be used at every moment. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Print Hint {\ident} }\\ This command displays only tactics associated with \ident\ in the hints list. This is independent of the goal being edited, to this command will not fail if no goal is being edited. \item {\tt Print Hint *}\\ This command displays all declared hints. \item {\tt Print HintDb {\ident} }\\ \label{PrintHintDb} \comindex{Print HintDb} This command displays all hints from database \ident. \end{Variants} \subsection{Hints and sections} \label{Hint-and-Section} Hints provided by the \texttt{Hint} commands are erased when closing a section. Conversely, all hints of a module \texttt{A} that are not defined inside a section (and not defined with option {\tt Local}) become available when the module {\tt A} is imported (using e.g. \texttt{Require Import A.}). \section{Generation of induction principles with {\tt Scheme}} \label{Scheme} \comindex{Scheme} The {\tt Scheme} command is a high-level tool for generating automatically (possibly mutual) induction principles for given types and sorts. Its syntax follows the schema: \noindent {\tt Scheme {\ident$_1$} := Induction for \ident'$_1$ Sort {\sort$_1$} \\ with\\ \mbox{}\hspace{0.1cm} \dots\ \\ with {\ident$_m$} := Induction for {\ident'$_m$} Sort {\sort$_m$}}\\ \ident'$_1$ \dots\ \ident'$_m$ are different inductive type identifiers belonging to the same package of mutual inductive definitions. This command generates {\ident$_1$}\dots{} {\ident$_m$} to be mutually recursive definitions. Each term {\ident$_i$} proves a general principle of mutual induction for objects in type {\term$_i$}. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Scheme {\ident$_1$} := Minimality for \ident'$_1$ Sort {\sort$_1$} \\ with\\ \mbox{}\hspace{0.1cm} \dots\ \\ with {\ident$_m$} := Minimality for {\ident'$_m$} Sort {\sort$_m$}}\\ Same as before but defines a non-dependent elimination principle more natural in case of inductively defined relations. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso \ref{Scheme-examples} \section{Generation of induction principles with {\tt Functional Scheme}} \label{FunScheme} \comindex{Functional Scheme} The {\tt Functional Scheme} command is a high-level experimental tool for generating automatically induction principles corresponding to (possibly mutually recursive) functions. Its syntax follows the schema:\bigskip \noindent {\tt Functional Scheme {\ident$_i$} := Induction for \ident'$_i$ with \ident'$_1$ \dots\ \ident'$_m$.}\\ \ident'$_1$ \dots\ \ident'$_m$ are the names of mutually recursive functions (they must be in the same order as when they were defined), \ident'$_i$ being one of them. This command generates the induction principle \ident$_i$, following the recursive structure and case analyses of the functions \ident'$_1$ \dots\ \ident'$_m$, and having \ident'$_i$ as entry point. \begin{Variants} \item {\tt Functional Scheme {\ident$_1$} := Induction for \ident'$_1$.}\\ This command is a shortcut for: {\tt Functional Scheme {\ident$_1$} := Induction for \ident'$_1$ with \ident'$_1$.} This variant can be used for non mutually recursive functions only. \end{Variants} \SeeAlso \ref{FunScheme-examples} \section{Simple tactic macros} \index[tactic]{tactic macros} \index{tactic macros} \comindex{Tactic Definition} \label{TacticDefinition} A simple example has more value than a long explanation: \begin{coq_example} Ltac Solve := simpl; intros; auto. Ltac ElimBoolRewrite b H1 H2 := elim b; [ intros; rewrite H1; eauto | intros; rewrite H2; eauto ]. \end{coq_example} The tactics macros are synchronous with the \Coq\ section mechanism: a tactic definition is deleted from the current environment when you close the section (see also \ref{Section}) where it was defined. If you want that a tactic macro defined in a module is usable in the modules that require it, you should put it outside of any section. The chapter~\ref{TacticLanguage} gives examples of more complex user-defined tactics. % $Id$ %%% Local Variables: %%% mode: latex %%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual" %%% TeX-master: "Reference-Manual" %%% End: