aboutsummaryrefslogtreecommitdiffhomepage
diff options
context:
space:
mode:
authorGravatar Maxime Dénès <mail@maximedenes.fr>2017-08-16 09:38:47 +0200
committerGravatar Maxime Dénès <mail@maximedenes.fr>2017-08-16 09:38:47 +0200
commit48e2ccee3614503dfbc18edf5ae8f1f230927d1a (patch)
treed8cf97c693970be8645e3cba7ae0fa621425e5a2
parentfe8aa7ea5af3e23d20c67c2bb791492244620f0c (diff)
parent8f0e4fbc634230d89bb710547bbb50a7f959d74b (diff)
Merge PR #940: Replace jarring use of "Remark" with "Note"
-rw-r--r--doc/tutorial/Tutorial.tex18
1 files changed, 9 insertions, 9 deletions
diff --git a/doc/tutorial/Tutorial.tex b/doc/tutorial/Tutorial.tex
index 8337b1c48..77ce8574f 100644
--- a/doc/tutorial/Tutorial.tex
+++ b/doc/tutorial/Tutorial.tex
@@ -241,7 +241,7 @@ Variables A B C : Prop.
\end{coq_example}
We shall consider simple implications, such as $A\ra B$, read as
-``$A$ implies $B$''. Remark that we overload the arrow symbol, which
+``$A$ implies $B$''. Note that we overload the arrow symbol, which
has been used above as the functionality type constructor, and which
may be used as well as propositional connective:
\begin{coq_example}
@@ -289,7 +289,7 @@ apply H.
We are now in the situation where we have two judgments as conjectures
that remain to be proved. Only the first is listed in full, for the
others the system displays only the corresponding subgoal, without its
-local hypotheses list. Remark that \verb:apply: has kept the local
+local hypotheses list. Note that \verb:apply: has kept the local
hypotheses of its father judgment, which are still available for
the judgments it generated.
@@ -654,7 +654,7 @@ Hypothesis R_transitive :
forall x y z : D, R x y -> R y z -> R x z.
\end{coq_example}
-Remark the syntax \verb+forall x : D,+ which stands for universal quantification
+Note the syntax \verb+forall x : D,+ which stands for universal quantification
$\forall x : D$.
\subsection{Existential quantification}
@@ -664,10 +664,10 @@ We now state our lemma, and enter proof mode.
Lemma refl_if : forall x : D, (exists y, R x y) -> R x x.
\end{coq_example}
-Remark that the hypotheses which are local to the currently opened sections
+The hypotheses that are local to the currently opened sections
are listed as local hypotheses to the current goals.
-The rationale is that these hypotheses are going to be discharged, as we
-shall see, when we shall close the corresponding sections.
+That is because these hypotheses are going to be discharged, as
+we shall see, when we shall close the corresponding sections.
Note the functional syntax for existential quantification. The existential
quantifier is built from the operator \verb:ex:, which expects a
@@ -687,7 +687,7 @@ verifies \verb:P:. Let us see how this works on this simple example.
intros x x_Rlinked.
\end{coq_example}
-Remark that \verb:intros: treats universal quantification in the same way
+Note that \verb:intros: treats universal quantification in the same way
as the premises of implications. Renaming of bound variables occurs
when it is needed; for instance, had we started with \verb:intro y:,
we would have obtained the goal:
@@ -859,7 +859,7 @@ Check weird.
Check drinker.
\end{coq_example}
-Remark how the three theorems are completely generic in the most general
+Note how the three theorems are completely generic in the most general
fashion;
the domain \verb:D: is discharged in all of them, \verb:R: is discharged in
\verb:refl_if: only, \verb:P: is discharged only in \verb:weird: and
@@ -867,7 +867,7 @@ the domain \verb:D: is discharged in all of them, \verb:R: is discharged in
Finally, the excluded middle hypothesis is discharged only in
\verb:drinker:.
-Note that the name \verb:d: has vanished as well from
+Note, too, that the name \verb:d: has vanished from
the statements of \verb:weird: and \verb:drinker:,
since \Coq's pretty-printer replaces
systematically a quantification such as \texttt{forall d : D, E},